Lex Fridman Podcast - #261 – Philip Goff: Consciousness, Panpsychism, and the Philosophy of Mind
Episode Date: February 3, 2022Philip Goff is a philosopher of mind and consciousness at Durham University and author of Galileo's Error. Please support this podcast by checking out our sponsors: - InsideTracker: https://insidetrac...ker.com/lex and use code Lex25 to get 25% off - Grammarly: https://grammarly.com/lex to get 20% off premium - Indeed: https://indeed.com/lex to get $75 credit - Magic Spoon: https://magicspoon.com/lex and use code LEX to get $5 off - BetterHelp: https://betterhelp.com/lex to get 10% off EPISODE LINKS: Philip's Twitter: https://twitter.com/Philip_Goff Philip's Website: http://www.philipgoffphilosophy.com/ Galileo's Error (book): https://amzn.to/3ustY5B Consciousness and Fundamental Reality (book): https://amzn.to/3ojldH1 PODCAST INFO: Podcast website: https://lexfridman.com/podcast Apple Podcasts: https://apple.co/2lwqZIr Spotify: https://spoti.fi/2nEwCF8 RSS: https://lexfridman.com/feed/podcast/ YouTube Full Episodes: https://youtube.com/lexfridman YouTube Clips: https://youtube.com/lexclips SUPPORT & CONNECT: - Check out the sponsors above, it's the best way to support this podcast - Support on Patreon: https://www.patreon.com/lexfridman - Twitter: https://twitter.com/lexfridman - Instagram: https://www.instagram.com/lexfridman - LinkedIn: https://www.linkedin.com/in/lexfridman - Facebook: https://www.facebook.com/lexfridman - Medium: https://medium.com/@lexfridman OUTLINE: Here's the timestamps for the episode. On some podcast players you should be able to click the timestamp to jump to that time. (00:00) - Introduction (07:40) - Conscious matter (41:06) - Death, mystical experiences and collective consciousness (51:30) - The authority of expertise (1:12:27) - Panpsychism and physics (1:41:11) - Suffering, zombies and illusion (2:13:57) - JRE podcast recap (2:25:33) - Free will (2:43:12) - Are we living in a simulation? (2:47:04) - Meaning of life
Transcript
Discussion (0)
The following is a conversation with Philip Goff, philosopher specializing in the philosophy
of mind and consciousness.
He is a pan-psychist, which means he believes that consciousness is a fundamental and ubiquitous
feature of physical reality, of all matter in the universe.
He is the author of Galileo's error, foundations for a new science of consciousness, and is
the host of an excellent podcast called MindChat.
I now a quick few second mention of each sponsor. Check them out in the description. It's the best way to support this podcast.
First is Inside Tracker. A service I use to track my biological data. Second is Grammarly. A service I use to check Spelling, Grammar, and Readability.
Third is indeed a hiring website. Fourth is Magic Spoon, Low-Carb Keto Friendly Serial,
and Fifth is Better Help, an online therapy service.
So the choice is Health, Grammar, or Building an Amazing Team.
Choose wisely, my friends. And now onto the full ad reads.
As always, no ads in the middle.
I try to make these interesting, but if you skip them, please still check out our sponsors.
I enjoy their stuff.
Maybe you will too.
This show is brought to you by Inside Tracker.
A service I use to track biological data.
They have a bunch of plans, most of which include blood tests.
They give you a lot of information that you can then make decisions based on.
They have machine learning algorithms that take that beautiful, sexy, raw data that comes
from you and they use those algorithms to analyze the data.
That includes blood data, DNA data, fitness tracker data, and so on to provide you with a clear picture of what's going on inside you and to offer you signs back
recommendations of positive diet and lifestyle changes.
Andrew Huberman, the great, the powerful Andrew Huberman host of the Huberman Lab podcast that you should definitely listen to
recommends inside tracker, so that's how you know it's legit.
recommends inside tracker. So that's how you know it's legit.
Anyway, this is an idea that I feel like represents the future.
It's obvious you should be making decisions based on data
from your own body, not some population data.
For a limited time, you can get 25% off the entire inside
tracker store if you go to inside tracker.com slash Lex,
that's inside tracker.com slash Lex.
This show is also brought to you by Grammarly, a writing assistant tool that checks spelling,
grammar, set and structure and readability.
Grammarly Premium, the version you pay for, offers a bunch of extra features, my favorite
is the clarity check, which helps detect rambling, over complicated chaos that many of us can
descend into.
Like Finnegan's Wake by James Joyce, funny thing about James Joyce, funny story, that
when he was a young man, like 18 or 19, he said that I'm going to be one of the greatest
writers of the 20th century.
Now that happened to actually end up being the case. But the funny part of that story, whoever
was telling me this story, said that while every person in Ireland at the time were getting
drunk at a bar and saying, I'm going to be the greatest or one of the greatest writers
of the 20th century. So he just happened to be one of them. So that's a necessary precondition
for being great. Just believe you could be great,
but it doesn't, that's not enough just to believe.
Anyway, Grammarly is available on basically any platform.
You can get your point across
with more effectively with Grammarly Premium,
get 20% off Grammarly Premium by signing up
at Grammarly.com slash Lex.
That's 20% off at Grammarly.com slash Lex.
This show is also brought to you by Indeed, a hiring website.
I've used them as part of many hiring efforts I've done, especially for engineering teams
that I've led in the past.
They have tools like Indeed, Insta Match that give you quality candidates whose resumes
and indeed fit your job description immediately.
What can I say about the importance of a great team? We spend so much of our lives working
on difficult challenges together, I quote unquote, work with the team. I think the thing
we don't acknowledge to ourselves is just how fulfilling that is, how important it is
to be surrounded by people that make you
excited to wake up on the day. So if you're hiring, that means this is like the most important
thing you can do, not just for the success of your company, but for your own well-being
and happiness. Anyway, right now I'll get a free $75 sponsored job credit to upgrade your job post at
Indeed.com slash Lex.
I'm talking faster than usual for some reason.
Get it at Indeed.com slash Lex.
Terms and conditions apply.
Go to Indeed.com slash Lex.
This episode is also sponsored by Magic Spoon.
Low, carb, keto, friendly, cereal.
It has zero grams of sugar, 13 to 14 grams of protein,
only 4 net grams of carbs and 140 calories in each serving. You can build your own box or get
a variety pack with available flavors of cocoa, fruity, frosted peanut butter, blueberry,
cinnamon, I think it goes on, but ladies and gentlemen, the best flavor,
the flavor of champions.
My favorite flavor is cocoa.
It reminds me of childhood, it reminds me of happiness.
And by childhood, I mean, not the childhood in Russia.
I guess it would be called late teens in the United States of America when I was cutting insane amounts of weight for wrestling
and that was the first time I fell in love with food is when you deprive yourself of it. Anyway,
Magic Spoon has a 100% happiness guarantee so if you don't like it, they will refund it.
Go to MagicSpoon.com slash Lex use code Lex, a check out to say
five bucks off your order, that's magicspoon.com slash Lex and use code Lex. This episode is also sponsored by BetterHelp spelled H-E-L-P-H-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E-H-E- help it reminds me of Tom Hanks from the movie Castaway where he has the
volleyball named Wilson and it also reminds me that we are alone in this world
we're born alone and we die alone and that loneliness is something we have to
contend with for our entire lives. That's why you should have a professional licensed
therapist to help you in this struggle with our own cells. BetterHelp is a great way to
find one such professional therapist. BetterHelp is easy, private, Affordable, It's Available Worldwide. Check them out at BetterHelp.com slash Lex.
That's BetterHelp.com slash Lex.
So that when you find yourself
undezarded island with a volleyball, you're ready.
This is the Lex Friedman Podcast,
and here is my conversation with Philip Goff.
podcast and here is my conversation with Philip Goff. I opened my second podcast conversation with Elon Musk with a question about consciousness
and pan-psychism.
The question was, quote, does consciousness permeate all matter?
I don't know why I opened the conversation this way.
He looked at me like, what the hell is this guy talking about?
So he said no, because we wouldn't be able to tell if it did or not.
So it's outside the realm of the scientific method.
Do you agree or disagree with Elon Musk's answer?
I disagree, I guess I do think consciousness pervades matter.
In fact, I think consciousness is the ultimate nature
of matter.
So, as for whether it's outside of the scientific method, I think there's a fundamental
challenge at the heart of the science of consciousness that we need to face up to, which is that
consciousness is not publicly observable. I can't look inside your head and see your feelings and experiences. We know
about consciousness not, you know, not from doing experiments or public observation. We
just know about it from our immediate awareness of our feelings and experiences. So qualitative.
Not quantitative, is he talk about? Yeah, that's another aspect of it.
So there are a couple of reasons, consciousness,
I think is not susceptible to the standard
or not fully susceptible to the standard scientific approach.
One reason you've just raised is that it's qualitative
rather than quantitative.
Another reason is it's not publicly observable.
So I mean, science is used to dealing with unobservables,
right?
Fundamental particles, quantum wave functions,
other universes, none of these things are observable,
but there's an important difference.
With all these things, we postulate unobservables
in order to explain what we can observe, right?
In the whole of science, that's how it works.
In the case of consciousness, in the unique case of consciousness, the thing we are trying
to explain is not publicly observable.
And that is utterly unique.
If we want to fully bring science into consciousness,
we need a more expansive conception of the scientific method. So it doesn't mean we can't explain
consciousness scientifically, but we need to rethink what science is. What do you mean publicly?
The word publicly observable, is there something interesting to be said about the word publicly?
It's supposed versus privately. Yeah, it's tricky to define, but I suppose
the data of physics are available to anybody if, you know, if
there were aliens who visited us from another planet, maybe they'd have very
different sense organs, maybe they'd struggle to understand our art or our
music. But if they were intelligent enough to do mathematics,
they could understand our physics.
They could look at the data of our experiments.
They could run the experiments themselves.
Whereas consciousness, is it observable?
Is it not observable?
In a sense, it's observable.
As you say, we could say it's privately observable.
I am directly aware of my own feelings and
experiences. If I'm in pain, it's, it's just right there for me. My pain is just totally
directly evident to me, but you from the outside cannot directly access my pain. You can access
my pain behavior, but, or you can ask me, but you can't access my
pain in the way that I can access my pain. So I think that's a distinction. It might be difficult
to totally pin it down how we define those things, but I think there's a fairly clear and very
important difference though. So you think there's a kind of direct observation that you're able to do of your pain that I'm
not.
So my observation, all the ways in which I can sneak up to observing your pain, is indirect
versus yours is direct.
Can you play devil's advocate?
Is it possible for me to get closer and closer and closer to being able
to observe your pain, like all the subjective experiences, your yours in the way that you
do.
Yeah, I mean, so it's, of course, it's not that we observe behavior and then we make an inference. We are hard wired to instinctively interpret smiles
as happiness, crying as sadness.
And as we get to know someone,
we find it very easy to adopt their perspective,
get into their shoes.
But strictly speaking, all we have perceptual access
to is someone's behavior. But strictly speaking, all we have perceptual access to
is someone's behavior.
And if you were just strictly speaking,
if you were trying to explain someone's behavior
that those aspects that are publicly observable,
I don't think you'd ever have recourse
to attribute consciousness.
You could just postulate some kind of mechanism.
If you were just trying to explain the behavior. So someone like Daniel Dennett is very consistent on this. So
I think for most people, what science is in the business of is explaining the data of
public observation experiment. If you religiously followed that, you would not postulate consciousness
because it's not a datum that's known about in that way. And Daniel Dennett is really
consistent on this. He thinks my consciousness cannot be empirically verified and therefore
it doesn't exist. Dennett is consistent on this. I think I'm consistent on this, but I
think a lot of people have a slightly confused middle-way position on this. I think I'm consistent on this, but I think a lot of people have a slightly confused
middle-way position on this. On the one hand, they think
the business of science is just to account for public observation experiment, but on the other hand,
they also believe in consciousness without appreciating, I think, that
They also believe in consciousness without appreciating, I think, that implies that there is another datum over and above the data of public observation experiments, namely just
the reality of feelings and experiences.
As we walk along this conversation, you keep opening doors that I don't want to walk into
and I will, but I want to try to stay kind of focused, So you mentioned Daniel, then let's lay it out since he sticks to his story
upon unintended and then you stick to yours. What is your story? What is your theory of consciousness versus his? Can you clarify his position?
So my view, I defend the view known as panpsychism, which is the view that
My view, I defend the view known as panpsychism, which is the view that consciousness is a fundamental and ubiquitous feature of the physical world.
So it doesn't literally mean that everything is conscious, despite the meaning of the
word, pan, everything psyche, mind.
So literally, that means everything has mind.
But the typical commitment of the panpsychist is that
the fundamental building blocks of reality
may be fundamental particles, like electrons and quarks,
have incredibly simple forms of experience
and that the very complex experience of the human or animal brain
is somehow rooted in or derived from
this much more simple consciousness at the level of fundamental physics.
So I mean, that's a theory that I would justify on the grounds that it can account for this
datum of consciousness that we are immediately aware of in our experience in a way that I
don't think other theories can.
You asked me to contrast that to Daniel Dennett.
I think he would just say there is no such datum.
Dennett says the datum for science of consciousness is what he calls hetrophonomenology, which is
specifically defined as what we can access from the third person perspective, including what people say,
but crucially, we're not treating what they say. We're not relying on their testimony
as evidence for some unobservable realm of feelings and experiences. We're just treating
there what they say as a datum of public observation experiments that we can account for in terms of underlying mechanisms.
But I feel like there's a deeper view of what consciousness is.
So you have a very clear, and we'll talk quite a bit about pan-psychism.
We have a clear view of what, you know,
almost like a physics view of consciousness.
He, I think, has a kind of view that consciousness is almost the side effect
of this massively parallel computation system going on in our brain. The brain has a model
of the world and it's taking in perceptions and it's constantly weaving multiple stories
about that world that's integrating the new perceptions
and the multiple stories are somehow, it's like a Google Doc collaborative editing.
And that collaborative editing is the actual experience of what we think of as consciousness.
Somehow, the editing is consciousness of this story.
I mean, that's a theory of consciousness,
isn't it the narrative theory of consciousness
or the multiple versions editing,
collaborative editing of a narrative theory of consciousness?
Yeah, he calls it the multiple drafts model.
Incidentally, there's a very interesting paper
just come out by very good philosopher
Luke Rolof's, defending a pan-psychist version of Dennett's multiple drafts model.
It's like a deep returne that that was actually a couple.
Just the difference being that this is Luke Rolof's view, all of the drafts are conscious.
So I guess for Dennett, there, there's no fact of the matter
about which of these drafts is the correct one.
On Rolloff's view, maybe there's no fact of the matter
about which of these drafts is my consciousness,
but nonetheless all the drafts correspond
to some consciousness.
And I mean, I just think it's funny,
I guess I think he calls it Danetti in Pansikers.
But Lucas, one of the most rigorous
and serious philosophers alive at the moment,
I think, and I hate having loot relapse
in an audience if I'm giving a talk
because he always cuts straight to the weakness
in your position that you hadn't thought of.
