Modern Wisdom - #649 - Anil Seth - Does Your Brain Hallucinate Conscious Reality?

Episode Date: July 3, 2023

Anil Seth is a professor of cognitive and computational neuroscientist at the University of Sussex, co-director of the Sackler Centre for Consciousness Science, and an author. What is the Self? What d...oes it mean that we are the same person we were 10 years ago? Why do we have a subjective experience of reality at all? Is consciousness created or perceived? These are fundamental questions that philosophers and neuroscientists have been trying to answer for centuries. So can a new science of consciousness give us the answers? Expect to learn why answering the problem of consciousness is such a difficult challenge, why you wake up as the same person everyday, whether we know for a fact that animals are conscious, why perception often is divorced from objective reality, just how reliable our memories are, how to trust your brain even when it's incredibly fallible and much more... Sponsors: Get 5 Free Travel Packs, Free Liquid Vitamin D and more from AG1 at https://drinkag1.com/modernwisdom (discount automatically applied) Get a Free Sample Pack of all LMNT Flavours with your first box at https://www.drinklmnt.com/modernwisdom (automatically applied at checkout) Get £150 discount on Eight Sleep products at https://eightsleep.com/modernwisdom (discount automatically applied) Extra Stuff: Check out The Perception Census - https://perceptioncensus.dreamachine.world/ Read Being You - https://amzn.to/3ppLiIj Get my free Reading List of 100 books to read before you die → https://chriswillx.com/books/ To support me on Patreon (thank you): https://www.patreon.com/modernwisdom - Get in touch. Instagram: https://www.instagram.com/chriswillx Twitter: https://www.twitter.com/chriswillx YouTube: https://www.youtube.com/modernwisdompodcast Email: https://chriswillx.com/contact/ Learn more about your ad choices. Visit megaphone.fm/adchoices

Transcript
Discussion (0)
Starting point is 00:00:00 Hello friends, welcome back to the show. My guest today is Annal Seth. He's a professor of cognitive and computational neuroscience at the University of Sussex, co-director of the Sackler Center for Consciousness Science and An Author. What is the self? What does it mean that we are the same person we were ten years ago? Why do we have a subjective experience of reality at all? Is consciousness created or perceived? These are fundamental questions that philosophers and neuroscientists have been trying to answer for centuries. So can a new science of consciousness give us the answers?
Starting point is 00:00:34 Expect to learn why answering the problem of consciousness is such a difficult challenge, why you wake up as the same person every day, whether we know for a fact that animals are conscious, why perception is often divorced from objective reality, just how reliable our memories are, how to trust your brain even when it's incredibly fallible. And much more. One week from today, Chris Bumssted, the four-time Mr Olympia classic physique champion will be on Modern Wisdom. I went to Florida, I recorded with him a couple of weeks ago, it is the most beautiful podcast production ever in history. It is absolutely phenomenal. The conversation is two hours long. We get to go deep into his mindset, his training, absolutely
Starting point is 00:01:14 everything. It is an awesome, awesome episode. And if you don't want to miss it, you need to make sure that you've hit the subscribe button. So go and do it, please, on Apple Podcasts or Spotify, or whatever else you are listening. Thank you. In other news, this episode is brought to you by AG1. AG1 is a daily, foundational nutrition supplement that supports whole body health. Even with the best diet in the world, it is hard to make sure that you get everything that you need and through a science-driven formulation of vitamins, probiotics and whole food-sourced nutrients,
Starting point is 00:01:45 AG1 delivers comprehensive support for the brain, gut, and immune system. This is why Joe Rogan and Lex Friedman and Dr Andrew Cuban and Tim Ferris are all massive fans. They have tried every other product out there, like I have, and this is by far the best one available. Since 2010, AG1 have improved the formula 52 times in the pursuit of making the best foundational nutrition supplement possible through high quality ingredients and rigorous standards. Also, there's a 90-day money back guarantee, so you can buy it and try it for 89 days, and if you don't like it, they'll just give you your money back. Head to drinkag1.com slash modern wisdom. For that 90-day day money back guarantee a year's free supply vitamin D, 5 free travel packs and more that's drinkag1.com slash modern wisdom.
Starting point is 00:02:32 In other other news this episode is brought to you by element. If you're having coffee first thing in the morning, it is pointless. Your adenosine system that caffeine acts on isn't active for the first 90 minutes of the day, but your adrenal system is and salt acts on your adrenal system. Element contains a science-backed electrolyte ratio of sodium potassium and magnesium with no junk, no sugar, no coloring, artificial ingredients, gluten, fillers, or any other BS. It plays a critical role in reducing muscle cramps and fatigue while stopped optimizing
Starting point is 00:03:00 brain health, regulating appetite and curbing cravings. But best of all, it just tastes phenomenal. It's a beautiful, fruity, salty drink, first thing in the morning in a cold glass of water. It is my favorite way to start the day. Also, there is a no BS, no questions ask, refund policy, so you can buy it 100% risk-free. They have unlimited duration returns and they will give you your money back and you don't even need to return the box.
Starting point is 00:03:23 That's how confident they are that you'll like it. Head to drinklmnt.com slash modern wisdom to get a free sample pack of all eight flavors with any purchase that's drinklmnt.com slash modern wisdom. And in final news this episode is brought to you by 8 sleep. Temperature is one of the most important factors in improving your sleep quality. When you wake up in the middle of the night or feel extra groggy in the morning, temperature is almost always to blame. Traditional mattresses trap heat throughout the night.
Starting point is 00:03:52 Literally the job of the duvet you've got on top and the mattress underneath. Whereas by using an 8-Sleep pod pro cover, which just fits over the top of your existing mattress, it can actively cool and heat your bed throughout the night. It'll have different zones, one for you and one for your partner. So if you sleep cool in your partner sleep's hot, it'll fix that problem as well. It tracks your sleep. It allows you to get HIV resting heart rate, absolutely everything just through the mattress cover that you've got and it'll keep you cool.
Starting point is 00:04:18 So if you are sweating too much and struggling to fall asleep because it is boiling hot wherever you are at the moment, the eight-Sleep Pod Pro cover is the ultimate sleep fix and I am being kept alive by mine at the moment in Austin's ridiculous summer heat. Head to 8sleep.com slash modern wisdom for $150 or 150 pounds off the pod pro cover that's e-i-g-t-t-sleep.com slash monomistam. But now, ladies and gentlemen, please welcome, Annalsef. What is the real problem of consciousness? I think it's the approach to understanding consciousness that I'm taking and I think a lot of my colleagues also are, whether they know it or not.
Starting point is 00:05:21 The real problem is in contrast to the so-called hard problem. The hard problem of consciousness is this problem, which seems very hard, of trying to figure out how in the world something like conscious experience felt experienced, the redness of red, the sharpness of pain, how that is generated by or is identical to stuff happening in the world of stuff, matter, biological stuff. We're made of stuff. It's complicated stuff, but it's still stuff. How does that give rise to conscious experience? That's the hard problem.
Starting point is 00:05:58 Now we can try and solve it head on, but no one's managed to do that yet. The real problem of consciousness is, it's just like consciousness exists, some philosophers even would have us doubt that, consciousness exists, we all know what it's like to have experiences of the world and the self, and they're related in intimate ways to the brain and the body. So can we try to explain properties of consciousness, like what experiences feel like, why a visual experience is different from an emotion. Can we explain properties of consciousness in terms
Starting point is 00:06:31 of the brain and the body? And I think if we do that, that's addressing the real problem. And whether we eventually completely solve the hard problem or not, it's still up for grabs. But let's see how far we get and my suspicion and belief really is that by making progress on this real problem, then the hard problem will eventually fade away and just dissolve in a puff of philosophical smoke. What would an explanation of the real problem of consciousness look like? I'm trying to work out what sort of form that could actually take. It could take many forms and there are many different forms. They all kind of move us away from what the neuroscience of consciousness started like, which was finding correlations between things happening in our experience and things happening in the brain.
