Making Sense with Sam Harris - #295 — Philosophy and the Good Life
Episode Date: September 9, 2022Sam Harris speaks to Kieran Setiya about the relevance of philosophy to living a good life. They discuss the existence of objective moral truths, being happy vs living well, our response to grief, the... difference between "telic" and "atelic" activities, the power of reframing, FOMO, bias toward the future, regret, the asymmetry between pain and pleasure, and other topics. If the Making Sense podcast logo in your player is BLACK, you can SUBSCRIBE to gain access to all full-length episodes at samharris.org/subscribe. Learning how to train your mind is the single greatest investment you can make in life. That’s why Sam Harris created the Waking Up app. From rational mindfulness practice to lessons on some of life’s most important topics, join Sam as he demystifies the practice of meditation and explores the theory behind it.
Transcript
Discussion (0)
Thank you. of the Making Sense podcast, you'll need to subscribe at samharris.org. There you'll find our private RSS feed
to add to your favorite podcatcher,
along with other subscriber-only content.
We don't run ads on the podcast,
and therefore it's made possible entirely
through the support of our subscribers.
So if you enjoy what we're doing here,
please consider becoming one.
Today I'm speaking with Kieran Setia.
Kieran is a professor of philosophy at MIT,
and he's the author of Midlife, a Philosophical Guide,
as well as Life is Hard, How Philosophy Can Help Us Find Our Way.
His writing has also appeared in the Los Angeles Review of Books, the Times Literary Supplement, the London Review of Books, the New York Times,
Aon, and the Yale Review. And in this conversation, we talk about the relevance of philosophy to the ongoing project of living a good life. We discuss the existence of objective moral truths,
Living a Good Life. We discuss the existence of objective moral truths, being happy versus living well, a response to grief, meditation as a remedy for psychological suffering, how to understand the
claim that the self is an illusion, the difference between telic and atelic activities, the power of reframing, FOMO, bias toward the future, regret, the asymmetry between pain and pleasure, and other topics.
I really enjoyed this conversation. I hope you find it useful.
And now I bring you Kieran Setia.
I am here with Kieran Setia. Kieran, thanks for joining me.
Thanks so much for having me.
So we have many shared interests. I loved your book, Midlife, a philosophical guide, and you have a new book, which I just have a PDF of. It's coming out soon, and I've just glanced at that. But I think we can
sort of merge the themes in both your books over the course of this conversation.
But before we jump in there, maybe you can summarize your background academically and
intellectually. What kinds of problems and concerns have you focused on?
Well, I'm a philosophy professor. I teach at MIT.
And my work on the sort of academic side has been about questions about the nature of human agency,
human knowledge, and broadly speaking, an ethics, sort of anything related to the problems of how we should live. And then over the last, I guess, five, seven years, I've been doing more outward
facing work that we'll talk about midlife and how it came out of my own experience years, I've been doing more outward-facing work that we'll talk about midlife
and how it came out of my own experience. But I've been trying to think about how the tools
of academic philosophy could be applied to the kinds of problems about how to live that
my friends and I seem to be facing and going through, some of which philosophers talk about,
many of which they tend not to spend so much time on. So the midlife crisis is one, and then in the new book,
life is hard, loneliness and grief and failure, and the kind of challenges that we confront when
we're living lives that are inevitably imperfect. Yeah, I've often marveled, and I'm not alone in this, in the marveling at the broken connection
between philosophy and the project of living well.
There used to be the whole point of philosophy, to come up with some vision of life and the
world that made securing as durable a possible form of well-being,
we'll talk about just what can be hoped for there,
and it was just intrinsic to the project of literally loving wisdom.
And that's the very concept of philosophy.
And then it became this far more abstract and arcane discipline where it seemed to want to emulate mathematics and science more.
And it became, following Wittgenstein, really just a kind of language game which viewed everything in terms of the parsing of concepts.