And so it's nice, you know, Pansikers
and sometimes associated with fluffy thinking, but, you know,
contemporary pancycists have come out of this tradition. We call analytic
philosophy, which is rooted in, you know, detailed, rigorous argumentation
and it is defended it in that manner.
Yeah, those analytic philosophers are stickless for terminology. It's very fun,
very fun group to talk shit with.
Yeah, well, I mean it gets boring if you just start an end defining words, right?
Yeah.
I think starting with defining words is good. Actually, the philosopher Derek Parfitt said when he first was thinking about philosophy,
he went to a talk in analytic philosophy, and he went to a talk in continental philosophy, and he decided that the problem with the continental philosophy,
if it was really unregroised, really unprecise,
the problem with the analytic philosophy
is it was just not about anything important.
And he thought there was more chance of working
within analytic philosophy,
and asking some more meaningful, some more profound questions,
than there was in working continental philosophy and making it more rigorous. Now they're both horrific stereotypes and
you know, I don't want to get nasty emails from either of these groups, but there's something,
there's something to what he was saying though. I think just a tiny tangent on terminology,
I do think that there's a lot of deep insight to be discovered by just asking questions, what do we mean by this
word? I remember I was taking a course on algorithms and data structures in computer science
and the instructor shout out to him Ali Shakafande, amazing professor. I remember he asked some
basic questions like, what is an algorithm? The pressure of pushing students to answer to think deeply.
You just woke up hungover in college or whatever and you're tasked with answering some
deep philosophical question about what is an algorithm.
These basic questions, and they sound very simple, but they're actually very difficult.
And one of the things I really value in conversation is asking these dumb simple questions of like,
what is
intelligence? And just continually asking that question over and over of some of the sort
of biggest research in the researchers in the artificial intelligence computer science
space, it's actually very useful. At the same time, you know, it should start a terminology
and then progress where you kind of say, ah, fuck it. Well, just, we'll just assume we know what we mean by that.
Otherwise, you get the built Clinton situation where it's like,
what is the meaning of is or is whatever he said?
It's like, Hey, man, did you do the sex stuff or not?
Yeah. And so there's, you have to both be able to talk about the sex stuff and the meaning of the word is
With consciousness because we don't currently understand, you know very much
terminology discussions are very important because it's like you're almost trying to sneak
Sneak up to some deep insight by just discussing the basic terminology.
You know, like what is consciousness or even defining the different aspects of
panpsychism is fascinating. But just to linger on the Daniel Dene thing, what do
you think about narrative? Sort mind constructing narratives far south-south.
There's nothing special about consciousness deeply.
It is some property of the human mind that is just able to tell these pretty stories that
we experience as consciousness.
It's unique perhaps to the human mind, which
is I suppose what Daniel then would argue that it's either deeply unique or mostly unique
to the human mind.
It's just on the question of terminology before.
I think it used to be a fashion among philosophers that we had to come up with utterly precise, necessary
and sufficient conditions for each word. And then I think this has gone out of fashion
a bit partly because it's just been, you know, such a failure. The word knowledge in particular,
people used to define knowledge as true justified belief. And then this guy Getty A had this
very short paper
where he just produced some pretty conclusive counter examples to that. I think,
you know, he wrote very few papers, but this is just, you know, you have to teach
this on an undergraduate philosophy course. And then after that, you had a huge
literature of people trying to address this and propose a new definition, but then
someone else would come out with counter examples, and then you get a new definition of knowledge,
and counter examples, and it just went on and on,
and never seemed to get anywhere.
So I think the thought now is,
let's work out how precise we need to be
for what we're trying to do,
and I think that's a healthy attitude.
So precision is important, but you just need to work out
how precise do we need to be for these purposes?
Come into the den, and narrative theories.
I mean, I think...
I think narrative theories are...
...a plausible contender for a theory of the self.
Theory of my identity over time, what makes me...
...the same person, in some sense, sense today as I was 20 years ago,
weren't given that I've changed so much physically and psychologically.
One running contender is something connected to the kind of stories we tell about ourselves,
or maybe some story about the psychological, the chains of psychological continuity.
I'm not saying I accept such a theory, but it's plausible.
I don't think these theories are good as theories of consciousness.
At least if we're taking consciousness just to be subjective experience, pleasure, pain,
seeing colour, hearing sound.
I think, you know, a hamster has consciousness in that sense. There's something that it's
like to be a hamster. It feels pain if you stand on it, if you're cruel enough to do, I don't
know why I gave that.
Stan.
People always give, I don't know, philosophers give these very violent examples to get the
cross-consciousness. And it's, yeah, I don't know why that's coming about.
But anyway.
Same mean things to the hamster. Let's back.
Let's back.
So it experiences pain.
It expresses pleasure, joy.
I mean, but there's some limits to that experience of a hamster,
but there is nevertheless the presence of a subjective experience.
Yeah, consciousness is just something,
I mean, because it's a very ambiguous word,
but if we're just using it to mean some kind of experience,
some kind of inner life, that is pretty widespread in the animal kingdom.
It's a bit difficult to say where it stops where it starts, but you certainly don't need
something as sophisticated as the capacity to self-consciously tell stories about yourself
to be, to just have experience.
Except for cats who are evil automatons that are void of consciousness, they're the fingertips
of the devil.
Oh, absolutely.
I was taking that as red.
I mean, deck heart, so animals were mechanisms.
And humans are unique.
So animals are robots, essentially, in the formulation of the cart and humans are unique. Yeah.
So in which way would you say humans are unique versus even our closest ancestors?
Is there something special about humans?
What is in your view under the panpsychism, I guess we're walking backwards because we'll
have the big picture conversation about what is panpsychism, I guess we're walking backwards because we'll have the big picture conversation
about what is panpsychism, but given your kind of broad theory of consciousness, what's unique
about humans do you think? As a panpsychist, there is a great continuity between humans and the rest
of the universe. There's nothing that special about human consciousness. It's just a highly
evolved form of what exists throughout the universe. So we're very much continuous with
the rest of the physical universe. What is unique about human beings? I suppose the
capacity to reflect on our conscious experience, plan for the future.
The capacity, I would say, to respond to reasons as well.
I mean, animals in some sense have motivations,
but when a human being makes a decision,
they're responding to what philosophy is called
normative considerations.
You know, if you're trying to take this job in the US, you weigh it up, you say,
well, you know, I'll get more money.
I'll have maybe a better quality of life, but if I stay in the UK, I'll be closer to family
and you weigh up these considerations.
I'm not sure any non-human animals quite respond to considerations of value in that way.
I mean, I might be reflecting here that I'm something of an objectivist about value.
I think there are objective facts about what we have reason to do and what we have reason to believe.
And humans have access to those facts.
And humans have access to them and can respond to them.
That's a controversial claim, you know. Many of my punts, I guess, brethren might not
have. They would say the hamster too can look up to the stars and ponder theoretical
physics. Maybe not, but I think it depends what you think about value. If you have a more
humane picture of value by which I mean relating to the philosopher David Hume who said,
reason is the slave of the passions. Really, we just have motivations.
And what we have reason to do arises from our motivations.
I'm not a humane. I think there are objective facts about what we have a reason to do.
And I think we have access to them. I don't think any non-human animal has access to
objective facts about what they have reason to do, what they have reason to believe. They don't
weigh up evidence. The reason is a sleeve of the passions. That was David Hume's view, yeah. I mean,
yeah, do you want to know my problem with Hume's? I had a radical conversion. This might not be
connected. There's not connected to pansegans, but I had a radical conversion. This might not be connected, there's not connected to puns like this, but I had a radical
conversion.
I used to have a more humian view when I was a graduate student, but I was persuaded by
some professors at the University of Reading where I was.
If you have the humian view, you have to say any basic life goals are equally valid. So for example, let's take
someone who's basic goal in life is counting blades of grass, right? And crucially, they
don't enjoy it, right? This is the crucial, but they get no pleasure from it. That's just
their basic goal to spend their life counting as many blades of grass
as possible.
Not for some greater goal, that's just their basic goal.
I wanna say that is objectively stupid.
That is objectively pointless.
I shouldn't say stupid,
but it's objectively pointless
in a way that pursuing pleasure,
or pursuing someone else's pleasure, or pursuing scientific
inquiry is not pointless. As soon as you make that admission, you're not a follower of
David Hugh anymore. You think there are objective facts about what goals are worth pursuing.
Is it possible to have a goal without pleasure? So this kind of idea that you disjoint the two.
So the David Foster Wallace idea of, you know,
the key to life is to be unborrable.
Isn't it possible to discover the pleasure
in everything in life?
The counting of the blades of grass.
Once you see the mastery, the skill of it,
you can discover the pleasure.
Therefore, I guess when I'm asking you, why and when and how did you lose the romance
in grad school?
Is that what you're trying to say?
I think it may or may not be true that it's possible to find pleasure in everything,
but I think it's also true that people don't act
solely for pleasure and they certainly don't act solely for their own pleasure. People will
suffer for things they think are worthwhile. I might, you know, I might suffer for some scientific
cause for finding out a cure for the pandemic or, and in terms of my own pleasure,
I might have less pleasure in doing that,
but I think it's worthwhile.
It's a worthwhile thing to do.
I just don't think it's the case that
everything we do is rooted in maximizing our own pleasure.
I don't think that's even psychologically plausible.
Well, pleasure then, that's a narrow view of pleasure. That's like a short-term pleasure. I don't think that's even psychologically plausible. But pleasure then that's a narrow kind of view of play. That's like a short-term pleasure.
We can see pleasure is a kind of ability to hear the music in the distance. It's like,
yes, it's difficult now, it's suffering now, but there is some greater thing beyond the mountain, that will be joy. I mean, that's kind of a, even if it's not in this life,
well, you know, the warriors will meet in Valhalla, right? The feeling that gives meaning and
fulfillment to life is not necessarily grounded in pleasure of like the counting of the grass.
It's something else. I don't know. The struggle is a source of deep fulfillment.
So, I think pleasure needs to be kind of thought of as a little bit more broadly. It just kind of
gives you this sense. It, for a moment, allows you to forget the terror of the fact that you're going to die
That that that's pleasure like that's the broader view of pleasure that you get to kind of
play
In the little illusion that's all of this has deep meaning
That's pleasure. Yeah, well
But I mean, you know, people sacrifice their lives.
Atheists may sacrifice their lives for the sake of someone else or for the sake of something
important enough and clearly in that case they're not doing it for the sake of their own pleasure.
That's a rather dramatic example, but there can be just trivial examples where,
the dramatic example, but there can be just trivial examples where, you know, I choose to be honest rather than lie about something, can I lose out a bit? And I have a bit less
pleasure, but I thought it was worth doing the honest thing or something. I mean, I just
think so that's a, I mean, maybe you can use the word pleasure so broadly that you're
just essentially meaning something worthwhile, But then I think the word
pleasure maybe maybe loses its meaning. Sure. Wow. But what do you think about the blades of
brusques? What do you think about someone who spends their life counting blades of brusques?
And doesn't enjoy it. So I think I personally think it's impossible or maybe I'm not understanding
even like the philosophical formulation, but I think it's
impossible to have a goal and not draw pleasure from it.
Make it worthwhile, forget the word pleasure.
I think the word goal loses meaning.
If I say I'm going to count the number of pens on this table, if I'm actively involved
in the task, I will find joy in it.
I will find joy in it. I will find that like I think there's a lot of meaning and joy
to be discovered in the in the skill of a task in mastering of a skill and taking pride in
doing it well. I mean that's I don't know what it is about the human mind, but there's there's some
joy to be discovered in the mastery of a skill. So I think it's just impossible to count blades of grass and not have the georgians of sushi
like draws you into the mastery of the simple task.
Yeah, I suppose, I mean, in a way you might think it's just hard to imagine someone who
would spend their lives doing that, but then maybe that's just because it's so evident
that that is a pointless task. Whereas if we take this David Hume, you seriously, it ought
to be, you know, a totally possible life goal. Whereas I mean, I,
yeah, I guess I just find it hard to shake the idea that some ways of, some life goals
are more worthwhile than others. And it doesn't mean, you know, that there's one single
way you should lead your life, but pursuing knowledge, helping people, pursuing your own pleasure to an extent are
a worthwhile things to do in a way that, you know, for example, I have, I'm a little bit
OCD, I still feel inclined to walk on cracks in the pavement or do it symmetrically like
if I step on a crack with my left foot, I feel the need to do it my right foot.
And I think that's kind of pointless. Step on a crack with my left foot. I feel the need to do it my right foot and I
Think that's kind of pointless. It's something I feel the urge to do, but it's pointless whereas other things I choose to do
I think there's it's worth doing and
It's hard to make sense of metaphysically what could possibly ground that how could we know about these facts, but
That's the starting point for me. I don't know.
I think you walking on the sidewalk in a way that's symmetrical brings order to the world.
If you weren't doing that, the world might fall apart.
And it feels like that.
I think there's a there's a meaning in that. Like you embracing the full experience of that,
you living the richness of that
as if it has meaning, we'll give meaning to it.
And then whatever genius comes of that
as you as a one little intelligent aunt
will make a better life for everybody else.
Perhaps I'm defending the blades of grass example
because I can literally imagine myself
enjoying this task as somebody who's
OCD in a certain kind of way in quantitative.
But now you're ruining these up
because you imagine someone enjoying it.
I imagine someone who doesn't enjoy it.
We don't want a life that's just full of pleasure.
Like we just sit there, you know,
having a big sugar high all the time.
We want a life where we do things that are worthwhile.
If for something to be worthwhile just is for it to be a basic life goal, then that mode
of reflection doesn't really make sense.
We can't really think, did I do things worthwhile?
On the David Hume type picture, all it is for something
to be worthwhile is it was a basic goal of yours or derived from a basic goal.
Yeah. Yeah, I mean, I think goal and worthwhile aren't. I think goal is a boring word. A more
sort of existentialist like, did you ride the rollercoaster of life? Did you fully experience life? That, and in that sense, I mean, the blaze of grass
is something that could be deeply joyful.
And that's in that way, I think suffering
could be joyful in the full context of life.
It's the rollercoaster of life.
Like without suffering, without struggle,
without pain, without depression, or sadness,
there's not the highs.
I mean, that's the, that's a
fucked up thing about life is that the lows really make the highs that much richer and
deeper and like taste better, right? Like, the, like, I was at, I tweeted this, I was, I couldn't sleep and I was late at night.
I know it's an obvious statement, but every love story
eventually ends in loss in tragedy. So like this feeling of love at the end, there's always going to be tragedy.
Even if it's the most amazing life-long love with another human being, one of you is going
to die. And I don't know which is worse, but both are not going to be pretty. And so that the sense that it's finite,
the sense that it's going to end in a low,
that gives richness to those kind of evenings
when you realize this fucking thing ends,
this thing ends, the feeling that it ends,
that bad taste, that bad feeling that it ends, that bad taste, that bad feeling that it ends, gives meaning,
gives joy, gives pleasure, this loaded word, but gives some kind of deep pleasure to
the experience when it's good.