Starting point is 00:07:26 For example, a correlation could be your part of your brain, maybe your frontal cortex lights up when you consciously see something, but doesn't when you don't. That's a correlation. It's useful to know, but it's not the whole story. It doesn't give us a sense of satisfaction. We all know the whole story. It doesn't give us a sense of satisfaction. And we all know intuitively and in other areas that correlations are not the same thing as explanations or causations. Like I think there's things like the historical price of cheese in Wisconsin correlates with a divorce rate in France. Which is a fun fact, but it doesn't mean anything. Have you seen the correlation between, I think, it's the number of movies that Nick Cage was in in that particular year and the number of people who drown in their own swimming pool?
Starting point is 00:08:12 Well, maybe there is a causal thing there. I mean, that seems potentially... I can't believe that. ...cowarding so many on that case. So they're on swimming pool to escape the new Nick Cage movie? Yeah, I mean, it seems unlikely, but you never know. No, it is the point that correlations, we can always find correlations. And the goal is to move from things that merely
Starting point is 00:08:32 correlate to things that have explanatory and predictive value so that we can say, okay, oh, yeah, that makes sense. Why that kind of pattern of brain activity goes along with that kind of conges experience. And to make that link, that to go from it just does, to, oh, it makes sense that it does, we need theories. We need theories that try to explain why conges experiences have the character that they do. And there are a number of theories on offer. The one I prefer and the one I work with mainly is the idea that the brain is a kind of prediction machine and that different kinds of conscious experience are different kinds of brain-based prediction. And that
Starting point is 00:09:15 gives a language for connecting these two different levels. Why is being ourselves and having a sense of self related to a discussion of consciousness? How do those two things get related? We know what it's like to have this phenomenological experience of being a self. We talk about it. The book is called being you. What's that got to do with consciousness? Why is the self rooted in consciousness and how do they relate? I think it's central. And I think this is actually one of the side benefits, or maybe it's
Starting point is 00:09:49 even the main benefit of the real problem of consciousness approach, because even if we don't solve the whole mystery, it changes the way we think about the problem. And in science and philosophy often when you change the way you think about the problem, you change the questions, that's also progress. And so when it comes to the self, we might think that the problem of consciousness is really the problem of how we experience the world around us. There's a world around us, it has objects in it and has people in it and we experience them as moving around, having different visual appearances and so on. But I think for many of us there is a sense of mystery about what the self is. We might take it for granted and just think, well there's this essence of me, you might want to call it a soul or a spirit or something, there's this essence of
Starting point is 00:10:35 me that is inside my skull, that is just there and it's the thing that does the perceiving and it's making the decisions about what my organism body does. And that's all there is to it. That's separate from the problem. I think it's the central part of the problem. Consciousness for each of us consists in experiences of the world, but also experiences of the self, of being the individual that we are.
Starting point is 00:11:06 And if I think back and talking to a lot of people, actually, that's where the relevance of consciousness research often becomes most clear. So I think most of us at one point or another in our lives have wondered, you know, who am I really? Why am I me and not someone else? Where was I before I was born? What will happen after I die? Am I the same person? From one year to the next. These are very personal questions. And so when we take the self to be not the thing that does the perceiving, but an aspect of this
Starting point is 00:11:39 flow of conscious experience that requires explanation itself, then I think we're making progress. Yeah, I think when we're talking about consciousness, the non-muruscientist amongst us, it's the most front and center part of it, right? Everybody understands what it's like to have a felt sense of existing. They know what it's like. They go through these things. They know what it's like. Sorry, yeah, I mean, they know what it's like almost to the extent that you don't even think about it because your self is kind of always there. Your conscious perceptions of the world changes, you move around. And you might have different emotions, of course, and your experience of self does change.
Starting point is 00:12:19 But it's with you because it is you. So that might make it easy to overlook when you think about the problem. What is the cell? Is it a perception that we have of the thing that inhabits all of the different experiences we go through? Like what does it mean to say that we are the same person now as we were 20 years ago? That's a very complicated question because I think it makes sense in some ways, but not in other ways. And the reason for that is that what it is to be a self is not one thing, and the self is not a thing.
Starting point is 00:12:56 It's a process. It's an unfolding process that encompasses different kinds of perceptual experience. One way to think of the nature of the self for adult human being is to break it down into different levels. So at the lowest level, as you said a minute ago, there's this basic, almost unquestionable experience of just being a living organism, of merely existing.
Starting point is 00:13:23 And on top of that, we have emotions and moods. These are key parts of what it is to be a self. An emotion is not a perception of something out there in the world. It feels within. It feels part of me, part of us. And then there's an experience of the body as an object. Again, very easy to take for granted. But when you think about it, we experience our bodies as separate from the rest of the world. And there are many conditions where this isn't the case, people with phantom limbs, people with other kinds of conditions where their brains create other experiences about what is or what is not the body.
Starting point is 00:14:01 And then built on top of that, you have experiences of perceiving the world from a first person perspective, that's part of the self, experiences of agency and the, and what we would call free will, which is not what most people think it is, but it's still part of the self in terms of the experience of free will. And only then do you get to the, the level of personal identity, the level of the self where you dissociate a name, a set of memories of the past and plans for the future, and a social network, a social influence on who we are. So there are all these different dimensions of selfhood that are bound together for most of us, most of the time, in a seamless whole. But we know from lab experiments, from neurology, from psychiatry, that they can and do come apart.
Starting point is 00:14:55 So the self is complex, it doesn't have to be the way it is. And when we ask, am I the same person I was 20 years ago or will be in 20 years time? In some ways, yes, some of these aspects of self might be quite similar, but others may well change. And we won't notice the change necessarily, unless we have a sudden illness or something like that, then we'll notice because it's very abrupt. But most of the time, the self-changes slowly and smoothly and continuously. And so we are the same person, but what that person is, is itself changing.
Starting point is 00:15:32 Yeah, there's a sort of strange chip of theses thing going on. I think every cell in your body has changed. Is it seven years? Something like that. I remember hearing, it was a piece of breakup advice for girls that said, no matter how bad it hurts, don't worry because in seven years time there won't even be a cell
Starting point is 00:15:50 left in your body that was around when you were in a relationship with your ex. Which I always thought was kind of a funny way of thinking about it. But even with that, right? So that there is a person that is you and there are cells that made up you. But you are more than just the cells because the cells can be replaced and yet your sense of self continues. That's exactly right. I think it would be, it's kind of strange to locate the self in a particular cell or collection of cells, but it's equally strange to not do that, right, because then what is going on
Starting point is 00:16:21 with the disease? What is it? It's in the organization and the process. And this happens in other things as well, right? I mean, you have maybe a wetter system and all the different molecules of water probably change over time as well. And yet, the storm system continues
Starting point is 00:16:39 to have a coherent identity of itself. And the same thing, I think, is here. It's another version of the shipathesis argument. By the way, that's the old kind of Greek story, isn't it, where you have a ship and you basically replace every part of the ship with a new piece of wood here, a new piece of wood there, and you rope here. And when you've replaced every single part of it, the question is, is it still the same shit? On Trigger's broom, if you're British and grew up in the 90s. Trigger, no, you're shaming me now.