And I just feel like we lost our purchase on something
important there. I don't know if you share that feeling. I mean, I think there's a lot of truth
to that. Philosophers are often embarrassed by the idea of self-help. But in a way,
when you think of the long trajectory of the history of philosophical ethics,
the idea that thinking about how to live should make your life better, should enable you to live better, is a very attractive, plausible
one.
And that makes the line between moral philosophy, ethics, and what would nowadays be thought
of as self-help pretty blurry.
And they really only start to diverge in the 18th century.
You get philosophers who want to pull apart the project of understanding morality
or ethics from the project of making people virtuous, making people better. A lot of what
philosophers do now is relevant. It's closely relevant to practical questions about how to live,
and some of that people know about through things like effective altruism, so bits of philosophy
that are directed to the question, what are your obligations to other people? But the relevance
of philosophy is much broader than that, but it's very much concealed by the way in which
philosophy is sort of now formulated as and structured institutionally as an academic
discipline. And I kind of wanted to reconnect those two and bring them back into conversation.
Yeah. Well, that's what I loved about your book, Midlife, and what I know I will love about Life
is Hard. And in Midlife, you remind us all of three questions that Kant asked, which are really
foundational to the whole project of philosophy, at least the first two. I guess I have some concern about the third,
but the questions are, what can I know, what should I do, and what may I hope? And I think
you and I both have some caveats to add to the concept of hope, but what can I know that really
is all of epistemology, and what should I do really crystallizes moral philosophy and
ethics and ultimately even meta-ethics. In what sense can things matter and how do we solve this
navigation problem of life? In my mind, morality is pretty much always a question of what we should do next,
given the space of all possible experience in which we're navigating. And there's a deeper
question about how any claims we might make about what we should do relate to claims about what is
true and what is knowable. How do you think about just the grounding of moral truth in a larger set
of truth claims, the central problems of metaethics? Do you spend much time thinking about that?
Yeah, so I do. And I tend to be sort of sympathetic to the idea that there are objective
ethical truths. I mean, there's various kinds of lines
that get drawn here that I think, drawing which sort of I think played a role in the divorce
between say, philosophical ethics and self-help, like drawing a line between morality as concerned
with our obligations to others, and then ethics as concerned with sort of how we should live more
broadly. Those two, I think, are sort of interconnected in ways that make them hard to separate. And similarly, you sort of mentioned
metaethics. And there was a kind of period in mid-20th century moral philosophy where a lot
of philosophers wanted to say something about ethics, sort of metaethics, in a way that didn't
really engage with the question how to live. They wanted to separate the question of the nature of
morality from practical questions about what the ethical standards were. And I think there's a kind of
tendency in recent moral philosophy ethics that I think is right to blur those lines and to suggest
that we can't really draw those distinctions. And I think that sort of blurring of lines also
applies to the kinds of questions about objectivity that you're raising. So on the one hand, there's a lot of moral disagreement, a lot of disagreement in ethics.
And when we try to engage in ethical arguments, we often sort of come to loggerheads with other
people. And it seems like there's a kind of question about how we could know the answer
or whether there are really objective answers. And that can seem like a challenge to the idea
of objective ethical truth.
On the other hand, when you think about questions about what we know or what the standards of scientific rationality are, one lesson of thinking about determined conspiracy theorists or science
deniers is that if you insist on rejecting any premise that could be used to dislodge your view, you can maintain consistency
at the cost of an increasingly warped but internally coherent perspective on how the
world is scientifically. I think these problems about how do you actually persuade people and
how does our failure to persuade people, what significance does that
have for the idea of objective knowledge and objective truth are much broader than ethics?
And I think in both cases, the right response is to say something like,
well, dialectical efficacy, like being able to actually persuade people is one thing. But the
fact that you can't persuade someone who's a conspiracy theorist or a committed flat earther,
and will say anything
it takes to avoid internal inconsistency, that shouldn't make us think that that's a
legitimate view.
It's still an unjustified response to the evidence, even if it can be made strictly
logically compatible with the evidence.