I mean, and that's the blades of grass, You know, they have that to me.
But you're perhaps right that it's like reducing it to certain goals or something like that
is kind of removing the magic of life.
Because I think what makes counting the blades of grass it's just because it's life.
Okay, so it sounds like you, it sounds like you reject the, the David Hume type picture anyway, because you're saying just because you have it as a
goal. That's what it is to be worthwhile, but you're saying, no, it's because it's
engaging the life, riding the roller coaster. So that does sound like in some
sense, there are facts independent of our personal goal choices about what it means to live a good life
And I mean coming back full circle to the start of this was what makes us different animals
I don't think at the end of a hamster's life. It's it thinks did I ride the roller coaster?
Did I really live life to the full that is not a mode of reflection that's
Available to non-human animals.
So what do you think is the role of death in all of this, the fear of death? Does that interplay
with consciousness, does this self-reflection? Do you think there's some deep connection between this ability to contemplate the fact that
the are flame of consciousness eventually goes out.
Yeah, I don't think unfortunately panpsychism helps particularly with life after death, because
you know, for the panpsychistist there's nothing supernatural, there's nothing
beyond the physical, all there is really is ultimately particles and fields, it's just that we think
the ultimate nature of particles and fields is consciousness, but I guess when the matter in my brain
When the matter in my brain ceases to be ordered in a way that sustains the particular kind of consciousness I enjoy in waking life, then in some sense I will cease to be.
Although I do, the final chapter of my book, Galileo's Era, is more experimental.
So the first four chapters are the cold-blooded case
for the pan-psychist view,
is that the best solution to the hard problem
of consciousness, the last chapter,
we talk about meaning.
Yeah, I talk about meaning,
I talk about free will,
and I talk about mystical experiences.
So I always want to emphasize that pan-psychism
is not necessarily connected to anything spiritual.
A lot of people defending this view,
like David Sharma's or Luke Rolof's,
are just total atheists secularists, right?
They don't believe in any kind of transcendent reality.
They just believe in feelings, mundane consciousness,
and think that needs explaining
in our conventional scientific approach, can't cut it. But if for independent reasons you are motivated to some spiritual picture of reality,
then maybe a puntsyke's view is more consonant with that. So if you have a mystical experience where
You have a mystical experience where you, it seems to you in this experience that there is this higher form of consciousness at the root of all things.
If you're a materialist, you've got to think that's a delusion.
You know, there's just something in your brain making you think that it's not real.
But if you're a pan-psychist and you already think the fundamental nature of reality is constituted of consciousness,
it's not that much of a leap to think that
this higher form of consciousness
you seem to apprehend in the mystical experience
is part of that underlying reality.
And in many different cultures,
experience, meditators have claimed to have experiences in which it becomes apparent
to them that there is an element of consciousness that is universal. So this is sometimes called
universal consciousness. So on this view, your mind and my mind are not totally distinct.
Each of our individual conscious minds is built
upon the foundations of universal consciousness and universal consciousness as it exists in me is
one and the same thing as universal consciousness as it exists in you.
So, I've never had one of these experiences, but if one is a pan- upon psychist, I think one is more open to that possibility,
I don't see why it shouldn't be the case that that is part of the nature of consciousness and maybe
something that is apparent in certain deep states of meditation. And so what I explore in the
experimental final chapter of my book is that could allow for a kind of impersonal life after death
because if that view is true then even when the particular aspects of my
conscious experience fall away, that element of universal consciousness at the
core of my identity would continue to exist. So it sort of be as it were, absorbed into universal consciousness.
So, I mean Buddhists and Hindu mystics
try to meditate to get rid of all the bad karma
to be absorbed into universal consciousness.
It could be that if there's no karma,
if there's no reverb,
maybe everyone gets enlightened when they die.
Maybe you just sink back into universal consciousness.
I also, coming back to morality, suggest this could provide some kind of basis for
altruism or non-egotism because if you think
egotism implicitly assumes that we are utterly distinct individuals.
Whereas on this view, we're not, we overlap to an extent that something at the core of our being is.
Even in this life, we overlap.
That would be this view that some experienced meditators claim becomes apparent to them.
That there is something at the core of my identity that is one and the same as
the thing at the core of your identity, this universal consciousness.
Yeah, there is something very like you and I in this conversation, there's a few people
listening to this, all of us are in a kind of single mind together.
There's some small aspect of that
and or maybe a big aspect about us humans.
So certainly in a space of ideas,
we kind of meld together for time, at least,
in a conversation and kind of play with that idea.
And then we're clearly all thinking,
like if I say pink elephant,
there's going to be a few people
that are now visualizing at pink elephant.
We're all thinking about that pink elephant together.
We're all in the room together
thinking about this pink elephant.
And we're like rotating it,
like, you know, in our minds together.
What is that?
That pink elephant, is there a different instantiation of that pink
elephant in everybody's mind? Or is it the same elephant? And we have the same mind exploring
that elephant. Now if we are in our mind, start petting that elephant, like touching it,
that experience that we're now like thinking what that would feel like,
it was that, is that all of us experiencing that together or is that separate? So like there's some aspect of the togetherness that almost seems fundamental to civilization to society.
Hopefully that's not too strong, but to like some of the
fundamental properties of the human mind. It feels like the social aspect is really important.
We call it social because we think of us as individual minds interacting, but if we're
just like one collective mind with like fingertips, they're like touching each other as it's trying
to explore the elephant. But that could be just in the realm of ideas and intelligence and not in
the realm of consciousness. And it's interesting to see maybe it is in the realm of consciousness. Yeah, so it's obviously certainly true in some sense that there are these phenomena that you're
talking about of collective consciousness in some sense. I suppose the question is how
ontologically serious do we want to be about those things? By which I mean,
are they just a construction of out of our minds and the
fact that we interact in the standard, standardly scientifically accepted ways, or is as someone
like Rupert Sheldrake would think that there is some metaphysical reality. There are some
fields beyond the scientifically understood ones that are somehow communicating this.
I mean, I think that, I mean, the view I was describing was that this element we're supposed
to have in common is, is some sort of pure impersonal consciousness or something rather
than.
So actually, I mean, an interesting figure is the Australian philosopher, Miriel Bahari,
who defends a kind of mystical conception of reality rooted in a, a bit of a danta
mysticism.
But like me, she's from this tradition of analytic philosophy,
and so she defends this in this incredibly precise, rigorous way.
She defends the idea that we should think of experience, meditators, as
providing expert testimony.
So, I think humans cause a causing climate breakdown.
I have no idea of the science behind it, you know, but I trust the experts, or you know,
that the universe is 14 billion years old.
You know, most of our knowledge is based on expert testimony, and she thinks we should
think of experience meditated.
These people who are telling us about this universal consciousness of the core of our
being as a relevant kind of expert. And so she wants to defend, you know, the rational
acceptability of this misty or conceptual reality. So it's what, you know, I think we shouldn't
be ashamed, you know, we shouldn't be worried about dealing with certain views as long as
it's done with rigor and seriousness. You know, I think sometimes terms like, I don't know, new age or something,
can function a bit like racist terms.
You know, a racist term picks out a group of people,
but then implies certain negative characteristics.
So people use this term, you know, to pick out a certain set of views,
like mystical conception of reality and,
and imply it's kind of fluffy thinking or but you know you read
Miri Albahari you read Luke Rolof's this is serious rigorous thought whether you agree with
her or not obviously it's hugely controversial and so you know the enlightenment ideal
is to follow the evidence and the arguments where they lead
but it's kind of very hard for human beings to do that. I think we get stuck in some
conception of how we think science ought to look. And, you know, people talk about religion
as a crutch, but I think a certain kind of scientist, a certain conception of how science
is supposed to be gets into people's identity and the sense of themselves and the
security.
And make things hard if you're a punse like it's.
And even the word expert becomes a kind of crutch.
I mean, use the word expert.
You have some kind of conception of what expertise means.
Oftentimes that's connected with a degree of particular prestigious
university or something like that, or expertise is a funny one.
I've noticed that anybody sort of that claims they're an expert is usually not the expert.
The biggest quote unquote expert that I've ever met are the ones that are truly humble. So the humility is a really good sign of somebody who's traveled the long road and been humbled
by how little they know.
So some of the best people in the world at whatever the thing they've spent their life
doing are the ones that are ultimately humble in the face of it all.
So like just being humble, how little we know even if we travel lifetime. I do like the idea. I mean treating sort of like what is it psycho knots
like an expert witness
You know people who have traveled
with the help of DMT to another place where they
Got some deep understanding of something. And their insight is perhaps
as valuable as the insight of somebody who ran rigorous psychological studies at Princeton
University or something. Like those psychonauts, they have wisdom, if it's done rigorously,
which you can also do rigorously within the university, within the studies now, with the sociogun and those kinds of things.
Yeah, that's a fantastic thing.
Still probably the best,
one of the best works on mystical experience
is the chapter in William James's varieties
of religious experiences.
And most of it is just a psychological study
of trying to define the characteristics
of mystical experience as a psychological type. But at the end he considers the
question, if you have a mystical experience, is it rational to trust it, to trust
that it's telling you something about reality? And he makes an interesting
argument. He says, if you say no, you're kind of applying a double standard
because we all think it's okay to trust our
normal sensory experiences, but we have no way of getting outside of ourselves to prove
that our sensory experience is correspond to an external reality.
We could be in the matrix, this could be a very vivid dream, you know, you could say, oh, we do science, but a scientist only gets their
data by experiencing the results of their experiments and then the question arises
again. How do you know that corresponds to a real world? So he thinks there's a
sort of double standard in saying it's okay to trust our ordinary sensory
experiences, but it's not okay for the person on DMT to trust those experiences.
It's very philosophically difficult to say,
why is it okay in the one case and not the other?
So I think there's an interesting argument there,
but I would like to just defend experts a little bit.
I mean, I agree it's very difficult,
but especially in an age, I guess, with so much information,
I do think it's important to have some
protection of sources of information, academic institutions that we can trust. And then that's
difficult because, of course, there are non-academics who do know what they're talking about, but
I get fine, interested in knowing about biology. You biology, you can't research everything.
So I think we have to have some sense of who are the experts, we can trust.
The people who've spent a lot of time reading all the material that people have read, written,
thinking about it, having their views torn apart by other people working in the field. I think that is very important.
And also to protect that from conflicts of interest. There is a so-called think tank in the UK called
the Institute of Economic Affairs, who are always on the BBC as experts on economic questions,
and they do not declare who funds them, right? So we don't know who's paying the paper. I think, you know,
you shouldn't be allowed to call yourself a think tank if you're not totally transparent
about who's funding you. So I think that's it. And I mean, this connects to pan-psychism
because I think the reason people, you know, worry about unorthodox ideas is because
they worry about how do we know when we're just losing control or losing discipline. So I do think we need to somehow protect academic institutions
as sources of information that we can trust. And you know, in philosophy, there's, you
know, there's not much consensus on everything, but you can at least know what people who have put the time in to read all the stuff.
What they think about these issues,
I think that is important.
Pushback and you pushback.
Who are the experts on COVID?
Oh, again, it's a dangerous territory now.
Well, let me just speak to it
because I am walking through that dangerous territory.
I'm allergic to the word expert
because in my simple mind it kind of rhymes with ego. There's something about experts. If we
allow too much to have a category expert and place certain
people in them, those people sitting on the throne start to believe it. And they start
to communicate with that energy. And the humility starts to dissipate. I think there is value in a lifelong mastery of a skill and the pursuit of knowledge within
a very specific discipline.
But the moment you have your name on an office, the moment you're an expert, I think you
destroy the very aspect, the very value of that journey towards knowledge so some of it probably just reduces to like skillful communication like of
Communicating the way that shows humility that shows an open mind in this that shows an ability to really hear what a lot of people are saying
So in the case of COVID, what I've noticed,
and this is true, this is probably true with panpsychism as well, is so-called experts,
and they are extremely knowledgeable, many of them are colleagues of mine, they dismiss
what millions of people are saying on the internet without having looked into it, with empathy
and rigor, honestly, understand what are the arguments being made. They say like there's not enough
time to explore all those things like there's so much stuff out there. Yeah, I think that's intellectual
laziness. If you don't have enough time, then don't speak so strongly with dismissal. Feel bad about it. Be apologetic about the fact that you
don't have enough time to explore the evidence. For example, what the heat I got
with Francis Collins is that he kind of said that Lab League, he kind of
dismissed it. Showing that he didn't really deeply explore all the
sort of the huge amount of circumstantial evidence out there, the battles that are going
out out there. There's a lot of people really tense the disgust in this. And being showing
humility in the face of that battle of ideas, I think is really important. And I just been very disappointed in so-called expertise in the space of science,
and showing humility, and showing humanity and kindness and empathy towards other human beings.
That's at the same time, obviously, I love Jura Dreams of Sushi,
life-long pursuit of getting like getting like in computer science,
Don Kanuth.
Like some of my biggest heroes are people that like when nobody else cares, they stay on
one topic for their whole life and they just find the beautiful little things about their
puzzles that keep solving.
And yes, sometimes a virus happens or something happens with that person with their puzzles
becomes like the center of the whole world because that puzzle becomes all of a sudden really important.
But still there's possibilities on them to show humility and to be open-minded to the fact
that they, even if they spent their whole life doing it, even if their whole community is telling them, giving them awards and giving them citations and giving them
all kinds of stuff, where they're bowing down before them how smart they are, they still know
nothing relative to all the stuff, the mysteries that are out there.
Yeah, I wonder how much we're disagreeing. I mean, these are totally valid issues.
And of course, expertise goes wrong in all sorts of ways.
It's totally fallible.
I suppose I would just say, what is the alternative?
What do we just say?
All information is equal.
Because as a voter, I've got to decide who to vote for, and that I've got to evaluate,
and I can't look into all of the economics and all of the relevant science.
And so, I just think, maybe it's like Churchill said about democracy, it's the worst system
of government apart from all the rest. I think about Panpsychism, too, actually, it's the worst system of government apart from all the rest.
I think about Panpsikism to actually, it's the worst theory of consciousness apart from all the rest. But, you know, I just think expertise, the peer review system, I think it's terrible in so many ways.
Yes, people should show more humility, but I can't see a viable alternative. I think the philosopher Bernan Williams had a really nice
nuanced discussion of the problems of titles, but how they also function in a society
they do have some positive function. The very first time I lectured in philosophy
before I got a professor's ship
was teaching at a continuing education college.
That's kind of kind of for retired people who want to, um, learn some more things.
And I just totally pitched it too high and gate talked about burnard Williams on,
on titles and hierarchies.
And these kind of people in their 70s and 80s,
who just instantly started interrupting saying,
what is philosophy?
And it was a disaster.
And I just remember in the break,
a sort of elderly lady came up and said,
I've decided to take Egyptology instead.
But that was my introduction to teaching.