Starting point is 00:17:11 I grew up in, well, maybe I'm too old. Only fools and horses. You watched only fools and horses, surely. I'm Trigger's, I'm not sure. I'm Trigger's, oh, Trigger, sorry, yeah, yeah, but I'm with you. Trigger's broom. A famous example for the Americans listening,
Starting point is 00:17:23 there's this guy who's kind of an idiot that was a friend of all of the other people on this comedy show and he said that he was given an award by the local council for having used the same broom for eight years and he couldn't believe it and They said hey, I made it with the same broom for eight years. It's amazing. He said yeah It's only had four new handles and three new heads and Everybody looked at him. So yeah, Trigger's broom is the British British ship of Thesias. And that's why British comedy is so good because it's a philosophy lesson as well as comedy. Fuck yeah.
Starting point is 00:17:51 But yeah, this same sense of self, yeah, is it the cells? Is it the fact that you can just replace this? Is it the organization of the cells? But even if it is, does that mean that if I was able to recreate that organization elsewhere, that that other me would be me? What's no, is it? Okay, so is it the fact that I, as me, inhabited this particular location, these particular
Starting point is 00:18:13 coordinates and had these particular experiences that I related to with all of my other experiences continuously over time? Well, maybe, but what about if you're unconscious? What about if you're going to general anesthetic? What about when you're asleep? Right. but what about if you're unconscious? What about if you're going to general anesthetic? What about when you're asleep? Right, so there are all kinds of weird thought experiments one can play about the self and things that one can do in practice,
Starting point is 00:18:32 like Anastasia. You know, on the first one, if you recreate all the parts somewhere else, then what happens? There's a very famous philosophical thought experiment, which I do talk about a bit in the book called the tele-transportation thought experiment. And this is the idea that a future or maybe even present Elon Musk in his next business venture develops this tele-transportation system where you go in, it scans you at whatever level of detail you think is relevant.
Starting point is 00:19:02 Now, maybe the neurons, maybe every single molecule, maybe every single atom or quark, and it recreates an identical, materially identical version of you somewhere else, let's say on Mars. And the question is, okay, so this happens, what happens to you subjectively? I mean, you're in, let's say, I don't know where it is, London, you get in the device, I mean, you're in, let's say, I don't know where it is London, you get in the device, and then you are rebuilt in Mars, but at the same time that you're rebuilt in Mars, you are destroyed in London, like a whole bunch of lasers come and evaporate you, because we don't want an ex-continual explosion of people, it has to work that way. So you, going into this transportation system should probably just experience yourself one instant you're in London the next instant you're in Mars
Starting point is 00:19:51 or on Mars. And then one day there's a mistake the system goes wrong and the automatic lasers which would have evaporated the London you don't work and you're still there in London. And a technician comes in holding a gun and says, I'm sorry, you've got to do it the old style way, but the lasers didn't work. And then suddenly you have this, but hold on a minute, I'm still here. So what is going on? The temptation is to think you're either in London or on Mars, but really, you're probably in both places and this highlights another assumption that we might make,
Starting point is 00:20:29 which is another pop culture reference like Highlander, that there can be only one. The idea of the self that is indivisible and unique, and I think this is probably wrong, if you do have exactly the same material thing down to whatever level of organization, then you're going to have the same conscious experiences. So in this case, initially, there would be exactly two of you, one on Mars, one in London, but let's assume they didn't pull the trigger and you leave the system and you go wandering around. Of course, from that moment on, what it is to be each one of you changes and you leave the system and you go wandering around. Of course, from that moment on, what it is to be each one of you changes
Starting point is 00:21:09 and you start to become different people, probably much like identical twins, start off very much alike and then even though they're surprisingly similar over the lifetime, they still diverge because they've had different experiences, their brains change, their selves change. Well, I don't think that even interestingly in that thought experiment, no one would think
Starting point is 00:21:29 that the version of them that was scanned and the version of them that appeared in Mars, even if they managed to delete the old one and create the new one at the same time. I don't think anybody listening would expect for their felt sense to now be on Mars. I don't think that anybody would believe that they, their experience, would be one contiguous stream, and then they would appear in Mars. I think it would be... Because then, if that happened, and they didn't, you would be split. What would happen?
Starting point is 00:22:01 You would be experiencing two lives at once, like two eyeballs facing in opposite directions. I don't think that that's true either. I don't know, that would be a question you'd have to, there's a branch of philosophy called experimental philosophy where instead of making assumptions about what people would think in these cases, you tell them and then you ask them, so what do you think would happen? I don't know, I think that if you describe it properly, properly, then I think it wouldn't be... It's a bit like the other example that you use when you go to sleep or go under anesthesia. When you go under anesthesia, you lose consciousness entirely and you'll move from one room to another.
Starting point is 00:22:38 You usually wake up in a recovery room, which is different from where the anesthetic was administered. And most people expect to be the same person on the other side of that, right? And they're not going from London to Mars, but they're going from one part of the hospital to another. So what's the difference in that situation? Yeah, yeah, yeah. Yeah. Why aren't you waking up as a different person? Why, when you wake up in the morning, do you expect to behave the same way as you did previously? Yeah, because I think the brain has a very strong prior expectation that we are the same person. And part of that is justified, because not all of the molecules change overnight, and a
Starting point is 00:23:16 lot of the processes that shape our conscious experience and maintain an integrity, maintain an identity like the storm system, maintain its identity over time as well. But we're not exactly the same people before or after sleep or before or after anesthesia. And I think that's fine. And I think recognizing and reconciling ourselves to the ever changing self is is actually both scientifically and philosophically accurate, but also quite helpful. And of course, echoes a lot of what people have been saying in things like Buddhist literature and meditative practice forever that there's an impermanence to things and there's an impermanence
Starting point is 00:23:59 to the self and to identity. And we should not try and fight against that impermanence. Well, you say that it might be comforting. It may have also spiraled somebody into this sort of recursive self-sceptical thought loop that means they're now not going to be able to leave bed for a little while. So, I apologize if that's happened. So, moving on to how we and our consciousness relates with reality, you say that our experience of reality is that of a controlled hallucination. What do you mean by that? No metaphor is perfect, but what I mean by this is that our experiences of the world and of the self too, but let's stay with the world for now are not direct reflections of some objective reality, like as if the world was
Starting point is 00:24:47 just there and it poured itself directly into our minds to our eyes and our ears. It might seem like that, you know, we open our eyes in the morning or after anesthesia and it just seems as though the world is there and it has all these properties like color and shape and size and sound. And our brains don't seem to have much to do with it, but our brains have everything to do with it. And the idea, and it's not a new idea, is that instead of our perceptual, conscious experience of the world being a process of reading the world out in this kind of outside in direction. It's a process of active interpretation in which the brain is always
Starting point is 00:25:35 trying to make its best guess about what's out there in the world on the basis of sensory information that comes in through the senses but is ambiguous and noisy and it doesn't have labels on it. It doesn't have a label saying I'm from a red thing or I'm from a car. It's just electrical activity. And the brain has to make sense of it. And the theory, the idea is that it does so by basically having an internal model of the most likely causes of the sensory signals that it gets. And what we experience is not a readout of the sensory signal, but the brain's predictions about what causes those signals. And this is
Starting point is 00:26:12 a pretty big flip in how we relate to our experiences, because even though it seems they come from the outside in, they're actually, I think, coming from the inside out. And the sensory signals are there to keep our brains, predictions, our brains' best guesses tied to reality in ways that are useful for our behaviour as a complex organism. That's where the metaphor of controlled hallucination comes from. Illucination because experiences are internally generated. And when we think about hallucinations in everyday language, we typically think about something that's generated internally, rather than something that's registering the outside world.