And in the same way in ethics, I think we shouldn't be dissuaded from the idea that
there really are objective,
knowable answers to questions about how we should live by the fact that we find ourselves sometimes
faced with intractable ethical disagreements. That's not to say that there aren't differences
between the case of science and ethics. I think a kind of pluralism about the variety of different
good ways to live is appropriate in ethics, and maybe that kind of pluralism doesn't have the same role to play in our thinking about science. But I think that
the sort of questions of, you know, how do we know, what do I know, and what should I do are
sort of deeply entangled. And I don't think that there's a sort of, it's very hard to explain why
one should be skeptical about objective ethical truth in a way that doesn't
just eat up the whole idea of objective rationality altogether.
Well, you just seem to have argued for the thesis of my book, The Moral Landscape,
in a wonderfully concise way. I don't know if you've seen that book or heard me argue about it.
I do know the book. Yes. Yeah, yeah.
I mean, obviously, I agree with everything you just said. You made a point, which I make there, but you sort of made it from the other side, which
I find pretty illuminating.
The complaint I've often lodged is that scientists and philosophers do something different.
They do something with the diversity of opinion on moral topics that they don't do with diversity of
opinion on any other topic, which is to say they conclude from the mere existence of disagreement
that there is no ground truth to be known, right? So the fact that someone can show up at your
morality conference and say, well, I happen to like the morality of the Taliban. What are you
guys going to do with that? Basically, the conference just dissolves at that point because people begin to say, well, clearly, you know, it's all just
made up. It's all cultural convention. There's no, there can be no objective or universal claims
about good and evil or right and wrong because we've got the Taliban over there doing, you know,
cutting people's heads off at halftime of their soccer games, and they tell us that's
how they want to live. What are we going to do? But my point has always been, if you ask the Taliban
about physics or epidemiology, you're not going to get a lot of good sense either, right? The fact
that they have opinions on those topics is never read by experts in those fields as evidence of
anything other than their ignorance, right?
And so the idea that you can find an island of people who are living in some starkly awful way
by our lights shouldn't convince you, you know, on its face that they have an equal claim to having
thought through the problem of, you know, what is right, what is the moral
structure, if there is one in human affairs or in the larger affairs of conscious creatures,
and that their language game needs to be taken seriously the way the language games of our
experts do. And so it's just the fact that we just sort of throw out the rule book
of what it would mean to just try to push the conversation further into persuasion
and to also recognize that in every other sphere of life,
there are people who are unpersuadable because there are people who,
as you say, they're committed to some form of dogmatism that's causing
them to just change the rules of conversation on their side so as to be immune to any stream of
evidence or argument that would destabilize their worldview. We don't read into that when we're
talking to young Earth creationists. We don't view that as a real challenge to our geology or astronomy or paleontology or anything else.
Yet, that's not the feeling you get when talking about questions of right and wrong and good and
evil among academics generally. I think that's exactly right. There's this phenomenon or idea
that comes out of 20th century philosophy of science, mid-20th century philosophy of science,
of the underdetermination of theory by
data. The idea is, if you're willing to adjust your auxiliary hypotheses, you can always avoid
accepting any theory that seems to be supported by the data by reinterpreting how exactly the
observations were related to theory, or how they were gathered, or disputing the reliability of
such and such instrument.
And the standard response, not the only response in philosophy of science, is to say,
well, yeah, there's more to scientific rationality than just bare consistency with the evidence.
Just not contradicting the evidence is not all there is to coming up with the best,
most justified, most illuminating, most explanatory best theories.
And I think it's a puzzle to which there are kind of interesting historical answers why we don't take the same view in ethics of saying, well, yeah, someone can hold a consistent,
internally coherent, but abhorrent moral view, an abhorrent view in ethics. That doesn't mean
that there's no fact of the matter
or that there's no justification. What it means is, well, there's more to ethical rationality,
sort of thinking well about ethics, than just not contradicting yourself. Put that way,
it really shouldn't be that surprising that mere consistency is not all there is to
ethical virtue in one's thinking about ethics itself.