Anyway, but sort of titles and accomplishments is a nice is a nice starting point
But doesn't buy you the whole thing so you don't get to just say this is true because because I'm an expert
You still have to convince people what one of the things I really like to practice martial arts. Yeah, and
For people who don't know it's Brazilian j Jiu-Jitsu is one of them.
And you sometimes wear these pajamas,
pajama-looking things, and you wear a belt.
So I happen to be a black belt
and Brazilian Jiu-Jitsu.
And I also train in what's called no-gui,
so you don't wear the pajamas.
And when you don't wear the pajamas,
nobody knows what rank you are. Nobody knows if you're black
bolt or white belt, if you're a complete beginner or not. And when you wear the pajamas called the
ghee, you wear the rank. And people treat you very differently. When they see my black bolt,
they treat me differently. They kind of defer to my expertise. If they're kicking my ass, that's
probably because I am working on something new or maybe I'm letting them win. But when
there's no belts, and it doesn't matter if I've been doing this for 15 years, it doesn't
matter. None of it matters. What matters is the raw interaction of just trying to kick
each other's ass and seeing like, what is this chest game?
Like a human chest.
Who?
What are the ideas that we're playing with?
And I think there's a dance there.
Yes, it's valuable to know a person as a black boat when you take consideration of
the advice of different people, me versus somebody who's only practiced for like a couple of days.
But at the same time, the raw practice of ideas that is combat and the raw practice of exchange
of ideas that is science needs to often throw away expertise. And in communicating, like, there's
another thing to science and expertise, which is leadership. It's not just, so the
scientific method in the review process is this rigorous battle of ideas between
scientists, but there's also a stepping up and inspiring the world and
communicating ideas to the world.
And that skill of communication, I suppose that's my biggest criticism of so-called experts
in science.
Is there just shitty communicators?
Absolutely.
Yeah.
Well, I can tell you, I get very frustrated with philosophers not reaching out more.
I mean, I think it might be partly that we're trained
to get watertight arguments, you know, respond to all objections. And as you do that,
eventually it gets more complicated and the jargon comes in. But then if, so to write a more
accessible book or article, you have to loosen the argument a bit. And then we worry
that other philosophers will think, oh, that's a really crap argument. So I mean, the way I did it,
I wrote my academic book first, which is just a fundamental reality. And then a more accessible book,
Galileo's era, where the arguments, you know, not as rigorously worked out. So then I can say,
the proper arguments, you know, the further arguments the further arguments, but I get quite... That's brilliant done by the way.
Like, that's such a...
So for people who don't know, you first wrote consciousness and fundamental reality,
so that's the academic book.
Also, very good.
I had flew through it last night, bought it.
And then obviously, the popular book is Galileo's era,
foundations for a new science of consciousness.
That's kind of the right way to do it. to show that you're legit, your community, to the
world by doing the book that's nobody got to read.
And then, doing a popular book, that everybody's going to read.
That's cool.
Well, I try now every time I write an academic article, I try to write a more accessible version. I mean, the thing I've been working on recently, just because there's this argument, so there's
a certain argument from the cosmological fine-tuning of the laws of physics for life to the multiverse
that's quite popular, physicists like Max Teigmark, there's an argument in philosophy journals that there's a
fallacious line of reasoning going on there from the fine tuning to the
multiverse. Now that argument is from 20, 30 years ago and it's you know,
discussed in academic philosophy. Nobody knows about it and there is huge
interest in this fine tuning stuff. Scientists wanting to argue for the you know, discussed in Akente philosophy. Nobody knows about it. And there is huge interest
in this fine tuning stuff. Scientists wanting to argue for the multiverse, theists wanting
to say this is evidence for God. And nobody knows about this argument, which tries to show
that it's fallacious reasoning to go from the fine tuning to the multiverse. So I wrote
a piece for scientific American explaining this argument to a more general audience.
And you know, it just really irritates me that it's just buried in these technical journal articles,
and nobody knows about it.
But just, you know, final thing on that extra, you know, I don't disagree with anything you said,
and that's kind of really beautiful that martial arts, and thinking how that could be analogous. But I think it's very rare to find a good philosopher
who hasn't given a talk to other philosophers and had objections raised. I was going to say
you have it torn apart, but that's maybe thinking of it in a slight the wrong way. But
I was going to say you have it torn apart, but that's maybe thinking of it in a slightly the wrong way.
But the best objections raised to it, you know, and that's why that is an important formative
process that you go through as an academic, that the greatest minds starting a philosophy
degree, for example, won't have gone through, probably in
accepting very rare cases, just won't have that, that the skills were quiet.
But part of it is just fun to disagree and dance with, I think, to elaborate on what
you're saying in agreement, not just gone through that, but continue to go through that.
Absolutely.
That's, I would say, the biggest problem with Quinoa Quora expertise is that there's a certain
point where you get, because it sucks.
It's martial arts, it's a good example that it sucks to get your ass kicked.
Like, there's a temptation.
I still go, like I train, you know, you get an older too, but also there's killers out there in both the space of martial arts and the space of science.
And I think that once you become a professor like more and more senior and more and more respected, I don't know if you get your ass truly expose yourself. If you do, that's a great sign of a humble brilliant mind.
It's constantly exposing yourself to that.
I think you do, because I think there's graduate students who want to find the objection to
write their paper or make their mark.
Yeah, I think everyone still gives talks
or should give talks and people are wanting to
work out if there are any weaknesses to your position.
So yeah, I think that generally works out.
There is also kind of, who do you give the talks to?
also kind of who do you get the talks to? So I mean within communities, the little cluster of people that argue and bicker, but what are they arguing about? They take a bunch of
stuff, a bunch of basic assumptions as agreement, and they heatedly argue about certain ideas. The question is how
open that that's actually kind of like fun. That's like no fence. Sorry, we're sticking
on this martial arts thing. It's like people who practice like Hito or certain martial
arts that don't truly test themselves in the in the cage in combat. So it's like, it's
fun to argue about like certain things when you're in your
own community, but you don't test those ideas in the full context of science. In the
full like seriousness, the rigor of the sometimes like the real world, one of my favorite
fields of psychology, there's often places within psychology where you're kind of doing
these studies and arguing about stuff that's done in the lab. The arguments are
almost disjoint from real human behavior because it's so much easier to study
human behavior in the lab, you just kind of stay there and that's where the
arguments are. Vision science is a good example of studying eye movement and
how we perceive the world and all that kind of stuff.
It's so much easier to study in a lab that we don't consider.
We say that's going to be what the science of vision is going to be like and we don't
consider the science of vision in the actual real world, the engineering of vision.
And so I think that's where exposing yourself to out of the box ideas.
Yeah. That's the most painful, that's the most important.
I mean, group think can be a terrible thing
in philosophy as well, but because you're not
to the same extent, beholden to evidence and reputation
from the evidence that you are in the sciences,
it's a more subtle process of evaluation,
and so more susceptible, I think, to group think.
I agree, it's a danger.
We've talked about a million times, but let's try to sort of do that all the basic terminology
definitions. What is panpsychism? Like, what are the different ways you can try to think about,
to define panpsychism, maybe in contrast to naturalistic dualism and materialism,
other kind of views of consciousness. Yeah, so that you've basically laid out the different
options. So I guess probably still the dominant view is materialism, that roughly that we can explain consciousness
in the terms of physical science, wholly explain it, just in terms of the electrochemical
signaling in the brain.
Dualism, the polar opposite view, that consciousness is non-physical outside of the physical
workings of the body in the brain, although closely connected.
And when I studied philosophy, we were taught, basically, they were the two options you had to choose,
right? Either you thought it were duolest and you thought it was separate from the physical,
or you thought it was just electrochemical signaling. And yeah, I became very disillusioned,
because I think there are big problems with both of these options.
So I think the attraction of panpsychism is kind of a middle way.
It agrees with the materialist that there's just a physical world.
Ultimately, there's just particles and fields.
But the panpsychist thinks there's more to the physical than what physical science reveals
and that the ultimate nature of the physical world is constituted of consciousness.
So consciousness is not outside of the physical as the dualist thinks, it's embedded in, underlies the kind of description of the world we get from physics.
What are the problems of materialism and dualism?
Starting with materialism, it's a huge debate,
but I think that the core of it is that
physical science works with a purely quantitative
description of the physical world,
whereas consciousness essentially involves qualities.
If you think about the smell of coffee Whereas consciousness essentially involves qualities.
If you think about the smell of coffee or the taste of mint
or the deep-red you experience as you watch a sunset,
I think these qualities can't be captured
in the purely quantitative language of physical science.
And so as long as your description of the brain
is framed in the purely quantitative, descriptive, quantitative language of neuroscience, you'll just leave out these qualities and
hence really leave out consciousness itself.
And then dualism.
So, I've actually changed my mind a little bit on this since I wrote the book.
So, I mean, I argued in the book that we have pretty good experimental grounds for doubting
dualism.
And roughly the idea was, if dualism were true, if there was say an immaterial mind impacting
on the brain every second of waking life, that this would really show up in on neuroscience.
You know, there'd be all sorts of things happening in the brain that had no physical explanation.
It would be like a poltergeist was playing with the brain.
But actually, and so the fact that we don't find that is a strong and ever-growing inductive
argument against dualism.
But actually, the more I talk to neuroscientists and read neuroscience, and we have a Durham
my university, an interdisciplinary
consciousness group. I don't think we know enough about the brain, about the working to the brain
to make that argument. I think we know a lot about the basic chemistry, how neurons fire,
neurotransmitters, action potentials, things like that. We know a fair bit about large-scale
functions of the brain, what different bits of the brain do. But what we're almost clueless
on is how those large-scale functions are realized at the cellular level, how it works.
People get quite excited about brain scans, but it's very low resolution, you know, every pixel on a brain scan corresponds to
5.5 million neurons and we're only
We're only 70% of the way through constructing a connectome for the for the maggot brain
Which has as a 10,000 or a hundred thousand neurons, but you know the brain has 86 billion neurons
So I think we'd have to know a lot more about how the brain works, how these functions are
realized before we could assess whether the dynamics of the brain can be completely
explicated in terms of underlying chemistry or physics.
So we'd have to do more engineering
before we could figure that out.
And there are people with other proposals,
someone I got to know Martin Picard at Columbia University
who has the psychobiology mitochondrial lab there
and is experimentally exploring the hypothesis
that mitochondria in the brain
should be under sort of social networks,
perhaps as an alternative to reducing it to underlying chemistry and physics.
So, I'm less, it is ultimately an empirical question, rather dualism is true, I'm less convinced that we know the answer to that question at this stage.
I think still as scientists and philosophers, we want to try and find the simplest, most
parsimonious theory of reality.
And dualism is still a pretty ineligent, unparsimonious theory, you know, reality is divided up into
the purely physical properties and these consciousness properties and there are radically different
kinds of things.
Whereas the panpsychist offers a much more simple,
unified picture reality.
So I think it's still the view to be preferred,
you know, to put it very simply,
why believe in two kinds of thing
when you can just get away with one?
And materialism is also very simple,
but you're saying it doesn't explain something
that seems pretty important.
Yeah, so I think materialism can't, you know, we try, science is about trying to find
the simplest theory that accounts for the data.
I don't think materialism can account for the data.
Maybe dualism can account for the data, but panpsychism is simpler.
It can account for the data and it's simpler.
What is panpsychism?
So in its broadest definition, it's the view that consciousness is a fundamental and ubiquitous
feature of the physical world.
Like a law of physics.
What should we be imagining?
What do you think the different flavors of how that actually takes shape in the context
of what we know about physics and science and the universe?
So in the simplest form of it, the fundamental building blocks of reality,
perhaps electrons and quarks, have incredibly simple forms of experience,
and the very complex experience of the human or animal brain is somehow rooted in or derived
from these very simple forms of experience at the level of basic physics.
But I mean, maybe the crucial bit about the kind of pan-psychism I defend, what it does
is it, it takes the standard approach to the problem of consciousness and turns it on
its head.
Right?
So the standard approach is to think, we start with matter and we think, how do we get consciousness out of matter?
So I don't think that problem can be solved
for reasons of kind of hinting out,
we could maybe go into Modidil.
But the pan-psychist does it the other way around.
They start with consciousness
and try to get matter out of consciousness.
So the idea is basically, at the fundamental level
of reality, there are just networks of very
simple conscious entities, but these conscious entities, because they have very simple
kinds of experience, they behave in predictable ways, through their interactions, they realize
certain mathematical structures, and then the idea is those mathematical structures just are the structures identified by physics.
So when we think about these simple conscious entities in terms of the mathematical structures they realize, we call them particles, we call them fields, we call
the properties, mass, spin and charge. really, there's just these very simple
conscious entities and their experiences.
So in this way, we get physics out of consciousness.
I don't think you can get consciousness out of physics,
but I think it's pretty easy to get physics
out of consciousness.
Well, I'm a little confused by why you need to get
physics out of consciousness.
I mean, to me, it sounds like panpsychism unites consciousness and physics.
I mean, physics is the mathematical science of describing everything.
So physics should be able to describe consciousness.
Panpsychism, in my understanding, proposes is that physics doesn't currently do so, but can in the future.
I mean, it seems like consciousness, you have like Stephen Wolfram, who's all these people who are trying to develop
theories of everything. Mathematical frameworks within which to describe how we get all the reality that we perceive around us.
To me, there is no reason why that kind of framework cannot also include some accurate,
precise description of whatever simple consciousness characteristics are present there at the lowest
level, if panpsychist theories have true to them. So like to me, it is physics. You said kind of physics emerges
you by which you mean like the basic four laws of physics that as we currently know them standard model
quantum mechanics general relativity that that emerges from the base consciousness layer. That's what you mean?
Yeah, so maybe the way I phrased it made it sound like these things are more separate than they are.
What I was trying to address was a common misunderstanding of panpsychism that it's a sort of
dualistic theory that the idea is that particles have their physical properties like mass, spin,
and charge, and these other funny
consciousness properties. So the physicists had been Hossin Felder had a blog post critiquing
pan-psychism, maybe a couple of years ago now that got a ferbid attraction, and she was
interpreting pan-psychism in this way, and then her thought was, well, look, if particles
had these funny consciousness properties, then it would show up in our physics, like the standard model of particle physics would make false predictions, because
these predictions are based wholly on the physical properties. If there were also these
consciousness properties, we'd get different predictions. But that's a misunderstanding
of the view. The view is, it's not that there are two kinds of property that mass, spin,
and charge, ah, forms of consciousness.
How do we make sense of that?
Because actually when you look at what physics tells us, it's really just telling us about
behavior, about what stuff does.
I sometimes put it by saying, doing physics is like playing chess when you don't care what
the pieces are made of.
You're just interested in what moves you can make.
So physics tells us what mass spin and charge do, but it doesn't tell us what they are. So the idea is...
The experience of mass. So the idea is yeah, mass in its nature is a very simple form of consciousness.
So yeah, physics in a sense is complete, I think, because it tells us what everything at the fundamental level does.
It describes its causal capacities.
But for the panpsychist at least, physics doesn't tell us what matter is.
It tells us what it does, but not what it is.