Starting point is 00:26:56 But critically, the control is just as important. In normal, everyday perception, perceptual experiences don't just wander off into whatever they might be. They're very carefully regulated, controlled by the world and the body, and that's why perception, of course, works. That's why evolution has developed it that way
Starting point is 00:27:19 so that it's useful for us. Yeah, talk to me about how an evolutionary or sort of an ancestrally adaptive lens plays a role here. Why is it that we would have evolved this particular type of ability? Why is it that we would be making these predictions? What advantage does it give us and how does that work? I think it makes things a lot easier for complex organisms. It has to, maybe, especially so for complex creatures like us. If there were a one-to-one correspondence between some sort of sensory information and something in the world and what we should do about it, then we might not need any complex business of making predictions inside our
Starting point is 00:28:03 brains. But things aren't like that. Way back in philosophy, a manual can't point it out, or made the argument, that we can never perceive the world as it really is. We only perceive an interpretation as a transformation of it through a sensory veil. And sensory information that we get is not reliable, it's noisy, it's uncertain, it might come from different things, it changes according to the context, according
Starting point is 00:28:31 to the environment, according to lighting conditions. And so to get a reliable indication of what's going on in the world, it's not enough simply just a funnel sensory information into the brain, it has to be interpreted. And mathematically there's a way in which one might do this optimally, completely perfectly, but this turns out to not really be possible for things to do in practice. So this whole process by which the brain makes a prediction of what's out there and then use this sensory information to update these predictions, that turns out to be a very, very good approximation for how any kind of system would solve this problem of figuring out what's there under conditions of uncertainty. Why not just absorb what's
Starting point is 00:29:21 there? I don't know if I'm being thick here, but why not just observe it the way that it is? Why do this other thing? Well, take color, for example. Take our experiences of color. Now, when we experience color, this is a useful thing for brains to provide our experience with, right? Because colors allow us to keep track of surfaces, when lighting conditions change, they highlight things we might miss like the color of a ripe fruit in a tree, very, very useful. But where are colors in the world? Colors don't exist out there in objective reality. Anyway, there's just electromagnetic radiation that goes from radio waves to gamma waves. And our eyes are only sensitive to three wavelengths of that radiation. And out of those three wavelengths,
Starting point is 00:30:05 we experience millions of colors. So when we experience color, we're experiencing simultaneously less than what's there, because it's just three wavelengths out of a long vast spectrum. And more than, because we experience of millions of colors, not just three. So in this case, it wouldn't really be very useful for us to experience what's really there, because what would that mean? I mean, would it mean that we experienced a continuous, kind of set of wavelengths from kilometer long
Starting point is 00:30:37 to whatever X-ray, however long those are? So not even clear what that would mean to experience that. And yet, we don't even's not even clear what that would mean to experience that and yet we don't even Experience a small subset of that we create the brain create something out of the sensory environment that is very useful For us But you can put it even more simply like what's really out there? Is it objects or is it atoms or is it Quantum foam or something that really knows what's out there anyway.
Starting point is 00:31:06 So, to put as a benchmark experiencing things as they really are, is I think just to misunderstand what kind of business a brain is in. It's in the business of helping us stay alive. This doesn't feel, is it Donald Hoffman? Is that the guy that's got the kind of ideas that the world is very different out there? This doesn't feel a million miles away from what he talks about.
Starting point is 00:31:34 It is similar in some ways. So yeah, Don Hoffman has his idea of an interface theory of perception, which is that what we experience is some kind of user interface, which intervenes between how the world really is and something that's useful for us to survive by. We agree in the sense that the contents of experience are indirectly related to what's
Starting point is 00:32:02 going on out there in the world. But there are two places where we disagree. One is this metaphor of a user interface, I think, is problematic because it suggests that there's some kind of mini-me inside my head, you know, looking at this interface, as much as I might look at a computer screen and clicking on this icon or that icon, whereas back to the self, I think the self is part of the interface. There is no me that's separate from the flow of experience. And I think things that bring back,
Starting point is 00:32:33 that smuggle back in this inner homunculus is not the way to go. And then we also disagree, and this is something that I've talked to a few times about. He then also makes a whole bunch of claims about the real nature of what's out there in terms of little conscious agents everywhere. And I've not yet been persuaded by his ideas on that. I might be in the future, but I haven't been yet.
Starting point is 00:32:58 And you don't have to go that far. You can still just try to understand the nature of perception as solving this indirectness between how things are in the world and what's the best way for the brain to make sense of things in order to survive. I remember reading an explanation for an adaptive justification for consciousness and it included in that was the fact that as complex social beings who have to manage our own interpretation, our own status, who have to be able to model that of other people and how that other person is interacting with that other person and so on and so on and so on and so on. How important do you think the complex social networks
Starting point is 00:33:42 of ancestral humans has been to encouraging this predictive sense that consciousness sort of has? I think it's important, but I think it's important can be and sometimes has been taken too far. So we think about what it means to be an adult human self. We often put a great deal of emphasis on the level of personal identity, the me being and El Sethi being Chris Williamson. We have these identities being particular people.
Starting point is 00:34:12 And at the level of personal identity, the social aspect is very important. We have to differentiate ourselves from others. And we have to at the same time predict the behavior of others too. So, modeling the minds of others is absolutely key to our actual everyday behavior. And it may even be key to some aspects of what it means to be a self. So, it could be, as some people have argued, one of my mentors, Chris Frith has made this case, that the reason we know about our own mental states, when I have an experience, I don't just have it, I know that I have it, I can talk about it, the reason I have this insight into my own mental states is because my brain first evolved the ability to predict others' mental states. And it's that kind of theory of mind that then wrapped itself back into within the organism
Starting point is 00:35:11 and gave each individual a more elaborated sense of self. I think that might be the case, but I think you can go too far and say as some do as well that that's necessary for any kind of consciousness, that's why we have conscious experiences and that's why we have selves. For me I actually go right the other way and I say the origin of the predictive brain, the reason we have predictive brains is fundamentally because of the brains need to control and regulate the body. If you think about what brains are generally for, not only in humans, but in other animals as well, the prime rigidity of any brain is to keep itself and the body alive. And the best way to
Starting point is 00:35:58 regulate the body is to be able to predict what's going to happen to it. Prediction, is there any control engineer will tell you when you can have a predictive model of a system, you can much better control it because you can stop it going wrong before it even starts to go wrong. Like if you had a central heating system or an air conditioning system that predicted the change in the outside weather, you could keep the temperature of your house much more stable rather than just reacting to changes as they happen. So, for me, that is the fundamental reason why brains evolved this ability to make predictions about sensory signals. And everything else gets built on that, our ability then to predict
Starting point is 00:36:44 what the body is like to make perceptual predictions about what's out there in the world. I think it's plausible all this machinery rests on this fundamental imperative to stay alive. Eventually, social predictions become important as well. But if you want to figure out what's fundamental, I don't think we look there. That's very interesting. It's very interesting to think that it's not necessarily what important. You've done a ton of experiments that kind of show how the predictive, as opposed to the perceptual side of the brain, can cause people to erroneously predict, I guess. Could you explain some of your favorite examples of that? So this is one of the fun things about this kind of job, is that the experiments can be quite illuminating, but also entertaining. And this idea that what we perceive is a kind of controlled hallucination, begs the question, if we change things, can
Starting point is 00:37:46 we change people's experiences in ways that would be aligned with this idea? We've done this in a few different ways. So in one experiment, we wanted to simulate what it would be like when people's brains had overly strong perceptual predictions. So the control hallucinations become a little less controlled, you know, more little hallucination. And so let me say that again because I'm a little bit, so we wanted to try and understand what would happen if people's brains had overly strong perceptual predictions. So a little more hallucination, a little less control in the control delucination.