So I think the degree of disagreement historically and socially is maybe different,
and that maybe invites people to suppose that there's some dramatic contrast between
ethics and science. But it's really a difference of degree. And as conspiracy theorists become
more prevalent, the differences of degree
may start to diminish. Yeah. Well, the problem of persuading people about ordinary facts,
journalistic facts at this point, has become fairly excruciating. So the idea that it
remains difficult to persuade people about divergent moral facts. That's somehow
no longer surprising. We can't even agree about what should be on the front page of a newspaper
at this point. But that concern notwithstanding, let's plunge in. I think a good place to start is
the distinction you make between being happy and living well. How do you think about
those two concepts? Yeah, so I think this is sort of a kind of distinction that gets
drawn in various ways in philosophy, but also in ordinary life. So I think one way to sort of see
the contrast between being happy and living well and sort of asking yourself, you know, what is the object of self-help? Is the goal to be happy or to live well? Is to think about either there are
sort of abstract, wild philosophical thought experiments like people plugged into simulation
machines in which nothing they're experiencing is real. They're actually completely alone. Everyone
they seem to be interacting with is fake. Nothing that they think they're doing or almost nothing are they really doing. Many people have the thought, well,
that is not a life I want for people I love. That's not a good human life. That's barely
living at all. But of course, the person who's in that situation of deception and illusion
could feel incredibly happy. They feel great. If we think of happiness as the kind of subjective
state of mood or satisfaction, they have it. And what that suggests is, yeah, there's more to living
well than happiness. It's not that we should not care about happiness or strive to be unhappy,
but that's not really the goal of life. The goal is to live well. And that sometimes involves
unhappiness and the unhappiness that comes with confronting
reality. So there's also, as well as these wild thought experiments, I think it's something that
people are very vividly confronted with when they think about grief, where the idea that the pain of
grief and the unhappiness of grief and the sadness of grief among the other complex array of emotions
that grief involves, the idea that somehow, well, it would
just be better if we could get rid of that, that just doesn't seem right. The relationship between
the pain and suffering of grief and living well is much more complicated than that.
And I think that's a more general phenomenon, that the relationship between negative emotions,
negative feelings, and living well doesn't always make your life worse. In fact,
it's very important to living well to recognize when things are bad, to live in the world as it
is, not the world as you wish it would be. I think it's very important to frame the philosophical
project of ethics and the self-help project in terms of living well
primarily and happiness only secondarily. And one thing that does is to make clear that the
boundaries between oneself and others are much more porous. So when you start to think about
living well, part of living well is living as you should. And the question of how should I live,
well, it doesn't immediately tell
you how you should care about other people, but invites you to ask, well, if I'm going to live as
I should, how should I integrate the rights and needs of other people into my life? And if you
were just thinking about happiness, it might seem like, well, any connection between happiness and
caring about other people is contingent, and often caring about other people makes you vulnerable to unhappiness. But once you think, no, the goal is not just to feel happy,
it's to actually live a good life, you start to sort of break down the boundaries between what
we might think of as self-interest and what we might think of as morality. And I think that's
a useful way of sort of reframing what the project of self-help might look like if it was inspired by a kind of
philosophical approach to ethics. Yeah, there's a lot in what you just said.
There's so many intersecting questions and problems to sort out. I mean, so one point you
made about grief, which I find really interesting, and I think it at a certain point, it is going to be an actionable
use case for all of us that will pose some interesting psychological and ethical challenges.
And the way I've put it elsewhere, I think it might have been in the moral landscape. It
certainly was in some things I said while talking about that book. I just, I asked people to imagine
what it's going to be like when we develop, if we develop,
as seems pretty likely, a real cure for grief and bereavement, right? So let's just say we have a
grief pill that you could take and, you know, within an hour you will no longer feel sad about
that thing you've been completely brokenhearted over, whether it's the death of a loved one or the loss of a relationship or pick your poison there. If we had a cure for grief,
the question immediately arises, whether to take it ever and if to take it, how long do you wait?
Right. And clearly it seems like some kind of awful norm violation and even a break of trust with the person we ostensibly love if, while their body is still warm, we pop the pill and 45 minutes later we're out in an arcade playing video games, to date myself with an anachronistic reference.