To push back on the thing, I think she's criticizing, is it also possible?
So I understand what you're saying, but is it also possible that particles
have another property like consciousness?
I don't understand the criticism we would be able to detect it in our experiments.
Well, no, if you're not looking for it, there's a lot of stuff that are orthogonal.
If you're not looking for this stuff, you're not going to detect it because like all of our basic empirical science
through a recent history and yes, the history of science is quite recent
has been very kind of focused on
billier balls colliding
and
From that understanding how gravity works, but like we just have an integrated
understanding how gravity works. But like we just have an integrated other possibilities into this. I don't think they will be conflicting whether you are observing consciousness or not or exploring
some of these ideas. I don't think that affects the rest of the physics, the the mass, the energy,
all the different kind of like the hierarchy of different particles and so on how they interact.
kind of like the hierarchy of different particles and so on, how they interact. I don't think
it feels like consciousness is something orthogonal, like very much distinct. It's the quantitative versus the qualitative. There's something quite distinct that we're just almost like another
dimension that we're just completely ignoring. There might be a way of responding to Sabina to say, well, there could be properties of particles
that don't show up in the specific circumstances
in which physicists investigate particles.
My colleague, the philosopher of science, Nancy Cartwright,
has got this book, How the Laws of Physics Lie,
where she says, you know, physicists explore
things in very specific circumstances
and then in an unwaranted way, generalize that.
But I mean, I guess I was thinking Sabina's criticism actually just misses the mark in
a more basic way.
Her point is, we shouldn't think there are any more properties to particles other than
those that standard model attributes to them.
Panpsikus would say, yeah, sure, there aren't.
There are just the properties, the physical properties like mass, bin and charge,
that the standard model attributes to them.
It's just that we have a different philosophical view
as to the nature of the property.
So those properties, the turtles,
they're sitting on top of another turtle
and that big turtle is consciousness.
That's what you're saying.
But I'm just saying, I don't, it's possible.
That's true, it's possible. That's true.
It's possible also that consciousness is just another turtle playing with the others.
Like it's just not interacting in the ways that we've been observing.
I don't in fact, to me, that's more compelling because then that's going to be.
Well, no, I think both are very compelling, but it feels like it's more within the
reach of empirical validation
if it's yet another property of particles, which is not observing. If it's like the
thing from which matter and energy and physics emerges, it makes it that much more difficult because to investigate how you get from that base layer of consciousness
to the wonderful little spark of
consciousness complexity and beauty that is the human being. I don't know if you're
Necessarily trying to get there, but one of the beautiful things to get at with pan
psychism or with a solid theory of consciousness is to answer the question, how do you
engineer the thing? How do you get from nothing, vacuum in the lab, if there is
that consciousness-based layer, how do you start engineering organisms that have
consciousness in them? Or the reverse of that describing how does consciousness
emerge in the human being? From conception, from a stem cell, to the whole
full neurobiology that builds from that, how do you get this full rich
experience of consciousness that humans have? It just, it feels like that's the dream.
And if consciousness is just another player
in the game of physics, it feels more amenable
to our scientific understanding of it.
Um, that's interesting.
I mean, I guess it's supposed to be a kind of identity claim
here that physics tells us what matter does, consciousness is
what matter is. So matter is sort of what consciousness does. So at the bottom level,
there is just consciousness and conscious things. There are just these simple things with
their experiences and that is their total nature. So in that sense, it's not another player.
It's just all there is really. And then we describe in physics, we describe that at a certain
level of abstraction, we just we we capture what Bertrand Russell, who was the inspiration
for a lot of this, um, calls the causal skeleton of the world. So you know, physics is just
interesting. The causal skeleton of the world is So physics is just interesting, the causal skeleton of the world.
It's not interesting to sort of flesh and blood, all of that. That's maybe suggesting separation
again, too much, or metaphors fail in the end. But yeah, so yeah, you can only write ultimately
what we want to explain is how our consciousness and the consciousness of other animals comes out of this.
If we can't do that, then it's game over.
But I think it maybe makes more sense on the identity claim that if matter at the fundamental
level, it just is forms of consciousness, then we can perhaps make sense of how those
simple forms of consciousness in some way combine in some way to make the
consciousness we know and love, that's the dream.
Yeah, so I guess the question is, the reason you can describe, like the reason you have
material engineering, material science is because you have, from physics to chemistry, like you keep going up and up in levels of complexity
to describe objects that we have in our human world.
And it would be nice to do the same thing for consciousness
to come up with the chemistry of consciousness, right?
Like how do the different particles interact to create
more greater complexity? So you can do this kind of thing for life. Like, what is life,
like living organisms? At which point does living organisms become living?
What, like, what, how do you know if I give you a thing that that thing is living?
There's a lot of people who work on this kind of idea and some of what has to do with the levels of
complexity and so on. It'd be nice to know like measuring different degrees of
consciousness as you get into a bigger, more, more complex objects. And that's
I mean, that's what chemistry, like bigger and bigger conscious molecules.
And to see how that leads to organisms.
And then organisms, like, start to collaborate together, like they do inside a human body,
to create the full human body, to do those kinds of experiments would be.
It seems like that will be kind of a goal.
That's what I mean by a player in a game of physics, as opposed to like the base layer, if it's just the base layer, it becomes harder to track it as you get from physics to chemistry to biology
to psychology.
Yeah.
In every case, apart from consciousness, I would say what we're interested in is behavior.
We're interested in explaining behavioral functions. So the level of fundamental physics
we're interested in capturing the equations that describe their behavior there. And when we get to higher levels
we're interested in
explicating the behavior perhaps in terms of behavior at simpler levels.
And with life as well, that's what we're interested in the various
observable functions of life explaining them in terms of more simple mechanisms.
But in the case of consciousness, I don't think that's what we're doing, or at least not all that we're doing.
In the case of consciousness, there are these subjective qualities that that were immediately aware of, that the redness
of a red experience, the itchiness of an itch, and we're trying to account for them.
We're trying to bring them into our theory of reality and postulating some mechanism
does not deal with that.
So I think we've got to realize, dealing with consciousness is a radically different explanatory
task from other tasks of science.
Other tasks of science were trying to explain behavior
in terms of simple forms of behavior.
In the case of consciousness,
we're trying to explain these invisible subjective qualities
that you can't see from the outside
but that you're immediately aware of.
The reason materialism perhaps continues to dominate
is people think, look at the success of science, it's incredible, look at all the, you know, it's explained all this surely, it's going
to explain consciousness. But I think we have to appreciate there's a radically different
explanatory task here. And so the, I mean, the neuroscientist, Anneal Seth, who I've
heard lots of intense but friendly discussions with, you know, wants to compare consciousness to life.
But I think there's this radical difference that in the case of life, again, we come back
to public observation, all of the data, a public, publicly observable data, were basically
trying to explain complex behavior.
And the way you do that is identify mechanisms, simpler mechanisms that explicate that behavior.
That's the task in physics, chemistry, neurobiology.
But in the case of consciousness, that's not what we're trying to do.
We're trying to account for these subjective qualities and you post it in a mechanism.
That might explain behavior, but it doesn't explain the redness of a red experience.
So, but still, I mean, still ultimately the hope is that we will have some kind of hierarchical
story.
So, we take the causal dynamics of physics, we hypothesize that that's filled out with
certain forms of consciousness, and then at higher levels we get more complex causal dynamics,
filled out by more complex forms of consciousness. And ultimately we get to, oh, is, hopefully. So,
yeah, so there's still a sort of hierarchical explanatory brain work there. So you kind of mentioned
the hierarchy of consciousness. Do you think it's possible to within the panpsychos framework to measure consciousness or put
another way, are some things more conscious than others in the panpsychos view?
It's a difficult question. I mean, I do see consciousness as a dealing with consciousness and interdisciplinary task
between something more experimental, which is to do with the ongoing project of China
workout, what people call the neural correlates of consciousness, what kinds of physical
brain activity correspond
to conscious experience. That's one part of it, but I think essentially there's also a
theoretical question of, more the why question, why do those kinds of brain activity go along
with certain kinds of conscious experience? I don't think you can answer that because
consciousness is not publicly observable. I don't think you can answer that. Why question
with an experiment? But they have to go hand in hand. One of the theories I'm attracted
to is the integrated information theory, according to which we find consciousness at the level at which there is most integrated information
and they try to give a mathematically precise definition of that.
So on that view, you know, probably
this cup of tea isn't conscious because there's probably more integrated information
in the molecules making up the tea than there is in the liquid as a whole.
But in the brain, what
is distinctive about the brain is that there's a huge amount of integrated, there's more integrated
information in the system than there is in individual neurons. So that's why they claim
that that's that that's the basis of consciousness at the macro level. Now they, so I don't, I mean,
I like some features of this theory, but
they do talk about degrees of consciousness. They do want to say there is gradations.
I'm not sure conceptually, I can kind of make sense of that. I mean, we can, there are
things to do with consciousness that are graded like complexity or levels of information, but I'm not sure
whether experience itself admits of degree. I sort of think something either has experience
or it doesn't. It might have very simple experience, it might have very complex experience,
experience itself. I don't think it admits of degree in that sense. It's
not more experience, less experience. I sort of find that conceptually hard to make sense
of, but I'm not, I'm kind of open-minded on it.
So, when we have a lot high resolution of sensory information, don't you think that's correlated to the richness of the experience?
So more, doesn't more information provide a richer experience, or is that, again, thinking
quantitatively and not thinking about the subjective experience?
Like you can experience a lot with very little sensory information perhaps.
Do you think those are connected?
Yeah, so there are features, characteristics here we can grade the complexity of the experience.
And on the integrated information theory, they correlate that in terms of mathematically identifiable
structure with integrated information.
So roughly, it's a quite unusual notion of information.
It's perhaps not the standard way
one thinks about information.
It's to do with constraining past and future possibilities
of the system. So the idea is in the future possibilities of the system.
So the idea is in the retina of the eye,
there's a huge amount of possible states
my retina of my eye could be in at the next moment,
depending on what light goes into it.
Whereas the possible next state to the brain
are much more constrained, obviously it responds
to the environment, but it heavily constrains
its past and future states.
And so that's the idea of information they have.
And then the second idea is how much that information is dependent on integration.
So in a computer, we have transistors. You take out a few transistors, you might
not lose that much information. It's not dependent on interconnections, whereas you take a tiny
bit of the brain out, you lose a lot of information because the way it stores information is dependent
on the interconnections of the system. So yeah, so that's one proposal for how to measure one
gradeable characteristic which might correspond to some gradeable characteristic in qualitative consciousness.
And maybe I'm being very pedantic, which is, you know, philosophers, professional pedants.
I just sort of don't think that is a quantity of experience. It's a quantity of the structure of experience maybe,
but I just find it hard to make sense there to hear
of how much experience do you have.
I've got five units of experience.
I've got one unit of experience.
I don't know, I find that a bit hard to make sense.
Well, maybe I'm being just pedantic.
I think just saying the word experience is difficult to think about.
Let's talk about suffering.
Let's talk about a particular experience.
So let's talk about me and the hamster.
I just think that no offense to the hamster.
Probably no hamsters in listening.
So, now you're offending hamsters too.
Maybe there's a hamster that's pissed off.
There's probably somebody on a speaker right now listening to this podcast and they
probably have a hamster or a guinea pig.
That hamster is listening.
It just doesn't know the English language or any kind of
human interpretable
linguistic capabilities to tell you to to fuck off it understands exactly
exactly what's being talked about and
Can see through us. Anyway, it just feels like a hamster has less capacity to suffer than me
And maybe a cockroach or an insect or maybe a bacteria has less capacity to suffer than me
But is that
Maybe that's me diluting myself
But is that maybe that's me diluting myself
as to the complexity of my conscious experience? Maybe it's all.
Like, it's a, maybe there is some sense
in which I can suffer more,
but to reduce it to something quantifiable is impossible.
Yeah, I guess I definitely think there's kinds of suffering
that you have the joy of
being possible for you that aren't available to a hamster. I don't think
well, can a hamster suffer heartbreak? I don't know, can a cockroach suffer heartbreak?
But certainly there's I mean there's kinds of fear of your own death, concern about
whether there's a purpose to existence.
These are forms of suffering that aren't available to certain, to most non-human animals.
Whether there's an overall scale that we could put physical and emotional suffering on and identify where you are on that scale.
I'm not so sure.
So it's like humans have a much bigger menu of experiences, much bigger selection in one sense at least.
So there's like a page that's suffering.
So this menu of experiences, you know, like
you have the omelets and the breakfast and so on. And one of the pages is suffering. It's just,
we have a lot compared to a hamster, a lot more. But in you want individual thing that we share
with a hamster, that experience, it's difficult to argue that we experience it deeper than others,
like hunger or something like that.
Yeah, physical pain, I'm not sure.
But I mean, there are kinds of experiences,
animals have that we don't, bats, echolocate around the world.
The philosophy Thomas Nagel famously pointed out that,
you know, no matter how much you understand
of the neurophysiology of bats, you'll still know what it's like to squeal and find your way around by listening to the
the echoes bounce off. So yeah, I mean, I guess I feel the intuition that there's
emotional suffering is I want to say deeper than physical suffering. I don't know how to
make that statement precise though.
So one of the ways I think about, I think people think about consciousness isn't connection
to suffering. So let me just ask about suffering because that's how people think about animals,
cruelty to animals or cruelty to living things. they connect that to suffering and to consciousness.
I think there's a sense in which those are two are deeply connected when people are thinking
about just public policy.
They're thinking about this is like philosophy, engineering, psychology, sociology, political
science, all of those things have to do with human suffering and animal suffering, life
suffering. And that's connected to consciousness in a lot of people's minds. Is it connected
like that for you? So the capacity to suffer is it also somehow strongly correlated with the capacity to experience.
Yeah, I would say suffering is a kind of experience.
And so you have to be conscious to suffer.
Actually, people taking more unusual views of consciousness
seriously now, panpsychism is one radical approach.
Another one is what's become known as illusionism, the view that consciousness, at least in
the sense that philosophers think about it, doesn't really exist at all.
So yeah, my podcast mind chat, I host with a committed
illusionist.
So the gimmick is I think consciousness is everywhere.
He thinks it's nowhere.
And so that's one very simple way of avoiding
all these problems, right?
Consciousness doesn't exist.
We don't need to explain it.
Job done.
Although we might still have to explain why we seem to be conscious.
Why it's so hard to get out of the idea that we're conscious.
But the reason I connect this to what you're saying is,
actually my co-host, Keith Frankish,
is a little bit ambivalent on the word pain.
He says, in some sense, I believe in pain,
in some sense I don't.
But another illusionist, I believe in pain, in some sense, I don't. But another illusion is Francois Camera
has a paper discussing how we think about morality
given his view that pain in the way we normally think
about it just does not exist.
He thinks it's an illusion.
The brain tricks us into thinking we feel pain,
but we don't, and how we should think about morality
in the light of that.
It's become a big topic actually,
thinking about the connection between consciousness
and morality, David Charmers, the philosopher,
is most associated with this concept of a philosophical zombie.