Starting point is 00:38:30 And we did this by using a neural network, the sort of thing that's pretty old hat now, given the developments in AI, but a powerful neural network that's able to classify what objects appear in different images. And we ran it backwards using an algorithm that was adapted from what Google called deep dream. We ran it backwards.
Starting point is 00:38:50 So basically, it just takes a category of object like dog, and it projects that back through the image to simulate kind of hallucination of dog. And we did this with a 360 degree panoramic video of Sussex University, and then we gave people headsets, virtual reality headsets to where, and replayed the video so they could look around in all directions and see what was going on.
Starting point is 00:39:16 And the result is kind of striking. It's a really immersive experience. And it's a model, not of what people do or how they behave, but it's a model of a different kind of conscious experience and The initial experiment was just a proof of concept. It wasn't really like any specific experience People said it was a bit like psychedelic, but I don't think it was and now what we're doing is making it much more specific So we're taking this proof of principle and we're developing it so that we can model different kinds of visual hallucination. So people that have Parkinson's disease have hallucinations of a specific kind. People who have visual loss have hallucinations of another
Starting point is 00:39:57 specific kind. And we can now begin to understand these differences in terms of different ways the predictive brain can go wrong. And by doing this, we can understand much more about how the predictive brain works in a normal case. Again, there's a lesson from engineering here that if you want to understand how a system works, you kind of look at how it breaks in various ways and that gives you a clue about what's going on in the normal case, which you might otherwise miss things that you would take for granted. So that's kind of a cool, I'm enjoying this experiment because it involves just modeling weird kinds of experiences and then going out and testing whether they accurately reflect
Starting point is 00:40:40 what people in the world with these different kinds of hallucinations really experience. We've also seen other sort of experiments where people have had the, is it Corpus Colossum severed and then you can do all manner of strange things with different hands, right hand being related to the left hemisphere and left hand being related to the right hemisphere. And you can do things where you show images to different sides and people have to put their hand into bags and select certain things out. How much is that related to this discussion of consciousness and how much is that just, I guess, an artifact
Starting point is 00:41:14 of the fact that we've got this crisscross brain body connection? I think it's very related. And it's still an absolutely fascinating area. There was a lot of, most of this work was done quite a while ago, because back in the 50s, 60s, 70s, when people had really severe epilepsy, there weren't that many options to treat it. And one of the options, quite a radical option, was this kind of surgery.
Starting point is 00:41:39 It's called a calisotomy, and it is basically cutting this big bundle of connections that connect the two brain hemispheres. It sounds incredibly brutal, but the surprising thing is that if you do it, it seems to have surprisingly little effects. People are pretty much the same. And you can only find differences in these quite weird situations where you show different information to the different hemispheres. And then all of a sudden it seems like something strange is going on and it's very relevant
Starting point is 00:42:11 to consciousness because it immediately raises the prospect that are there now two conscious selves sharing a single brain. That's kind of weird. And it's still a little bit unresolved. These days, one of the side effects of better medical treatments, epilepsy, is that these operations aren't done so much. And if they are done, they're not done where you separate all of the hemispheres. You usually leave some bits intact. Now, this is great medically, but it's kind of deprived of this wonderful, strange, almost living thought experiment of a split brain. And the story, as it is now, have a colleague, a former postdoc of mine in Amsterdam,
Starting point is 00:42:58 the Ipinto, who sort of picked up the chase and tried to do a lot of these experiments have been done in the 60s and 70s again. So like a classic experiment, as you say, would be you'd show a picture, which one brain hemisphere would see, and you'd ask it to draw what it saw, and then you'd ask the person What why they drew what they drew but having shown that hemisphere another word and So what's it's a it's a bit hard to explain it basically one hemisphere is usually where the Neural circuitry for language resigns usually the left hemisphere and in most most adult humans and so the left hemisphere Which sees the right visual field, can describe what it sees. But the left visual field, which goes to the right hemisphere,
Starting point is 00:43:56 doesn't usually involve language. It can sort of do other things. It can draw with the left hand, because everything is crossed in the brains. Where the left goes to right, right, go to left. And when you introduce a conflict, then the left hemisphere, which can speak, will often just make something up to explain what the right is doing or can fabulate. But it will be completely weird and wrong. And you have this uncanny sense that the left hemisphere is just unaware of what the other half of the brain is doing. Now these days it seems to be a little more finesse than that. These massive separations, they may be not quite so dramatic, they might resolve over time.
Starting point is 00:44:38 But there are still differences. There's definitely differences in how people with split brain operations, how they can integrate information across the whole visual field. And there is still this fundamental question about the unity of consciousness. Can it be divided? And what does that, what does that even mean? I find that it's probably not resolvable, but it just, it provokes our assumptions about what we are. I mean, again, we have this idea, just like the teletransportation experiment, that we are one thing and unique and indivisible, but there are all sorts of ways that the self can come apart, and this
Starting point is 00:45:18 is just one of them. Well, people have areas of the brain that are removed or damaged for a variety of reasons. And consciousness persists, perhaps their personality changes. So consciousness suggests at least in part distributed in some regard. It can't be necessary for every single bit of the brain to be operating the way it is for consciousness to persist. Maybe that person is somehow less conscious if they were to lose 5% of their brain because a railway sleeper or whatever railway screw goes through the top of their
Starting point is 00:45:56 head or whatever that famous story is. But does it make sense to ask the question, where does consciousness arise? Is that even a question that makes sense? It makes some sense, like all these questions. It doesn't make sense if you're looking for one place, the seat of the soul. I don't think it makes sense that way. But one of the most, I think, most informative aspects of the neuroscience of consciousness in the last 20 years has been to try and identify those parts of the brain that are more involved in consciousness compared to those that aren't, and it will change. It changes depending
Starting point is 00:46:35 on how you look, but there are some things which are relatively clear. One of the things I find always a bit surprising is that three-quarters of your brain, if you count it by a number of neurons, number of brain cells, three-quarters of your brain, does not seem to be much involved in consciousness at all. This is the cerebellum. So our brains are organized into these two hemispheres, but we also have this mini-brain at the back, are organized into these two hemispheres, but we also have this kind of mini-brain at the back, a cauliflower-shaped thing called the cerebellum. It is very important in controlling how we move, and maybe even in orchestrating how we think, the ability to do things in sequence and so on, but it doesn't really seem particularly implicated in consciousness. There are some
Starting point is 00:47:27 people born without a cerebellum, that seems absolutely fine. All the brain activity that when we contrast things like what happens when somebody loses consciousness or when they're conscious of something and versus not, it never really involves the cerebellum. So the mechanisms that are most relevant for consciousness are elsewhere, and they seem to be in the cortex, maybe underneath the cortex, so in the more frontal parts of the brain compared to the cerebellum. And here it's still just a big open question. There are some experiments and some theories.
Starting point is 00:48:07 And here I must feel, I must admit, it feels a little depressing that after this long and the advanced technology that we've gotten so on, one of the main debates in the field is still about whether consciousness is more in the front of the brain or more in the back of the brain. I mean, great, but it's a bit, it's a bit blunt, isn't it? I mean, that's quite a big contrast. And it's still unresolved. And part of the reason it's unresolved is there's one extremely tricky problem with studying consciousness, which is that we only know what people are conscious of if they tell us in some way, whether through words or through pressing a button or through some other way of reporting what they're conscious of.