But it's like it's the idea that the love of your life dies and that you would want to take a pill
which nullified your bereavement immediately, that somehow seems incompatible with love itself.
incompatible with love itself, of course, some real experience of grief seems appropriate and desirable. But then the question is, is there any point where grief itself becomes maladaptive and
no longer a sign of just how important that person was to you, but also a sign of a failure of resilience and a failure to
thrive and a failure to live in precisely the way your loved one would want you to live after they're
gone, right? So like at what point, at some point you could imagine a grief pill really could be a
necessary intervention for someone whose life has just unraveled under the pressure of bereavement.
So there's a half a dozen other things that occurred to me as you were talking,
but maybe we can take that case. Do you have any thoughts about that?
Sure. I mean, it's a fascinating thought experiment. I mean, in fact, there's already
a kind of natural experiment that prompts anxieties of the kind you're describing. So
the empirical work on grief suggests that
most people tend to be quite resilient, even in the face of loved ones that they were deeply
attached to. Often within six months, their lives are almost back to normal. That actually
occasions a lot of discomfort and anxiety, the sense that something has gone wrong with one's attachment, given how rapidly
it's possible to recover.
So even without the grief pill, we sort of have a kind of emotional immune system that
restores us to equilibrium much faster than many of us expect, and in fact, much faster
than many of us are comfortable with.
When you try to think through why that is, part of the answer leads to another puzzle
you raised about how long. Part of the answer seems to be, well, when you think, think through why that is, I mean, part of the answer leads to another puzzle you raised about how long.
So part of the answer seems to be, well, when you think, what am I grieving for?
Well, there's the loss of the relationship.
There's how bad it was for the person who died, the life that they could have had.
But there's also just a kind of recognition of the sheer loss of life.
And grief is a kind of rational response to that. In the same way as we have reasons for other
emotions like anger is a response to a perceived insult or fear is a response to danger or threat,
grief seems to be a kind of reason for it is a certain kind of loss. And the puzzle is,
well actually that starts to answer the question why we shouldn't
take the pill. The thought is, if we didn't grieve in response to the loss of someone we love,
we wouldn't be taking in reality. This goes back to the contrast between being happy and living
well. We want to take in reality, and in reality, we should feel grief. We should respond in a way that acknowledges the terribleness of that loss.
But then the puzzle is, hold on, if the reason for grief is just that my loved one is dead,
that's not going to change. I mean, the reason, that just stays the same, and it stays the same
forever. So now we face the question, the puzzle is less why should we grieve or whether we should grieve,
but how can we ever justifiably stop grieving? And there's a real puzzle there. I mean,
you know, when you try to describe how the situation has changed later,
you think to yourself, it's true, they died a while ago, and I've grieved for a while.
But those things all seem irrelevant to the scale of the loss. Those things don't diminish their loss in having died. So how can they make it rational to stop
grieving? And I think this is kind of a puzzle I talk about in the chapter on grief in Life is
Hard. I think this is where really what's happening is that our emotions respond to reasons. And this
is a case where if we just look at the object of the
emotion and try to proportion our emotional response to changes in it, we'll find that
there's just a kind of indeterminacy. We don't know. There's nothing in the object of grief
that tells you how long to grieve for. And this is, I think, one reason why rituals of grieving,
And this is, I think, one reason why rituals of grieving, practices of mourning, which are not rationally mandated, they take various cultural forms, are so important. Because what they do is allow you to grab onto something to guide and shape the process of grieving in a way that enables you to at least, in practice, get through this sense of the arbitrariness of grieving for a
certain length or others. And often what they have is distinctive temporal shapes. So you sit shiva
for seven days, or in ancient Roman customs, there were guidelines for how many months you should mourn for a child or a wife. What they do is precisely
try to regulate something that, if we just look at the object of grief, would seem unregulable.
I think that is a deep feature of the nature of grief and the way in which it responds to loss.