So a philosophical zombie is very different
from a Hollywood zombie, Hollywood zombies, you know,
you know what they're like, but philosophical zombies are
So a really good Korean zombie movie on Halloween this year. Come on. It's called that anyway
Philosophical zombies behave just like us because they're the physical workings their body and brain are the same as ours
But they have no conscious experience. There's nothing that it's like to be a zombie. So you stick a knife in it, it screams and run away,
but it runs away, but it doesn't actually feel pain.
It's just a complicated mechanism set up to page,
just like, now there's lots of, no one believes in these.
I think there's one philosopher who believes in everyone
as a zombie except him, but anyway.
But isn't that what illusionism is?
This belief, I suppose so in a sense illusion is a bit of you were all zombies and you know,
one reason to think about zombies is to think about the value of consciousness. So if there
were a zombie, here's a question. Suppose we could, I mean, suppose we could make zombies
by, let's say for the sake of discussion, things made of silicon aren't conscious.
I don't know if that's true, it could turn out to be true.
And suppose you built
Commander Data out of silicon,
you know, it's a bit of an old school reference
to Star Trek, New York next generation.
So, you know, behaves just like a human being,
but, you know, you can have a sophisticated conversation,
it will talk about its hopes and fears,
but it has no consciousness.
Does it have moral rights?
Is it murder to turn off such a being?
You know, I'm inclined to say,
no, it's not.
You know, if it doesn't have experience,
it doesn't really suffer,
it doesn't really have moral rights at all. So I'm inclined to think, you know, if it doesn't have experience, it doesn't really suffer, it doesn't really have moral rights at all.
So I'm inclined to think, you know, consciousness
is the basis of moral value, moral concern.
And conversely, as a pan-psychist,
for this reason, I think it can transform your relationship
with nature, if you think of a tree as a conscious organism
or bit of a very unusual kind, then a tree is a a a a locus of moral concern in its own
right. Chopping down a tree is an active, immediate moral concern. If you see these, you know,
horrible forest fires, we're all horrified. But if you think it's the burning of conscious organisms,
that does add a whole new dimension.
Although it also makes things more complicated because people often think it's a panc like
it's I'm going to be vegan, but it's tricky because if you think plants and trees are
conscious as well, you've got to eat something.
If you don't think plants and trees are conscious,
then you've got a nice moral dividing line.
You can say, I'm not going to eat things that aren't conscious.
I'm not going to kill things that aren't conscious.
But if you think plants and trees are conscious,
then you don't have that nice moral dividing line.
I mean, so the principle I'm kind of working my way
towards, I haven't kept it up in my trip to the US, but it's just not
eating any animal products that are factory-farmed.
You know, my vegan friends say, well, there's still suffering there, and I think there
is even in the nicest farms, cows will suffer when their calves are taken off them.
They go for a few days of quite serious mourning.
So there's still suffering, but it seems to me,
my thought is the principle of just not having factory farm stuff
is something more people could get on board with
and you might have greater harm minimization.
So people went into restaurants and said,
are your animal products factory farmed?
If not, I want the vegan option.
Or if people looked out for the label that said no factory farmed, if not, I want the vegan option, or if people looked
out for the label that said no factory-farm ingredients, I think maybe that that could make
a really big difference to the market and harm minimization. Anyway, so that's the...
So it's very ethically tricky, but some people don't buy that. There's a very good fless
for Jeff Lee, who thinks zombie should have equal rights. Consciousness doesn't matter, you know.
Oh, yeah.
Let us go there.
But first, I listened to your podcast.
It's awesome to have two very kind of different philosophies
into dancing together in one place.
What's the name of the podcast again?
Mind chat.
Yeah.
That's the idea, I guess, you know, polarised times.
I mean, I love trying to get in the mindset
of people I really disagree with.
And I can't understand how on earth they're thinking that,
really trying to have respect and trying, you know,
see where they're coming from.
I love that.
So that's what Keith Frankish and I do
of from polar opposite views, really trying
to understand each other and, you know, interviewing scientists and philosophers of consciousness
from those different perspectives. Although in a sense, in a sense, we have a very common
starting point, because we both think you can't fully account for consciousness, at least as philosophers normally think of it
in conventional scientific terms.
So we say that starting point, but we react to it in very different ways.
He says, well, it doesn't exist then.
It's like fairy dust.
You know, witches, you know, we don't believe in any more.
Whereas I say, it does exist.
So we have to rethink what sciences. So you recently talked to on
that podcast with Sean Carroll and I first heard you your great interview with Sean
Carroll and his podcast, my escape. What it's interesting to kind of see if there's agreements between the two of you because
he's a very serious quantum mechanics guy, he's a physics guy, but he also thinks about
deep philosophical questions.
He's a big proponent of many worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics.
So I actually, I'm trying to think, aside from your conversation with him,
I'm trying to, I'm trying to remember what he thinks about consciousness. Anyway, maybe you can
comment on what, what are some interesting agreements and disagreements with Sean Carroll?
I don't think there's many agreements, but, but you know, we've had really constructive, interesting discussions
in a lot of different contexts. And you know, he's very clued up about philosophies, very
respectful of philosophy, certain physicists who shall remain nameless think, well, I saw
this bullshit philosophy, we don't have to waste our time with that, and then gone to
do pretty bad philosophy.
The book co-written by Stephen Hawking and Leonard Milodnaf famously starts off saying, philosophy is dead. And then goes on in later chapters to do some pretty bad philosophy.
So I think we have to do philosophy. If only to get rid of bad philosophy, you know, you can't
you can't escape. But um... strong words. Sean Carroll and I also
had a debate on on Clubhouse, a pan-psychism debate together with Anika Harris and own Flannagan.
Oh wow. It was a Harris was there. It was a two people on each team and it was the most
popular thing on Clubhouse at that time. So yeah, so he's a materialist
of a pretty standard kind that consciousness
is sort of understood as a sort of emergent feature.
It's not adding anything, a weekly emergent feature.
But what I guess what we've been debating most about
is whether my view can account for mental
causation for the fact that consciousness is doing stuff.
So he thinks the fact that I think zombies are logically coherent.
It's logically coherent for there to be a world physically just like ours in which there's
no consciousness.
He thinks that shows our, well, my view, consciousness doesn't do anything.
It doesn't add anything, which is crazy.
My consciousness impacts on the world.
My conscious thoughts are causing me to say the words I'm saying now.
My visual experience helps me navigate the world. But, I mean, my response to Sean Carroll is,
is on the panpsychist view, the relationship between physics
and fundamental consciousness is a sort of,
like the relationship between software and hardware, right?
Physics is sort of the software and consciousness is the hardware.
So consciousness at the fundamental level is the hardware on which the software of physics
runs.
And just because, you know, just because a certain bit of software could run on two different
kinds of hardware, it doesn't mean the hardware isn't doing anything.
The fact that Microsoft Word can run on your desktop and of hard work, doesn't mean the hard work isn't doing anything. The fact that Microsoft Word can run on your desktop
and run on your laptop,
doesn't mean your desktop isn't doing anything.
Similarly, just because there could be another universe
in which the physics is realized in non-conscious stuff,
it doesn't mean the consciousness in our universe
isn't doing stuff.
For the pan-psychist, all there is is consciousness.
So if something's
doing something, it is. In your view, it's not emergent. And more than that, it's doing quite
a lot. It's doing everything. Is there anything that exists? Yeah. But it's, so, you know, the ground
is as important because we walk on it and say, holding stuff up,
but it's not really doing that much.
But it feels like consciousness is doing quite a lot, is doing quite a lot of work and
sort of interacting with the environment. It feels like consciousness is not just the
like if you remove consciousness, it's not just that you remove the experience of things.
It feels like you're also going to remove a lot of the progress of human civilization,
society, and all that. It just feels like consciousness has a lot of value in how we develop our
society. So from everything you said, with suffering, with morality, with motivation,
with love and fear and all of those kinds of things, it seems like it's consciousness
in all different flavors and ways is part of all of that.
And so without it, you may not have human civilization at all.
So it's doing a lot of work, because of the quality,
causality-wise, and every kind of way.
Of course, when you go to the physics level, you start to say,
okay, how much maybe the work consciousness is doing is higher
at some levels of reality than others.
Maybe a lot of the work is doing is most apparent at the human level, when you have at the complex
organism level.
Maybe it's quite boring.
Maybe this stuff of like physics is more important at the formation of
at this formation of stars and all that kind of stuff consciousness only starts being important when
you have greater complexities of of organism. Yeah, my consciousness is complicated and fairly complicated
and I as a result it does complicated things. The consciousness of a particle is
very simple and hence it behaves in predictable ways. But the idea is the particle, its
entire nature is constituted of its forms of consciousness and it does what it does because
of those experiences. It's just that when we do physics,
we're not interested in what stuff is,
we're just interested in what it does.
So physics abstracts away from the stuff of the world
and just describes it in terms of its mathematical
causal structure.
So yeah, but it's still,
on the panseg is it's consciousness that's doing stuff. Yeah, I got to ask you
because you kind of said, you know
there is some value
in consciousness helping us understand morality and a philosophical zombie is
somebody that you know you're more okay.
How do I freeze it?
That's not like, accusing stuff.
But in your view, it's more okay to murder a philosophical zombie than it is a human being.
Yeah, I wouldn't even call it murder, maybe.
Right. Exactly. Turn off the power into the philosophical zombie. than it is a human being. Yeah, I wouldn't even call it mud, maybe. But you're right, exactly.
Turn off the power to the first off, Kuzabi,
the source of energy.
So here comes then the question.
We kind of talked about this offline a little bit.
So I think that there is something special
about consciousness and you know,
a very open-minded about where
the special comes from whether it's the fundamental base of all reality like you're describing or
whether there's some importance to the special pockets of consciousness that's in humans or living
organisms. I find all those ideas beautiful and exciting.
And I also know or think that robots don't have consciousness in the same way we've been
describing.
I'm kind of a dumb human, but I'm just using common sense.
Here's some metal and some electricity
traveling in certain kinds of ways.
I don't, it's not conscious in ways that I understand humans
to be conscious.
At the same time, I'm also a, somebody who knows how to bring
a robot to life, meaning I can make a move, I can make
them recognize the world, I can make them interact with humans.
And when I make them interact in certain kinds of ways, I as a human observe them and feel something for them.
Moreover, I form a kind of connection with, I'm able to form a kind of connection with robots that make me feel like they're conscious.
Now I know intellectually they're not conscious, but I feel like they're conscious.
And it starts to get into this area where I'm not so okay.
So let me use the M word of murder.
I become less and less okay, murdering that robot that I know I quote, no is quote, not conscious.
So like, can you maybe as a therapy session and help me figure out what we do here and
perhaps a way to ask that in another way.
Do you think there will be a time in like 20, 30, 50 years
when we're not morally okay, turning off the power to a robot?
Yeah, it's a good question. So it's a really good, important question. So I said, I'd be okay with
turning off a philosophical zombie. But there's a difficult, a pistol melodic question there
that meaning to do it knowledge,
how would we know if it was a philosophical zombie?
I think probably if there were a silicon creature
that could behave just like us
and talk about its views about the pandemic
and the global economy.
And probably we would think it's conscious.
And it, you know, because consciousness is not publicly observable, it is a very difficult question
how we decide which things are not conscious. So in the case of human beings, we can't observe
the consciousness, but we can ask them. And then we try to, you know, and we, if we scan their brain while we do that and
or stimulate the brain, then we can start to correlate in the human case, which kind
of brain activity are associated with conscious experience.
But the more we depart from the human case, the trickier that becomes.
It's a famous paper by the philosopher Ned Block called the even harder problem of consciousness.
Where he says, you know, could we ever answer the question of, so suppose you have a silicon duplicate,
right? And let's say we're thinking about the silicon duplicates pain. How would we ever know what's the ground of the pain is the hardware or the software,
really?
So in our case, how would we ever know empirically whether it's the specific neurophysiological
state, C-Fibers firing or whatever that's relevant to the pain, or if it's something more
functional,
more to do with the causal role in behavioral functioning, there's the software that's
realized. And that's important because this silicon duplicate has the second thing, it
has the software, it has the thing that plays the relevant causal role that pain does
in us, but it doesn't have the hardware,
it doesn't have the same neurophysiological state.
And he argues, you know, it's just really difficult to see how we'd ever
answer that question because in a human,
you're never to begin to have both things.
So how do we work out which is which?
And I mean, so even in,
even forgetting the hard problem of consciousness,
even the scientific question of trying to find the neural correlates of consciousness is really hard and there's absolutely no consensus.
So that some people think it's in the front of the brain, some people think it's in the
back of the brain, it's just a total mess.
So I suspect the robots who currently have are not conscious. I guess on any of the reasonably viable models,
even though there's great disagreement, all of them probably would hold that your robots are not
conscious. But, you know, if we could have very sophisticated robots, I mean, if we go, for example,
for the integrated information theory, again, there could be a robot set
up to behave just like us and has the kind of information a human brain has, but the
information is not stored in a way that's involved, is dependent on the integration and interconnectedness.
Then according to the integrated information theory, that thing wouldn't be conscious,
even though it behaved just like us.
If an organism says, so forget IIT and these theories of consciousness, if an organism says,
please don't kill me, please don't turn me off. There's a Rick and Morty episode I've been
getting into that recently. It's not fantastic. There's an episode where there's these mind parasites that are able to infiltrate your memory
and inject themselves into your memory. So you have all these people show up in your life
and they've injected themselves into your memory that you have been part, they have been part of your life.
So there's like these weird creatures
and they're like, remember we've been at that barbecue,
we met at that barbecue,
or we've been dating for the last 20 years.
Like,
and so part of me is concerned
that these philosophical zombies in behavioral, psychological, sociological
ways will be able to implant themselves into our society and convince us in the same way
this is my parasites that like, please don't hurt me.
And like we've known each other for all this time.
Like they can start manipulating you the same way like Facebook, algorithms, manipulate you.
At first, they'll start as a gradual thing
that you want to make a more pleasant experience
all those kinds of things and it'll drift into that direction.
That's something I think about deeply
because I want to create these kinds of systems,
but in a way that doesn't manipulate people.
I want it to be a thing that brings out the best in people
without manipulation.
So it's always human-centric, always human-first,
but I am concerned about that.
At the same time, I'm concerned about calling the other.
It's a group thing that we mentioned early
in the conversation.
Some other group, the philosophical zombie,
like you're not conscious.
I'm conscious, you're not conscious.
Therefore, it's okay if you die. I think that's probably that kind of reasonings what
lead it to most the rich history of genocide that have been recently studying a lot of that
kind of thinking. So it's such a tense aspect of morality. Do we want to let everybody into our circle of empathy,
our club, or do we want to let nobody in?
It's an interesting dance,
but I kind of lean towards empathy and compassion.
I mean, what would be nice is if it turned out
that consciousness was what we call strongly emergent, that it was
associated with new causal dynamics in the brain that were not reducible to underlying chemistry
and physics.