Starting point is 00:48:51 And the challenge here when we look at what's happening in the brain is how do we separate what's happening in the brain that actually underlies what we're conscious of at any moment and what is just necessary for us to talk about it, to report it. And it could be that the experiments that say the front of the brain is critical, well, they show that, but actually what they're showing is that the front of the brain mechanisms are important for our ability to say what we're conscious of, but not for the conscious experience itself. So the last few years in this field, a lot of it's been about trying to get around that, whether it's through theory or through clever experimental design. It's a real challenge, but it's an exciting challenge because I think it's overcomable,
Starting point is 00:49:39 just not simple. Yeah, I guess it's almost like that section of the brain is a little bit more of the philosophical zombie. It is the one that is able to explain it but less so the one that is actually the experience of it. That that's a very nice way to put it. That may be the case, but then there are other people who say, no, actually those are the same things. It's kind of the ability to explain what's going on in another part of the brain, that is the experience. There are various theories like there's a theory called Hyrule to Thought Theory, which basically says that, that consciousness is in the act of one part of the brain explaining or looking at another part of the brain. But then
Starting point is 00:50:16 other theories would be the other way around. So given that it seems like there's varying parts of the brain that are involved in varying degrees to our experience of consciousness. And there are chunks of it that are the latest in terms of our evolution to develop that seem to be a little bit more advanced. Is it right to say that lower order animals in that case aren't conscious? Have you got any idea whether or not
Starting point is 00:50:40 other animals are conscious? Do they meet a threshold or a test by which you would be happy to say that they are? It's so interesting you mentioned test and one of the active projects I'm involved in right now is what do we even mean by a test for consciousness? What would we want from one and how might we develop it? Because it's not just in non-human animals, it's also in brain damaged people, it's in newborn infants, and it's, of course, in new technologies like AI and also neural organoids,
Starting point is 00:51:12 which are collections of brain cells grown in the lab. There's lots of areas where we might want to test for consciousness because, well, firstly, for moral and ethical reasons, as soon as something is conscious, it has some sort of moral status and ethical status. For non-human animals, I personally think, it's very hard to know for sure,
Starting point is 00:51:35 but this is a part of the problem, we can't ask them. But if we look at the preponderance of evidence in terms of what brain mechanisms are shared with other species that we know or have good reason to believe are important in human consciousness, then I think it's fairly clear that all mammals have some kind of conscious experience, even if they can't tell us about their conscious experiences. They share the same parts of cortex and the bits underneath the cortex, the thalamus that that just are very deeply implicated in human consciousness. When you get beyond mammals, it becomes harder because we don't have a consensus theory of consciousness that we can generalize to other things very easily. It's going to be a kind of what's our best guess. Now, what's the best thing
Starting point is 00:52:25 we can say with the limited evidence that we have. And here it depends on what kind of theory about the most important aspects of consciousness. If you think, as we said earlier, like if you think having a sense of theory of mind and being able to predict what other people, other animals are going to do is important, maybe it's quite restricted. If you think consciousness is co-extensive with something like intelligence or social intelligence, then maybe it's not present in that many other species. My dog doesn't know whether I'm going to go left or right or whether it's whatever time or this other time. But it might even, some people might even make a stronger claim that because your dog can't do that, it's not conscious at all. Yeah, precisely. Yeah, yeah, yeah,
Starting point is 00:53:15 I think this is, I find this unappealing. I'm not just unappealing because I like to think dogs are conscious, but I find it theoretically unappealing because I think that the roots of conscious experience are in the need for brains to regulate the body, to keep the body going in environments where there's a lot of information in their sensory world that pertains to how the brain regulates the body. So if you think consciousness is more rooted in this fundamental process of physiological regulation, then you're going to be more liberal about how many other creatures have it. And you might start to think, okay, it's not just mammals, it's it's maybe birds, it's maybe cephalopods like octopuses
Starting point is 00:54:06 and squid. I'm down for octopi. I'm down for octopi being conscious, man. I've read enough sci-fi stories about super intelligent octopi. What is the most commonly used definition of consciousness that is the barometer that most researchers in this field are using to work out whether a threshold is being crossed on it. So the definition doesn't really provide a threshold which is part of the problem. I mean the definition that most people use people use different definitions but a fairly good one comes through the philosopher Thomas Nagel, who says, for a conscious creature, there is something it is like to be that creature.
Starting point is 00:54:53 It feels like something to be me. It feels like something to be a dog, but it doesn't feel like anything to be a table or a chair. It's what makes a conscious creature more than just an object. That's the intuitive definition. That of course is just a description. It doesn't give you something that you can then go and measure. And the consensus about what to do and what to actually go out and measure, well, there is no consensus. It's a very febrile area of discussion.
Starting point is 00:55:32 It depends what kind of consciousness people are looking for. A well-used test in the sense of, that's been used a bunch of times, is the mirror self-recognition test. So the mirror self-recognition test asks whether an animal knows in some sense that its mirror image is itself rather than another animal. We humans, we do this naturally, we look in the mirror and for better or worse, we know that it's us. But this ability in humans doesn't appear at birth, it takes several months, it takes probably over a year to develop in human infants. What does this mean? It means that it takes a while for that aspect of self-consciousness to develop. It does not mean that consciousness was entirely
Starting point is 00:56:20 absent before then, it just means the aspect of perceiving oneself as a distinct entity. That might take quite a while and may be restricted to a few species rather than loads of species. At the other end, you might say something about responsiveness to pain. And here I have a lot more sympathy. So you can look at what animals will do when they are subjected to something damaging or all painful. And not just do they run away, but do they do the kind of constellation of behaviors that we associate with our conscious response to
Starting point is 00:57:00 pain? Do we tend the wound? Do we go to somewhere where there's anesthetic available? Do we change our whole organization of our behavior so as to aid recovery? I think this is a more sensible place to look. It might be a bit, you have to pick where on the scale you want to make, do you want to be overly conservative or overly liberal because you're not going to get it bang on. So in my feeling, pain is important. If a species, if a creature has the ability to suffer, then it's really deserving of a place in this sort of charm circle of ethical moral consideration.
Starting point is 00:57:45 Yeah, I was thinking about a snake and something tells me that a snake can't reflect, I can't recognize itself in a mirror, but if you stick a stapler into the side of it, it's probably going to know. It's going to know, for sure. Yeah, I don't know. I have actually no idea whether anyone's done the mirror self-recognition test on a snake. I mean, this is also part of the problem. These experiments are quite hard to do and we've only studied a handful of species with any sort of stage to draw. Get a snake, get a mirror, stick it on the floor. You know what I mean?
Starting point is 00:58:20 Well, you know, you say not hard to do, but you have to do it several times. And also, there's many reasons why animals fail this test. Like, many animals don't like to make eye contact. And some don't like mirrors. So they're just going to fail this test for reasons for other reasons. So even then, you don't know how to interpret the results. I was thinking, as you were explaining the mirror self-recognition test, I was thinking about bats of voles that have got particularly poor eyesight, basically no eyesight, or what
Starting point is 00:58:54 about an animal who's had both of its eyes damaged? If it's never able to detect itself, does that mean that it's no longer conscious? Again, like... Yeah, probably not, right? I mean, that was Thomas Nagel's point in his his paper where we where the definition of consciousness came for on that we we've been talking about his paper was what is it like to be a bat and it's a very interesting thought experiment because bats of course have a co-location we don't have anything like a co-location and So it will be impossible for us to experience being a bat unless you actually are a bat with the potential exception of not Batman, but there's this there's a few people who have
Starting point is 00:59:35 developed so-called human echo location. So people who've gone blind, who are born blinds, and have developed the ability to make clicking sounds and perceive the layout of their environment through processing the echoes to these clicking sounds. I find this really, really interesting. It's, you know, we are brains that involve to do this, so it's not going to be as good as a bat, not as good as a bat, but it's the closest that we might be able to get. The weirdest first date that I ever went on was it, I think it's called cafe noir in London. Have you heard of this?