So yeah, I think we can sort of answer the question,
what would we lose if we took the grief pill by saying, well, we wouldn't be responding to reality
the way we should. And then we face this problem, okay, how can we ever justifiably stop recognizing
that loss for what it is? And we sort of rely on what are to some extent conventional,
arbitrary social practices to help us do that.
Yeah, that's all very interesting and useful. Although there's a mystery on the other side of
the continuum here, which is that one could ask how one ever justifiably starts grieving in the
sense that, and this has a direct connection to meditation and mindfulness and just the nature of consciousness.
I know you know that's an interest of mine because, I mean, just for instance,
take my present circumstance, right? I'm recording this conversation with you.
I'm alone, which is to say that no one I love is present in my studio now, they're never going to be more absent for me than they are now,
right? My wife and kids are, you know, I know them to still exist. I have no reason to be bereaved.
But the truth is, I also know that I am totally fine in their absence, right? So the question is,
how do I ever become someone who is not fine in their absence? Not only not fine, but how does their absence become synonymous with really the ruination of my well-being for whatever half-life that suffering has for me, in the case of everyone I love dying. And it seems like perhaps
a callous question, or at least a bizarre one, but in terms of the mechanics of psychological
suffering, it's a very real one, because the way we suffer is to think about the reasons we have to suffer in this case. It is a kind of abstraction,
and the thought, I will never see her again, meets out its punishment to you in the act of
identifying with it. And that's why meditation promises to be a truly generic remedy for
psychological suffering, because it's in being able to break
the spell of thought that one can recognize that consciousness is, if only for that next moment,
free of the implications of thought. And actually, I know from reading Midlife,
you have some concerns about what's considered the center, the bullseye here, the illusoriness
of the self, and perhaps we'll get there. I'd love to speak with you about that. But
the conundrum you posed about how it ever becomes reasonable to stop grieving, I do think is
actually mirrored on the other side by this property of the mind. How is it that it becomes
so reasonable to start grieving when in this moment, I know that, and you know, and any listener must know, that it's totally possible to not only endure the next moment of solitude, you can thrive in this next moment of solitude.
And how does that fundamentally change ever?
That's really, that is very interesting. And I think it relates to a distinction
I want to draw between different objects of grief and sort of the plurality of things that
grief attaches to. So a distinction I think is useful is between relational grief or grief about
the end of a relationship and grief for the sake of the one
who's died. And they come apart. So when you have a terrible breakup and the person hasn't died,
nevertheless, there's something like grief, the devastation of rejection and loss of a relationship.
And then when someone you love dies, there's both. You both have this phenomenon that the
relationship is now, I think, not really ended, but it's ruptured and changed in a dramatic way.
And then you have, I think, also grief for their sake. And I think part of what you're pointing to
is that if we focus on relational grief, the kind of relationship, you think, well,
insofar as I was capable of being happy in my relationship with someone in their absence. All I have to do
to get through grief is more of that. And so, yeah, why shouldn't I just sort of stay in the
mode of being fine in their absence? And I think that is a very interesting puzzle, but I think
it deals with one side of grief, the sort of relational side, the relationship-focused part
about, you know, I'll never see them again, I'll never interact with them again. And I think it deals with one side of grief, the sort of relational side, the relationship focused part about, you know, I'll never see them again.
I'll never interact with them again.
And I think there is also a dimension of grief that is not in that way.
It's not that relational grief is self-regarding, but it involves you as one of the two, you
know, sides of the relationship.
I think there's also grief that is just not relational.
It's just about the death of someone else.
I think there's also grief that is just not relational. It's just about the death of someone else. And there, I think, the issue of how you could survive their absence doesn't seem to offer consolation. The thought is, it's just a fact that they are dead, and the appropriate sort of emotional response to the enormity of that fact is to grieve, to begin this sort of complicated, difficult emotional process.