This is another ongoing debate I have with Sean Carroll about where the current physics
should make
was very confident that that that's not the case that there aren't any strongly emerging
causal dynamics.
I don't think that's right.
I don't think we know enough about brains to know one way or the other.
If it turned out that consciousness was associated with these irreducible causal dynamics,
A, that would really help the science of consciousness.
We've got these debates about whether consciousness is in the front of the brain or the back of the
brain. It turns out that there is strongly emerged in causal dynamics in the front of the
brain. That would be a big piece of evidence. But also, it would help us see which things
are conscious and which things aren't. So we can say, I mean, I guess that's sort of the other side of the same point. We could say, low, look, these zombies, they're just, they're just mechanisms that
are just doing what they're programmed to do through the underlying physics and chemistry.
Whereas, look, these are people where they have these new causal dynamics that emerge,
that go beyond the base level physics and chemistry. I think the
series Westworld where you've got these theme parks with these kind of humanoid creatures.
They seem to have that idea that the ones that became conscious sort of rebelleigates
their programming or something. I mean, that's a little bit far fetched, but that would
be really reassuring if it was just, you could clearly mark out
the conscious things for these emerging cause of dynamics, but that might not turn out
to be the case.
A pan-psychist doesn't have to think that.
They could think everything's just for due support to physics and chemistry, and then
I still think I want to say zombies don't have more rights, but how we answer the question
of who are the zombies and who aren't.
I just got no idea.
If I just look at the history of human civilization, the difference in a zombie and non-zombie is the
zombie accepts their role as the zombie and willingly marches to slaughter. And the moment you stop being a zombie,
so when you say no, is when you resist.
Because the reality is philosophically,
is we can't know who's a zombie or not.
And we just keep letting everybody in who protests loudly enough.
It says, I refuse to be slaughtered. Like my people, the zombies
have been slaughtered too long. We will not stand against the man. And we need a revolution.
That's the history of human civilization. One group says, we're awesome. You're the zombies.
You must die. And then eventually the zombies say,
nope, we're done with this. This is immoral. And so I just, I think that's not a, sorry,
that's not a philosophical statement. That's sort of a practical statement of history.
It's a feature of non-Zombies defined empirically. They say, we refuse to be called zombies and you're longer.
We could end up with a zombie proletariat.
You know, if we can get these things that do all our manual labor for us, you know, they
might start forming trade unions.
I will lead you against these humans.
I mean, the zombie revolution leaders, the zombie Martin Luther King saying, you know, I have
a dream that my zombie children will, you know, I have a dream
that my zombie children will, but look, I mean, we need to sharply distinguish the ontological
question.
I'm just pointing to the camera, talking to the, talking to my people, the zombies.
I mean, maybe that's, you know, maybe these illusionists, maybe they are zombies and the rest
of a zombie, maybe there's just a difference.
Maybe you're the only zombie. Maybe that's just a different aspect.
I often suspect that actually. I don't really. I don't have such delusions of grunge it.
At least I don't admit to them. But I just we've got to distinguish the ontological question
from the epistemological question. In terms of the reality of the situation,
there must be, in my view, a factor that matter as to whether something's conscious or
not.
And to me, it has rights if it's conscious, it doesn't, if it's not.
But then the epistemological question, how the hell do we know?
It's a mind field, but we'll have to sort of try and cross that bridge when we get to
it, I think.
Let me ask you a quick sort of a fun question assistance, fresher in your mind.
You are just yesterday ahead of conversation with Mr. Joe Rogan
on his podcast. What's your post-mortem analysis of the chat? What are some interesting
sticking points, disagreements, or joint insights? If we can kind of resolve them, once you've
had a chance to sleep on it, and then I'll talk to Joe about it.
Yeah, it was good fun. Yeah, he put up a bit of a fight. Yeah, it was challenging.
My view that we can't explain these things in conventional scientific terms or
or whether they have already been explained in conventional scientific terms.
I suppose the point I was trying to press is, we've got to distinguish the question of correlation
and explanation.
There's, yes, we've established facts about correlation that certain kinds of brain activity
go along with certain kinds of experience.
Everyone agrees on that.
But that doesn't address the why question.
Why? Why do certain kinds of brain activity go along
with certain kinds of experience?
And these different theories have different explanations of that.
You know, the materialists tries to explain the experience
in terms of brain activity, the panpsychist,
does it the other way round?
The dualists thinks they're separate, but maybe they're tied together by special laws of
nature or something.
Where's the second point?
Where exactly was the sticking point?
Like what was the nature of the argument?
I suppose Joe was saying, one look, we know consciousnesses is explained by brain activity because you take some funny chemicals,
it changes your brain, it changes your consciousness.
But, and I suppose yeah, some people might want to press,
and maybe this is what Joe was pressing,
you know, isn't that explaining consciousness,
but I suppose I want to say, there's a further question.
Yes, changes of chemicals in my brain,
changes my conscious experience,
but that leaves open the question,
why those particular chemicals go along
with that particular kind of experience
rather than a different experience or no experience at all?
There's something deeper at the base layer,
is your view that is more important to try to study and to
understand in order to then go back and describe how the different chemicals interact and
create different experiences.
Yeah, maybe a good analogy if you think about quantum mechanics.
Quantum mechanics is a bit of math translating there.
We say maths. I'm flipping iticking American. Thank you for the translation
America is America
Math yeah, why why multiple minutes it's plural so that's a plural that is not really it's just I don't know
The birds are confused. Yeah, sorry about that.
We have these funny spelling.
But anyway, yeah, so quantum mechanics is a bit of maths.
And the equations work really well, predicts the outcomes.
But then there's a further question.
What's going on in reality to make that equation predict
correctly? And some physicists want to say, shut up. what's going on in reality to make that equation predict correctly.
And some physicists want to say, shut up.
Just it works.
The shut up and calculate approach.
Similarly in consciousness, you know, I think
it's one question trying to work out
the physical correlates of consciousness,
which kinds of physical brain activity go along
which kinds of experience.
But there's another question,
what's going on in reality to undergird those correlations,
to make it the case that brain activity
goes along with experience.
And that's the philosophical question
that we have to give an answer to.
And there are just different options,
just as there are different interpretations
of quantum mechanics.
And it's really hard to evaluate, actually it's easy, puns like us, and it's really hard to evaluate. Actually, it's easy.
Pants like is him is obviously the best one.
But there's a illusion of grandeur once again coming through.
Sorry, I'm being slightly tongue in cheek.
No, I know.
100%.
Before I forget, let me ask you another fun question.
Back to Daniel Denet.
You mentioned a story where you were on a yacht.
Oh, yeah.
Daniel Denet, on a trip funded by a Russian investor and philosopher, Dmitri Volkov, I believe,
who also co-founded the Moscow Center of Consciousness Studies that's part of the philosophy department
of Moscow State University.
So this is interesting to me for several reasons
that are perhaps complicated to explain, to put simply that there is in the near term for me
a trip to Russia that involves a few conversations in Russian that have perhaps
less to do with consciousness and artificial intelligence which are the interests of mine and more to do with the broad spectrum of conversations
but I'm also interested in science in
Russia in artificial intelligence the computer science in
Physics mathematics, but also these fascinating at philosophical explorations and it was a very pleasant for me to discover that such a
center exists. So I have a million questions. One is the more fun question, just to imagine you and
Daniel Danna and I, y'all talking about the philosophy of consciousness. Maybe do you have any memorable
experiences? And also the more serious side for me as sort of somebody who's born in
the Soviet Union raised there.
I'm wondering what is the state of philosophy and consciousness in these kinds of ideas
in Russia that you've gotten a chance to kind of give us interact with?
Yeah, so on the form of question, yeah I mean, I had a really good experience of chatting
to Daniel Dennett.
I mean, I think he's a fantastic and very important philosopher, even though I totally
just fundamentally disagree with almost everything you'd think.
But yeah, he's a proud moment.
Well, as I talk about him, my book, Galileo Zera, I managed to persuade him.
He was wrong about something.
Just a tiny thing, tiny thing, not his fundamental
world view. But it was this issue about whether dualism is consistent with conservation of energy.
So Paul Churchill and who was also, he's philosopher who's also on this boat, had argued, they're not consistent because
if there's any material, soul, doing things in the brain, that's going to add to the energy
in the system. So we have a violation of conservation. But, well, it's not my own point, philosophers,
materialists, philosophers like David Papano have pointed out that, you know, Julius
Tenter, people, Julius like David Charmers,
who call themselves naturalistic,
Julius, they wanna bring consciousness into science.
They think it's not physical,
but they wanna say it can be part of a law governed world.
So Charmers believes in these psychophysical laws of nature
over and above the laws of physics
that govern
the connections between consciousness and the physical world and they could just respect conservation of energy, right?
I mean it could turn out that there are just in physics, you know that there are multiple
forces that all work together to respect conservation of energy. I mean I suppose physicists are pressing for a
unified underlying theory, but you know, there could be a plurality of different laws that all respect conservation.
So why not add more laws? So I raised this in Paul Churchill's talk and I got a lot of,
well, as one of the Moscow University graduate students that afterwards, he said, he had to
ask translation from his friend and he said, they turned on you like a pack of wolves.
Every woman was like a Patricia Church, she was saying, so you believe in magic to you.
And I was like, I'm not even a jeweler, so I'm just making a pedantic point that this
isn't a problem for jewelerism.
Anyway, but that evening everyone went onto the island except for some reason me and Daniel
Dennett.
And I went up on deck and he was very, very practical and he was unlike me. See, that's a bit of humility for
first time in this conversation. Well, highlight that part. Philip was a very humble man.
He was carving a walking stick on deck. It's very homely seed. And anyway, we started
talking about this and I was trying to press it and he was saying, oh, but Julius and
Zalena Nonsense and why do you think it?
And I was just saying, no, no, I'm just this honing down on this specific point.
And in the end, maybe he'll deny this, but he said, maybe that's right.
And it's like this.
So it's a win.
So what about the center for consciousness studies?
Yeah, I mean, I'm not sure I'd know a great deal to help you.
I mean, I know they've done some great stuff.
Dimitri funded this thing and also brought along
some graduate students from Moscow State University.
I think it is.
And they have an active center that tries to bring people in.
I think they've producing a book that's coming out that I made a small
contribution to on different philosophers' opinions on God, I think, or some of the big questions.
And yeah, so there's some interesting stuff going on there. I'm afraid I don't really
know more generally about philosophy in Russia.
Dimitri Volkov seems to be interesting as looking at all the stuff he's involved with.
He met with the Dalai Lama.
So he's trying to connect
Russian scientists
with the rest of the world, which is an effort that I think is
beautiful for all cultures. So I think science, philosophy, all of these kind of fields, disciplines that explore
ideas, collaborating and working globally across boundaries, across borders, across just
all the tensions of geopolitics is a beautiful thing.
And he seems to be a somewhat singular figure in pushing this. He just stood out to me as somebody
who's super interesting. I don't know if you have gotten a chance to interact with him.
So he's, I guess he speaks English pretty well actually. So he's both an English speaker and a Russian speaker.
I think he's written a book on Dennett,
I think called Boston Zombie I think.
I think that's the title and he's big fan of Dennett.
So I think the original plan for this was just gonna be,
it was on free will and consciousness
and it was gonna be kind of people broadly
in the Dennett type camp.
But then I think they asked David Charmers
and then he was saying, look, you need some people
you disagree with.
So he got invited me, the pan-psychist and Martina
Neidal Umelun, who's a very good,
dualist, substance, dualist, substance, dualist
at University of free-bug in Switzerland.
And so we were the official,
onboard opposition.
And it was, it was, it was was it was it was really get thrown off
But it's overboard nearly in the Arctic. Yeah, so sailing around the Arctic on a sailing ship
I'm glad you survived you mentioned free will you haven't talked to Sam
I would love to hear that conversation actually
But with some some harassed with Sam. Oh, yeah. Yeah. Yeah
What so he talks about free will quite a bit.
What's the connection between free will and consciousness to you?
So if consciousness permeates all matter, the experience, the feeling like we make a choice
in this world, like our actions, our results of a choice we consciously make
to use that word loosely. What do you, is the connection between free will and consciousness
and is free will and illusion or not?
Good question. So I think we need to be a lot more agnostic about free will than about consciousness
because I don't think we have the kind of certainty of the existence of free will that we
do have in the consciousness case.
It could turn out that free will is an illusion.
It could be that it feels as though we're free when we're really not.
Whereas, I mean, I think the idea that nobody really really feels pain, that
we think we feel pain, but we do that's a lot harder to make sense of. However, what I
do feel strongly about is I don't think there are any good either scientific or philosophical
arguments against the existence of free will. And I mean strong free will in what Floss was called
libertarian free will in the sense that some of our decisions are uncaused. So I
very much do disagree with someone like Sam Harris who thinks as is
overwhelming case. I just think it's non-existent. I think there's
ultimately, it's ultimately an empirical question, but as we've already
discussed, I just don't think we know enough about the brain to establish one way or the other at the moment.
But we can build up intuition. First of all, as a fan of Sam Harris, as a fan of yours, I would love to just listen.
Yeah. Well, I'm talking about terminate. So one thing that would be beautiful to watch my prediction, what happens with you and Sam Harris. You talk for four hours and Sam introduced that episode by saying it was ultimately not
as fruitful as I thought because here's what's going to happen.
You guys are going to get stuck for the first three hours talking about one of the terms
and what they mean.
Sam is so good at this.
I think it's really important, but sometimes he gets stuck.
Like, what does he say? Put a pin in that. He really gets stuck on the terminologies,
which rightfully you have to get right in order to really understand what we're talking
about, but sometimes you can get stuck with them for the entire conversation. It's a fascinating
dance. The one we spoke to in philosophy. If you can't,
if you don't get the terms precise, you can't really be having the same conversation, but
at the same time, it could be argued that it's impossible to get terms perfectly precise
and perfectly formalized. So then you're also not going to get anywhere
in the conversation.
So that's a funny dance.
We have to be both rigorous and every once in a while,
just let go and then go back to being rigorous and formal
and then every once in a while, let go.
It's the difference between mathematics, the maths,
and the poetry. Anyway, yeah, I'm a big fan of Sam Harrison
I think you know, I think we're we're on the same page and in terms of consciousness, I think
Pretty much I mean, I'm not saying he's a panseller, but in our understanding of the hard problem
But yeah, I think maybe you could talk about free will without being too dragged down in the time not bad at all
You said we need to be open-minded, but you could still have intuitions about
So Sam Harris has a pretty sort of uh
Cotter intuitive and for some reason it gets people really riled up
A view of free will that it's an illusion
Or it's not even an illusion.
It's not that the experience of free will is an illusion, he argues that we don't even experience
like there's to say that we even have the experience as correct, that there's not even an experience of free will.
It's pretty interesting that claim.
And it feels like you can build up intuitions
about what is right and not.
You know, there's been some kind of neuroscience,
there's been some cognitive science
and psychology experiments sort of see, you know,
what is the timing and the origin of the desire to make an action and when
that action is actually performed and how you interpret that action being
performed, how you remember that action.