Starting point is 01:00:17 Is this where they serve food in total darkness? Correct. And it's only blind servers. Now I think that rather than using echo location, the servers have just memorized the rooms layout incredibly well. But, you know, my bedroom, I tried to go to the bathroom last night without turning the light on so it wouldn't ruin my sleep, and I crashed into something. I've been in that room, you know, hundreds of times. So, I've been in that room hundreds of times. So there is some part of their spatial awareness,
Starting point is 01:00:48 their proprioception, which has been tuned up for them to be able to carry plates through a room with tons of people in, all talking, and not drop it on the wrong person. And remember where they're going, find the person of where they're going, et cetera, et cetera. But yet, that was the first day. I don't know what it says that this girl decided to take me into a room where she literally couldn't see me.
Starting point is 01:01:10 I'm not really too sure what that says about our first day, but it was really fun, actually. And I remember thinking at the time, there's something going on here. There is something that has happened to allow these people to compensate for. Is it? Yeah, it's fascinating. And the thing is, I know know your example of you kind of stumble around in the darkness trying to find a bathroom
Starting point is 01:01:30 but you know if you if you adapted to it if you gave yourself time and you can do surprisingly well picking up just these very subtle cues out there and if you think about these waiters in cafe noir there. And if you think about these weighters in cafe noir, imagine like how much better you get at moving around in the dark after just trying to do it for an hour and then just imagine that they've done it for a lifetime. Maybe it's not so surprising that they're really good. But about the mirror thing, I mean, it's true that we tend to overemphasize or we tend to strongly emphasize visual stuff as humans. We feel we're very visual creatures. And again, that bias may lead us astray
Starting point is 01:02:10 when thinking about other animals. The mirror self-recognition test seems to be a visual test, but there are some researchers looking, for instance, didn't even go to bats, you go to dogs, dogs, they have vision, of course, but for dogs, smell, all-faction is so much more important. So there are people trying to develop an all-factory mirror test for a dog, and I'm not, don't ask me quite how it works, I have no idea exactly what they do, but I like the point that you have to try and understand the ecological niche, or as there's a German philosopher, psychologist, Jacob von Erkskul, he came up with this concept
Starting point is 01:02:58 of the umwelto, the kind of lived world of another animal. So if you were a bat, your world is suff world is suffused by a co-locatory signal. So you kind of would have a sense of where things are that wouldn't be visual, but it would be like having radar or something like that. And then bees have another unveiled entirely where the light reflects it from in the UV or infrared becomes very prominent.
Starting point is 01:03:24 And I think this is a wonderful book by Ed Yong called An immense World, which really highlights that it seems as if we're sharing the same world, but if you have a human, a mouse, a bat, an elephant, all in the same space and assume they're all conscious and ask, well, if they are conscious, what would their experiences be like? Their experiences are so different. Well, I suppose what's interesting about that example of having a number of different animals within the same environment. And then let's say that it's a maze or they just need to go about and do the normal thing. They need to maybe find some food and some water
Starting point is 01:04:02 and do the rest of it. From the outside, you can observe behavior which looks like it could be coming from the same place. Because the net outcome of their behavior is the same. It may do it in different ways, but the now outcome is that they eventually find some food and they find some water and they go in shade when it's hot and they go into sunlight when it's cold and blah, blah, blah. But internally, when it's hot and they go into sunlight when it's cold and blah blah blah. But internally, how each of those animals arrives at the thing that it's doing to track down the food, the human may heavily rely on its visual field, the dog may heavily rely on its olfactory senses, the mouse may use, if it was a bee, the bee would have ultraviolet light. So, okay, you're able to produce behavior, which
Starting point is 01:04:50 is not only adaptive and useful, but from the outside might not look all that different, and yet the root at which each animal got to it is completely different. Well, that's linger on that for a second. I think there's something worth unpacking here, because in this example, a mosquito, an elephant, a human, it sounds like a bad joke, doesn't it, go into a bar. And they're all in the same bar. And I think in this case, the behaviors are quite different. Like in a mosquito, we'll detect levels of carbon dioxide and be able to use that to find skin. I think that's what they're sensitive to.
Starting point is 01:05:29 I can't remember now, but they'll be sensitive to very different kinds of things and we'll do things that seem a bit uncanny. Like, move around in the dark. Myce was so sensitive in their hearing and sense of vibration that they'd be able to run away owls can hear things at such a vast distance, that the behaviors would be different. And so it's maybe easy to recognize that the perceptual world, the unveil to these creatures
Starting point is 01:05:54 would also be different to ours. I think where we might make mistakes is actually within a species. So if you have a bunch of people in this room, in a room, and they're all interacting with each other, then you're right, they may all do the same sort of thing. They may all look for food, they may all go from to the shade when it's hot and so on.
Starting point is 01:06:20 And just in general, in our everyday lives, we tend to expect people to behave in a way that we might behave, and it more or less. And so it's very easy, then, to assume that other people experience the world the same way we do, because their behaviors might be relatively consistent compared to the difference between me and a mosquito. But I think this is a mistaken assumption. It seems to us we see the world as it is, and we use the same words often to describe things like I see a red car, you see a red car, we both say it as a red car. And so we assume then that we're having the same internal experience of this shared objective reality.
Starting point is 01:07:11 And I don't think that's true. In fact, I know it's not true. In fact, this is not a new thing to say. There's plenty of evidence out there of people who experience the world in very different ways in it, that have hallucinations and so on. Have synesthesia when people see colors when they hear sounds and mixing of the senses. And of course, there's the whole
Starting point is 01:07:31 area of neurodiversity, which really highlights that there are substantial differences in how different people encounter a shared world. But I think we still underestimate what's going on because of the moment, unless we are hallucinating or unless we associate ourselves with a neurodivergent condition like autism or something like that, it's easy to assume that we're neurotypical and we experience the world just as it is. And I don't think there is such a thing. I think that we all differ. And understanding that, unpacking that, I think is a great challenge because we know the importance of taking into account and actually really relishing, relishing. I'm trying to think of the right word here. Not just taking to account,
Starting point is 01:08:25 but recognizing the value of diversity that we can see on the outside, you know, diversity and cultural background and body shape, size and so on. But we also have this in a diversity. And it's, if we don't recognize that it's there because we use the same words and it seems as though we see things as they are, I think we're losing an opportunity to benefit from a diversity of ways of perceiving, of ways of seeing things. And this is a, this is a, sorry, it's a very long-winded way of mentioning that we have a project at the moment called the Perception Census, which is trying to do exactly this. It's a big citizen science project where we ask people to join in and do a bunch of pretty
Starting point is 01:09:17 simple and fun little interactive visual illusions and so on, to try and help us get a picture of perceptual diversity to map out this hidden landscape of inner variation. And it's online, it's all you need is a computer and you can- Like can people go if they want to try this up? If they just look for perception census, just type that into Google or go through my website, just look for analcet.com and take you straight there. And you can do a little bit, you can set it aside, come back, and we'll keep track of your progress. And you'll learn a lot about perception and your own particular way of perceiving the
Starting point is 01:09:54 world. We've already had about 26,000 people try it now and from 100 countries. So we want to make this a real landmark study, both to map out this perceptual diversity, but also to raise awareness that it's actually there. And I think that will be of quite a significant social value. Talking about perception. What happened when you took LSD? Quite a lot.