And I think that kind of sort of outward-looking, for the sake of them, grief, it's not clear to me that it's subject to the same therapy you just gave. I think the therapy for that would have
to be something much more radical, which would point us towards the non-existence of the self and more radical Buddhist ideas where the thought would be, if we could fully take in
that we don't really exist and no one we're attached to really exists in the way we think
they do, if that was really true and we could really take it in, then the thought might be,
well, the kind of loss that attachment would bring, this sort of outward-looking loss where
the value of something irreplaceable is just gone and you're sort of devastated by that,
it would be sort of answered by sort of denying that we really existed in the kind of way that
would make us fit objects of that kind of attachment. I mean, there are many puzzles
about this we could talk about. One puzzle for me is that it's never been clear to me really why the sort of revelation of no-self
isn't like sort of discovering that everyone you know and love, including you, is already dead. I
mean, it's itself a kind of devastating discovery. And in fact, there's this idea of mindfulness
meditation as a kind of therapy that is stress-reducing.
There's sort of empirical literature on that that's sort of divorced from the kind of insights
that Buddhist mindfulness meditation is supposed to bring us to.
But there are sort of aspects of the Buddhist tradition in which meditation of this kind
is not really stress reduction.
It's a form of stress induction.
The process is supposed to be one of confronting something very, very difficult. The non-existence of
yourself and those you love is a devastating thing to confront. What's true is that once
you've confronted it, you come out on the other side and you've, as it were, already pre-processed
the grief. You're, as it were, through to the other side of grief. And that sort of makes sense to me. What I feel like might be having it both ways
is a kind of picture of mindfulness meditation on which both the process itself involves stress
reduction and the outcome involves a kind of equanimity. I feel like that is the thing that
I find it harder to make sense of.
Okay, so maybe we'll deal with it now. I think there's some confusion about what is meant by
no-self in Buddhism or really in any contemplative tradition, certainly any of the Indian
contemplative traditions that spread east and north. So this is now encompassing all variants of Buddhism,
including Vajrayana and also Indian teachings like Advaita Vedanta.
Not to say that the adherents of all those traditions
think they're all teaching precisely the same thing,
but at their core, I think there is the same insight at the end of the day that is being described and entangled with various forms of religious belief and dogmatism,
and it's more or less mingled with helpful or harmful concepts to varying degrees in these various traditions.
But the core insight is that, well, first, we can mean many different things by the term self,
and not all of them are illusory. So it's not the claim that people are illusions,
or that you can't say anything coherent about the biographical or psychological continuity of a person, right? I mean, it's not mysterious that I wake up today
as me and not as you in a different house, in a different life, etc. I mean, that's not a puzzle
that anyone is trying to solve. And I do think there are very interesting puzzles around identity,
you know, a la Derek Parfit. But the real insight here and the illusion that is cut through, and again, it's cut through not merely
conceptually but experientially, is the apparent default condition of feeling like there is a
subject in the center of experience. Most people don't merely feel identical to experience. They feel like they're having
an experience. They feel like they're appropriating their experience from some point,
very likely in their heads, that is just the witness, the thinker of thoughts, the guider
of attention, the willer of will, the guy in the boat who has free will, who can decide what to think and do next. That's the
default state for more or less everybody, as far as I can tell. And it's a peculiar point of view,
as commonplace as it is, it doesn't make a lot of sense. It certainly doesn't make biological sense.
It's not the same thing as feeling identical to your body, because people, again, don't feel identical to their
bodies. They feel like they're subjects who have bodies to a large degree. I mean, they feel this
kind of a Cartesian dualism here that is intuitive for people. And this is, I think, my friend Paul
Bloom has said that people are common sense dualists. And I think that's true, and that does link up with
many beliefs about the divorceability of mind from brain and the immortality of the soul and
all the rest. It seems somehow intuitive that your mind must be something other than what the brain
is doing, and it may in fact be. I'm not actually somewhat agnostic as to how consciousness is
arising in this universe, And I take the hard
problem of consciousness seriously. That's a separate question. But as a matter of experience,
there's this feeling that I'm a subject behind my face. In some cases, certainly under conditions
of being embarrassed or you're being suddenly made the object of other people's attention,
I can almost feel like I'm wearing my face as a mask, right? I mean, the object of other people's attention, I can almost
feel like I'm wearing my face as a mask, right? I mean, you think of what it's like to feel
acutely self-conscious and to be blushing, say, in front of somebody. You know, you're at odds
with your own face. And so where the hell are you in this situation? You're the subject who's
thinking. And so it's that point of view who we represent. So now this
is sort of the totality of conscious experience here. We represent the world. So we have the
deliverances of our senses. We see and hear and smell and taste and touch. And so there's the full
set of our perceptions. And there's more to it than that. There's proprioception and everything
else you can be consciously aware of, your body in space. So there's the world, and then you represent your body in the world. But again, from the point of
view of the subject, your body is a kind of object in the world. It's out there to some degree,
and you're in it. And you, so then there's this final representation of being a subject
internal to the body that is directing attention,
thinking thoughts, willing its will, and vulnerable to the warp and woof of life.