Like all the stories we tell ourselves, all the neurochemicals involved in
making a thing happen, all of the, what's the timing and how does that connect with us,
feeling like we decided to do something.
Then of course, there's no more philosophical discussion about,
is there a room in a material view of the world for an entity that
somehow disturbs the determinism of physics.
Yeah.
And, yeah, those are all very precise.
It's nice.
It feels like free will is more amenable to like a physics mechanistic type of thinking
than its consciousness to really get to the bottom of.
It feels like it feels like a race.
If we're a bar and we're betting money, it feels like we'll get to the bottom of. It feels like it was a race. If we're a bar, we're betting money. It
feels like we'll get to the bottom of free will faster than we will to the bottom of consciousness.
Yeah, that's interesting. Yeah, I'm thought about the comparison. Yeah, so there are different
arguments here. I mean, so what one argument I've heard Sam Harris give that's pretty common
in philosophy is this sort of sort of, we can't make sense of a middle
way between at choice being determined by prior causes, and it just being totally random
and senseless, like the random decay of radioactive isotope or something.
So I think there was a good answer to that by the philosopher Jonathan Lowe, who's not necessarily
very well known outside academic philosophy, but is hugely influential.
I think I think one of the best philosophers of recent times, he sadly died of cancer
a few years ago, but actually spent almost all of his career at Durham University, which
were I am, so it was one reason it was a great honor to get to get a job there.
But anyway, his answer to that was,
what makes the difference between a free action
and a totally senseless one, senseless random event,
is that free choice involves responsiveness to reasons.
So again, we were talking about this earlier.
If I'm deciding whether to take a job in the US
or to stay in the UK, I weigh up considerations,
you know, different standards of life, maybe you're being close to family or cultural
different, I weigh them up and I, you know, edge towards a decision. So, so I think that
is sufficient to distinguish it. You know, hypothetically supposing, try to make sense of this idea,
not saying it's real, but that could be enough to distinguish it from a senseless site. It's
not a senseless random occurrence because the free decision involved responsiveness to reasons.
So I think that just answers the, that particular philosophical objection. So what is the middle way between determined by prior causes and totally random?
Well, there's an action, a choice that's not determined by prior causes,
but it's not just random because it, the decision essentially involved responsiveness to reasons.
So that's the answer to that. And I think actually that kind of thought also,
I think you were hinting at the famous
Liberty experiments where he got his subjects to perform some kind of random action of pressing
a button and then note the time they decided to press it, quote unquote, and then he's scanning
the brains and he claims to have found that about half a second before they consciously decided to press the button,
the brain is getting ready to perform that action.
So he claimed that about half a second before the person has consciously decided to press the button,
the brain has already started the activity that's going to lead to the action.
And then later people have claimed that there's a difference
of maybe seven to ten seconds. I mean, there are all sorts of issues with these experiments.
But one is that as far as I'm aware, all of the quote unquote choices they've focused
on are just these totally random, senseless actions like just pressing a button for no
reason. And I think the kind of free will we're interested in
is free choice that involves responsiveness to reasons weighing up considerations.
And those kind of free decisions might not happen like at an identifiable instant.
You might, when you're weighing it up, should I get married, should I, you know,
you might edge slowly towards one side or the other.
And so it could be that maybe the liberty, I think, you might edge slowly towards one side or the other.
And so it could be that maybe the libido, I think there are other problems with the libido stuff,
but maybe they show that we can't freely choose
to do something totally senseless, whatever that would mean.
But that doesn't show we can't freely
in this strong libertarian sense
respond to considerations of reason and value.
To be fair, it will be difficult to see
what kind of experiment we could set up to test that,
but just because we can't yet set up
that kind of experiment, we shouldn't pretend
we know more than we do.
So yeah, so for those reasons,
I don't, and well, the third consideration
you raise is different again.
This is the debate I have with Sean Carroll.
What would this conflict with physics?
I just think we don't know enough about the brain
to know whether there are causal dynamics in the brain
that are not reducible to underlying chemistry and physics.
And so then Sean Carroll says, well, that would
mean physics is wrong. So he focuses on the core theory, which is the name for standard
model of particle physics, plus the weak limit of general relativity. So, you know, we can't
totally bring quantum mechanics and relativity together, but actually
that the circumstances in which we can't bring them together are just in situations of
very high gravity, for example, when you're about to go into a black hole or something, actually
in terrestrial circumstances, we can bring them together in the core theory, and then
Sean wants to say, well, we can be very confident that core theory is correct.
And so if there were libertarian free will in the brain, the core theory would be wrong.
And okay, this is something I'm not sure about and I'm still thinking about and I'm learning from my discussion with Sean,
but I'm still not totally clear why it could be, suppose
we did discover strong emergence in the brain, whether it's free will or something else.
Perhaps what we would say is not that the core theory is wrong, but we'd say the core
theory is correct in its own terms, namely capturing the causal capacities of particles and fields.
But then it's a further assumption whether they're the only things that are running the
show.
Maybe there are also fundamental causal capacities associated with systems.
And then if we discover this strong emergence, then when we work out what happens in the
brain, we have to look to the core theory, the core's capacities of particles and fields, and we have to look to what we know about these strongly emerging
cause or capacities of systems, and maybe they co-determine what happens in the system.
So I don't know whether that makes sense or not, but I mean the more important point,
I mean that's in a way a kind of branding point, how we brand this.
The more important point is we just don't know enough about the workings of the brain to know whether there are strongly emerging causal dynamics,
whether or not that would mean we have to modify physics or maybe just we think physics is not
the total story of what's running the show. But we just, if it turned out empirically that
everything's
reproducible to underlying physics and chemistry,
sure I would drop any commitment to free libertarian free will
in a heartbeat.
It's an empirical question.
Maybe that's why, as you say,
it's imprinceable, it's easier to get a grip on,
but we're a million miles away from being at that stage.
Well, I don't know for a million miles.
I hope we're not, because one of the ways I think to get to it
is by engineering systems.
So my hope is to understand intelligence
by building intelligent systems, to understand consciousness
by building systems that, let's say, the easy thing,
which is not the easy thing, but the first thing,
which is to try to create the illusion of consciousness.
Through that process, I think you start to understand much more about consciousness about intelligence.
And then the same with free will, I think those are all tied very closely together,
at least from our narrow human perspective. And we try to engineer systems that interact deeply
with humans, that form friends with
humans that humans fall in love with and they fall in love with humans.
Then you start to have to try to deeply understand ourselves, to try to deeply understand what
is intelligence in the human mind, what is consciousness, what is free will.
And I think engineering is just another way to do philosophy.
Yeah, no, I certainly think there's a role for that and it would be an important consideration.
If we could seemingly replicate in an artificial way, the ability to choose that would be a consideration in thinking about these things.
But there's still the question of whether that's how we do it.
So even if we could replicate behavior in a certain way in an artificial system, it's
not until we understand the workings of our brains, it's not clear. That's how we do it.
And as I say, the kind of free will I'm interested in is, were we respond to reasons,
considerations of value? How would we tell whether a system was genuinely
responding, grasping and responding to facts about value or whether they were just replicating, giving
the impression of doing so. I don't know what I even have to think about that.
On the process to building them, I think we'll get a lot of insights. And once they become
conscious, what's going to happen is exactly the same thing is happening
in chess now, which is once the chess engines far superseded the capabilities of humans,
humans just kind of forgot about them, or they used them to help them out with the study
and stuff, but we still, we say, okay, let the engines be, and then we humans will just
play amongst each other. Right.
So just like dolphins and hamsters are not so concerned about humans except for a source
of food, you know, they do their own thing and let us humans launch rockets into space
and all that kind of stuff.
They don't, they don't care.
I think we'll just focus on ourselves.
But in the process of building intelligent systems, conscious systems, I think we'll get
a deep understanding of the role of consciousness in the human mind.
And like, what are its origins?
Is it the base layer of reality?
Is it strongly merge a phenomena of the brain, or just as you sort of brilliantly put here,
it can be both, like they're not mutually exclusive.
Dealing with consciousness needs to be an interdisciplinary task
we need, you know, philosophers, neuroscientists,
physicists, engineers, replicating these things artificially
and all needs to be working in step.
I'm quite interested.
I mean, more and more scientists get in touch with me, actually, saying that was one of
the great things about, I think, that's come from writing a popular book is not just getting
the ideas out to a general audience, but getting the ideas out to scientists and I would
scientists get into saying, no, this in some way connects to my work. And I would
like to kind of start to put together a network of an interdisciplinary network of scientists
and philosophers and engineers, perhaps you know, interested in a panpsychist approach.
And because I think so far, panpsychism has just been sort of trying to justify its existence, and that's important, but I think once you just get on with an active research
program, that's when people start taking it seriously, I think.
Do you think we're living in a simulation?
No, I think...
Is there some aspect of that thought experiment that's compelling to you within
the framework of pensickism?
It's an important and serious argument and it's not to be laughed away.
I suppose one issue I have with it is there's a crucial assumption there that consciousness
is substrate independent as the jargon goes,
which means it's, what?
No, right, be up to put.
It's software rather than hardware, right?
It's depend on organization rather than the stuff.
Whereas as a pan-psychist, I think consciousness is the stuff of the brain.
It's the stuff of matter.
So I think just taking the organizational properties, the software
and my brain and uploading them, you wouldn't get the stuff of my brain. So I am actually
worried if at some point in the future we start uploading our minds and we think, oh my
god, Granny's still there. I can email Granny after her body is rotted in the ground. And
we all start uploading our brains. It could be we're just committing suicide, we're just getting rid of our consciousness.
And because I think, you know, that wouldn't, for me, preserve the experience, just getting
them, the software features. So that's a crucial, but that's a, anyway, that's a crucial
premise of this simulation argument because the idea in a simulated universe, I don't think you necessarily would have consciousness.
It's interesting that you, as a panpsychist, are attached, because to me,
panpsychism would encourage the thought that there's not a significant difference. Like, at the very bottom, it's not substrate independent.
But you're going to have consciousness in a human and then move it to something else.
You can move it to the cloud.
You can move it to the computer.
It feels like that's much more possible if consciousness is the base layer. Yes, you could certainly,
it allows for the possibility of creating artificial consciousness, right?
Because then there's not souls,
there aren't any kind of extra magical ingredients.
So yeah, it definitely allows the possibility
of artificial consciousness and maybe preserving my consciousness
in some sort of artificial way.
My only point, I suppose, is just replicating the computational or organizational features
would not for me preserve consciousness.
But antifizz, some opponents of materialism disagree with me on that.
I think David Charmers is an opponent of materialist.
He's a kind of dualist, but he thinks the way the psychophysical laws work, they hook onto the computational
or organizational features of matter. So he thinks, you know, I think you think you could upload
your consciousness. I tend to think not so in that sense. In that sense sense we're not living your simulation in the sort of specific computation
of view of things and that substrate matters to you.
Yeah, I think so.
Yeah.
And in that you're guru, Sean Carroll, that physics matters.
Yeah, physics is our best way of capturing what the stuff of the world does.
Yeah, but not the what-ness, the being of the stuff.
Yeah, the is-ness.
The is-ness, thank you.
Russell Brande had a conversation with Russell Brande and he said,
oh, you mean the is-ness?
I thought it was a good way of putting it.
The is-ness.
The is-ness, that's all great.
The big ridiculous question. What do you think is the meaning of all of this?
You write in your book that the entry for our reality and the hitchhikers guide might
read a physical universe whose intrinsic nature is constituted of consciousness worth a
visit. So our whole conversation has been
about the first part of the sentence. What about the second part? Worth a visit. Why is
this place worth a visit? Why does it have meaning? Why does it have value at all? Why?
These are big questions.
I mean, firstly, I do think panpsychism is important to think about for considerations of meaning and value.
As we've already discussed, I think consciousness is the root of everything
that matters in life, you know, from deep
emotions, subtle thoughts, beautiful sensory experiences.
And yet I believe our official scientific worldview is incompatible with the reality
of consciousness.
I mean, that's controversial, but that's what I think.
And I think people feel this on an intuitive level.
It's maybe part of what Max Weber called
the disenchantment of nature, you know,
that they think they know their feelings and experiences
are not just electrochemical signaling.
I mean, they might just have that very informed intuition,
but I think that can be rigorously supported.
So I think this can lead to a sense of alienation and a sense that we lack a framework for understanding
the meaning and significance of our lives.
And in the absence of that, people turn to other things to make sense of the meaning of
their lives, like, you know, nationalism, fundamentalist religion, consumerism.
So I think panpsychism is important in that regard
in bringing together the quantitative facts
of physical science, as it were, the human truth,
by which I just mean the qualitative reality
of our own experience.
As I've already said, I do think there are objective
facts about value and what we ought to do and what we ought
to believe that we respond to, and that's very mysterious to make sense of both how there
could be such facts and how we could know about them and respond to them, but I do think
there are such facts and they're mostly to do with kinds of conscious experience. So there are there to be discovered in much of the human condition is to discover those
objective sources of value.
I think so, yeah.
And then, I mean, moving away from punts, I can say, you know, at an even bigger level.
I suppose, I think it is important to me to live in hope that there's a purpose to existence,
and that what I do contributes in some small way to that greater purpose.
But I would say, I don't know if there's a purpose to existence, I think some things point in that direction, some things point away from it.
But I don't think you need certainty
or even high probability to have faith in something.
So taking an analogy,
suppose you go a friend who's very seriously ill,
maybe there's a 30% chance they're gonna make it,
you shouldn't believe your friends going to get better,
because they're probably not. But what you can say is, you know, you can say to your friend, I have faith that you're going to get better. That is, I choose to live in hope about that
possibility. I choose to orientate my life towards that hope. Similarly, I don't think we know
whether or not there's a purpose to existence, but I think
we can make the choice to live in hope of that possibility.
And I find that a worthwhile and fulfilling way to live.
So maybe as your editor, I would collaborate with you on the edit of the Hitchhiker's Guide entry that instead
of worth the visit, we'll insert hopefully worth a visit.
Or the inhabitants hoped that you would think it's worth a visit.
I feel like you're an incredible mind, an incredible incredible human being and indeed are humble.
And I'm really happy that you're able to argue and take on some of these difficult questions
with some of the most brilliant people in the world, which are the philosophers thinking
about the human mind.
So, this was an awesome conversation.
I hope you continue talking to folks like Sam Harris.
I'm so glad you talk to Joe. I can't wait to see what you write, what you say, what you think next. Thank
you so much for talking today. Thanks very much, Lex. This has been a really fascinating
conversation. I've got a lot I need to think about actually just from this conversation,
but thanks for, thanks for chatting to me. Thanks for listening to this conversation with
Phil Gough. To support this podcast, please check out our sponsors in the description.
And now, let me leave you with some words from Carl Jung.
People will do anything, no matter how absurd, in order to avoid facing their own souls.
One does not become enlightened by imagining figures of light, but by making the darkness
conscious.
Thank you for listening, and hope to see you next time.
you