Starting point is 01:10:20 I mean, I didn't take LSD until I was in my 40s. I didn't have the opportunity or probably the desire when I was a teenager in South Oxfordshire. And at some point, it seemed like the right thing to do. I guess I really wanted to know what it was like from the first person. And I'm thinking about consciousness a lot. For me, it doesn't do this for every researcher in this area,
Starting point is 01:10:46 but for me, maybe very curious about what kinds of conscious experiences are available, because part of the whole motivation for me is understanding what we take for granted in our own experience, because it's always been now, it's always been some particular way and not another way. So ways to get out of the perceptual habits that we're in, I think, can be very illuminating and there are many ways to do this. There's meditation, there's jumping out of the plane, there's all sorts of things, right? But psychedelics is one obvious way and really reliable. It's very reliable and it's reliably substantial. You just know, well, this is what I was expecting and this is what I'd been told and in fact, this is true, right?
Starting point is 01:11:35 You put a little tab on your tongue and under your tongue and then stuff will happen. And it will happen for a while. And I think I was both reassured and surprised. And the way to explain that is nothing happened that I didn't expect to happen but the fact it was happening to me was still surprising. And what it involved was large changes in my perceptual environment. Things became much more fluid, things became much more changeable. There seemed to be this influence that I could have over what I was perceiving by almost willing clouds to change into things they did,
Starting point is 01:12:26 things started to bleed together, and things became imbued with this sort of sense of quite magic. There would be this quality to the whole environment that changed. And of course the sense of self-change as well. And it's very, it's notoriously hard to describe these kinds of experiences without sounding entirely naff. I think Michael Pollan has done a good job in his book, How to Change Your Mind. Well, if Aldous Huxley, you know, if we have to call on one of the greatest words, Smith's
Starting point is 01:12:56 of all time, to try and tell us what he thinks in Dozer perception, then, yeah. Yeah, it's hard. And I don't want to to Mangle these things and rather just appeal to these kinds of authorities, but but it was it was You know, I've been prepared to be disappointed I think about okay. It's it's well that wasn't quite as transformational as I've been hoping for but it was I was not I was not disappointed and It is it is remarkable. I think the other thing that it's interesting that, for me, it just reinforced the idea that I went in with that our conscious experiences are biological phenomena. In the same way that anesthesia did. Anesthesia anesthesia for me shows that you can, if you change the brain in a very specific way, you change consciousness in a very reliable, predictable, specific way as well. With anesthesia, it goes away and then comes back.
Starting point is 01:13:56 With psychedelics, again, you're intervening in the system in a very precise and very specific way and your conscious experience changes. In a very, you know, the details may vary, but the overall trajectory of what's happening is very predictable. Yeah, so the implication here is that if consciousness wasn't something which is, as you had predicted, it shouldn't be able to be impeded or imposed on by these sorts of substances. You shouldn't reliably be able to change it because it should be something which is outside of the changeable. It's interesting because some people would take entirely the opposite conclusion and
Starting point is 01:14:40 the fact that a psychedelic experience may give you a sense that you, you're outside of your body, or that yourself as part of the universe, may take these experiences at face value and reach the conclusion that their normal conscious experience is some kind of heavily filtered down version of the... This is the perturbed version of the molested perverse version of what is true. It always happens to be that what is true involves psychedelics. It's never what is true is your mind when you're sat on the toilet. It's never that state. It's always a state of sort of psychedelic bliss.
Starting point is 01:15:19 Yeah, and that's one way you can go. And you can say, now I've seen things as they really are. The blinkers are off. the filters have been removed. That for me is not an appealing way to think about it. It is for me. It is, yeah, you change your brain, you change your experience. It's exactly what you would expect to happen if our conscious experiences were embodied
Starting point is 01:15:42 biological phenomena. Moving beyond just your research, how has all of the work that you've done into the nature of self changed about how you think about problems or deal with the challenges and the joys of life? Have you found that it's sort of impacted the way that you relate to emotions? It's one of the things we haven't necessarily mentioned is emotions for all that they may be this phenomenon that exists and they're kind of there or there and not there at the same time. They feel incredibly real. They feel like the most real thing that you can think of, you know, going through anxiety. It's the reason why the Greeks and the Romans personified the gods, right? Because it felt like something, it was such a visceral experience
Starting point is 01:16:31 that it could only be bestowed on you by a higher power that was cursing or blessing you specifically. And I'm interested in how all of this time thinking about the nature of self and consciousness has changed your relationship with your enjoyable and unenjoyable experience of it. Yeah, emotions, they're definitely real as experiences and they're probably the most important experiences we have. I mean, they're what matters. And they guide and direct our behavior every minute of every day.
Starting point is 01:17:03 They're real in the same way that colors are real, I think. They don't exist out there independently of a mind, but they are critical to our mental lives. In my work, I think of that connection even more tightly. So an emotion for me is another kind of perception. It's a perception of the state of the body in the context in which we're in. It's a perceptual inference about what's happening in the body. And so they're very tightly coupled. And thinking about this a lot, it's always a challenging question to try and understand what its impact has been on me personally, partly because I don't have a twin brother who went off to be in a state agent to
Starting point is 01:17:51 compare against. But I think it has had an effect. However unreliable that introspective conclusion might be. And I mean, I can kind of see it. maybe it's just getting older as well, but I can kind of see that I'm a bit more adaptively detached from the transient flow of emotions than I was. Not entirely. I mean, I'm not claiming to be some sort of enlightened monk. I mean, I still feel frustrated, anxious, sad, upset, for furious at times, happy to sometimes. Now, the flow of emotions is still there, but I think it has helped me in the round to navigate things more effectively.
Starting point is 01:18:38 And of course, the goal isn't to be uniformly happy. I don't think the goal is to just be able to accept the stream of emotions and curate them a little bit, but to live a life where they're part of you and you don't try and fight them quite so much. I think in one specific area I can see progress, so for a few times in my life I did suffer depression. I had it pretty bad and and and when you were saying that the visceral reality of things like anxiety, I know this very well and these were the hardest times in my life. How to get out of those is it's a great challenge everyone does it in their own way, but I think
Starting point is 01:19:27 thinking about the impermanence, the constructed, provisional nature of the self and of emotional responses has helped me in this regard a bit. It provides a little bit of a psychological immune system. It may be a bit similar to a clinical immune system. It may be a bit similar to meditation. People who've done a ton of meditation also learn to pay attention to their emotions and their mental states and to recognize that they're transient that they pass. I think the direct experience of meditation is probably better than the theoretical knowledge in the same way that direct experience of psychedelics knowledge in the same way that direct experience of psychedelics exceeds and outstrips what one might learn from the books and from experiments. But I think it can get you somewhere. And in a sense, thinking about consciousness for now, 20, 25, 30 years, that's been a lot of hours. And so in a way,
Starting point is 01:20:22 that's been a lot of some kind of meditative practice on the nature of the self and of perception. And I would be disappointed if it had no effect. I think it has had an effect. And I think it's had a beneficial effect though, you know, there's still a lot of work. I'm still very much working progress. Anil Seth, ladies and gentlemen, if people want to keep up to date with the stuff that you're doing online, where should they go?
Starting point is 01:20:44 The easiest place, go to my website. It's an anilseth.com or you can follow me on Twitter, I still use Twitter, anilketh. And I really appreciate you. I look forward to seeing what you do next. I've been a fan of your work for a long time, so it's been very cool to catch up today. I'm so glad we were able to have this conversation. I know it took a long time to arrange. Thanks so much Chris.

There aren't comments yet for this episode. Click on any sentence in the transcript to leave a comment.