So it's that final representation of the subject that is the illusion. And to put this in
neurological terms, you know, this is, let's just say for the sake of argument that all of this is just, you know, neurophysiological events in the brain and delivering these representations. It is
plausible, or at least should be plausible, that any one of these processes can be interrupted,
right? So you can cease to faithfully or coherently represent a world, right? You can
suddenly, you know, go blind, You know, you can suddenly not be able
to name living things, but still be able to name tools. You can suddenly not be able to perceive
motion or location. You know, those things break apart. All kinds of things can be disrupted,
for worse, certainly. But what these contemplative traditions have recognized is that certain things can be disrupted or brought to a halt for the better, right?
And the thing that really does, really can interrupt the usual cascade of mediocrity and suffering, psychologically speaking, is this representation of self as subject in the middle of experience. It is a kind
of, again, I realize I've been bloviating for quite some time here, giving you a lot, and there's much
more to say on this, but you can represent the world, and you can represent your body in the
world, and you can cease to represent a subject internal to the body, or cease to, I should say, construct a subject internal to the
body. And what remains in that case is a sense that the mind is much vaster than it was a moment
ago, because it's no longer confined to this sense that there's this central thinker of thoughts.
There's the recognition that thoughts simply arise all by themselves, just the way sounds do.
No one is authoring your thoughts.
You certainly aren't.
In fact, the sense that you are is what it feels like to be identified with this next spontaneously arising thought.
So you lose the sense that you're on the edge of your life, you're on the
edge of the world, sort of looking over your own shoulder, appropriating experience. And what you
can feel, you know, very vividly, again, this is not a new way of thinking about yourself in the
world, this is a ceasing to identify with thought. What you can feel is a real unity. And again, there's fine print here
in whether we want to talk about this as unity or as emptiness. My preferred formulation here
is non-duality. A non-duality of subject and object such that there really is just experience,
right? Again, I'm not making any metaphysical claims about how this relates to matter or the universe but as a matter of experience you can feel identical to experience itself right you're
not having an experience you're not on the edge of the river watching things go by you are the river
and that solves a very very wide class of problems speaking, with respect to suffering. So it does land
in a surprising kind of equanimity and even eudaimonia that may seem counterintuitive
in the midst of the cacophony of ordinary life. But it's there to be found. But again, it's not
the negation of personhood. It doesn't introduce all kinds of conundrums about
how am I me and not you. It's just a recognition that as a matter of experience,
there is just experience. And the feeling that there's an experiencer is yet more experience,
right? So if you drop back, there is just everything in its own place.
Anyway, so I gave you a lot there,
but that's my attempt to perform an exorcism on the concept of no self that you seem to be working with.
Well, I mean, I think there's something deeply right
about the line of thought you're pushing.
What I find hard to get in view,
and still struggle with, is this sort of sense.
If you'd like to continue listening to this conversation,
you'll need to subscribe at SamHarris.org.
Once you do, you'll get access to all full-length episodes
of the Making Sense podcast,
along with other subscriber-only content,
including bonus episodes and AMAs
and the conversations I've been having on the Waking Up app.
The Making Sense podcast is ad-free
and relies entirely on listener support, and you can subscribe now at samharris.org.