Rev Left Radio - RED MENACE DEBUT - Socialism: Utopian and Scientific by Friedrich Engels
Episode Date: February 11, 2019On the debut episode of Red Menace, the brand new Rev Left Radio sister show, Alyson and Breht discuss Socialism: Utopian and Scientific by Friedrich Engels. The video episode can be found on youtube ...at: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=mKdxX5eqQyk Outro Music by Adia Victoria - Invisible Hands Check out and support her beautiful music here: http://www.adiavictoria.com -------- Our logo was made by BARB, a communist graphic design collective! You can find them on twitter or insta @Barbaradical. Please reach out to them if you are in need of any graphic design work for your leftist projects! -------- Please Rate and Review Red Menace on iTunes. This dramatically helps increase our reach. Support the Show and get access to bonus content on Patreon here: https://www.patreon.com/TheRedMenace Follow us on Twitter @The_Red_Menace
Transcript
Discussion (0)
Hello everybody. This is your host and comrade Brett O'Shea from Revolutionary Left Radio.
Today we are launching our brand new spin-off show, Red Menace.
Red Menace is a multimedia project, both a podcast and a YouTube video produced show,
hosted by Allison Escalante from our state and revolution as well as our gender abolition episodes.
What we do is we take a work of revolutionary political theory.
We explain it, then we analyze it, and then we apply its lessons to,
our current material conditions.
This is just a first time debut episode release, and we're just encouraging people that if
you like what we do here to go check us out and possibly even support us on those other
platforms.
Before we get into this brand new debut of Red Menace, I do want to give a shout out to
Barb, B-A-R-B.
They're a left-wing graphics design collective from Canada.
They made the new logo for Revolutionary Left Radio, and they also made the brand-new logo for
our new podcast, Red Menace.
Dennis. They wanted us to give a shout out to a Canadian podcast. The podcast is the Alberta
Advantage. On Twitter, it's at Berta Advantage. The show notes will link to that. They are broadcasting
from the capitalist belly of the climate change beast, Calgary, Alberta. Alberta is, of course,
the home of the Althabasca Tar sands, the vilest of all foes in the fight against climate change.
They are fearless in their eco-socialism in this hostile environment, in their defense of
indigenous people and climate change fighters.
They analyze the politics of Alberta, the Canadian prairies, much like the Great Plains
region here in the U.S., and Canada at large.
They are open about their identities, particularly the lead host, and this has led to endless
harassment, abuse, violent racism, and death threats directed against them by Canadian
reactionaries.
Again, the show is called the Alberta Advantage, especially for those interested in environmental
issues, climate change issues, or those who live in Canada are interested in Canadian politics.
from a left-wing perspective, definitely go check out the Alberta Advantage.
And if you're looking for any graphic design work for any of your projects,
you can reach out to them anytime, and they will do graphic design work for you.
You'd be supporting a left-wing collective, and they'll be supporting you and your project.
So it's a wonderful little ecosystem that we have going on here.
Now, with all of that said, here is our debut episode of Red Menace.
Hi there. My name is Allison, and I'm here with my co-host, Brett, and you are listening to or potentially watching The Red Menace.
This is a new podcast and YouTube project that Brett and I are working on, where our goal is to take a work of theory and to break it down, explore its main themes, discuss it, and then apply it to today.
And our hope isn't to just do theory for theory's sake, but we're trying to focus on the way that theory informs our actual organizing and the mass work that we're involved in and show how these classic theoretical texts still weigh on us today and can inform our strategies in really useful and productive manners.
So to that end, our show is broken down into three sections.
In the first section, we're going to go through the text that we've chosen, and we're going to try to focus on the main themes, pull out a couple of quotations, and really break down what it's saying.
In the second section, we're going to propose some discussion questions for each other, going to do.
have a little bit of back and forth and maybe get into some of our thoughts, concerns, and
questions with the text. And then finally, in section three, we're going to focus on applying that
text to the organizing work that we as communists are doing today and to focus on how it is actually
useful for helping us work towards revolution. That's right. And if you enjoy what we do and you want
to keep up with us, you can follow us on Twitter at the underscore red underscore menace or on
Patreon at patreon.com forward slash the specter haunts. Let us know what sort of bonus content you
want to see from us on our Patreon because although Allison and I have structured this show,
we're still sort of wondering about what sort of Patreon content we could give to draw in
supporters and keep them happy. So if you get in on the ground floor right now, you can sort of
guide what sort of content we will be putting out on Patreon going forward. But yeah, with that
said, I think the best thing to do is just jump right in. Do you want to tell people what the text
that we're focusing on today is? And then we can go from there, Alison. Definitely. So to
Today we are going to be focusing on a text by Friedrich Engels called Socialism, Utopian, and Scientific.
And we'll get a little bit into the nature of that text, but we're focusing on it because it's a really good introduction to historical materialism
and to sort of a lot of the contemporary debates within Marxism about Marxism status as a science and why that status is really important for us to emphasize.
Yeah, exactly. And we also thought it would be the perfect text to start our entire show with because it is so fundamental to the market.
It is angles, so it's rooted in marks and angles as the original progenitors of the Marxist tradition.
And, you know, as we go on with the show, we're going to be tackling theoretical texts from
all over the left spectrum, but this is a solid, you know, sort of anchor to start our show with,
and that's why we decided to choose it.
So I guess the best way to start this episode is to talk about sort of the background context
and perhaps what angles set out to do when he sat down to write this text.
And I guess the main thing that Engels stresses is that he wanted an accessible alternative to reading Capital.
So Capital is really the masterpiece of Marx and Engels' work.
But at the same time, because of its length and because of how difficult of a text that can sometimes be,
Angles wanted to find a way to sort of synthesize the main ideas of Capital, of the Marxist tradition, of Marx and Engels' philosophy,
into a single almost pamphlet-sized theory text so it can be easily handed around and accessible
to workers, et cetera.
And so I think you'll find a lot of the core ideas of Marxism in this text, which is another
reason why we decided to do it.
And then also some more of the context is that Engels is systematizing Marx's work in
the face of Dr. During's attacks.
And I think Allison will talk a little bit about the anti-During text that this is.
sort of taken from, but Engels said that my opponents, i.e. Dr. During, gave me the opportunity
of developing in opposition to him and in a more connected form than had previously been done,
the views held by Marx and myself on this great variety of subjects. And so I think that gives you
kind of the idea of what Engels set out to accomplish with this text. Alison, what else should we
know about this text before we get into it? Yeah, so this text is not a completely original text for
Ingalls and as much as he's actually drawing on some of his previous writing. So there's a larger work,
which is commonly called anti-During, which is this, again, broader response to during. And this is
one of the really philosophically interesting Marxist texts, where Ingalls does the work of
juxtaposing Marxism with a lot of other philosophical schools and social scientific developments at the
time. What I love about this text as well is that you see some of that carrying over. And so what
Ingalls is trying to do in this text, really, is get at what it is that makes
the Marxist approach to materialism different than everything that's come before it and why it is that
there's a unique advantage to that. And so in order to do that, he's going to focus on how Marxist
materialism is scientific, and we'll get into all the reasons that he provides for that. But that's
sort of the main project. One thing that Ingalls was very aware of in his own lifetime was that
this is one of the most translated texts that he wrote. It became hugely popular. The English
translation was actually one of the later ones. It was originally written in German, and then
the French translation helped popularize it, but this became a very popular pamphlet for introducing
people, especially people who don't have like a very literary background in Marxism to the
ideas of Marx and explaining why Marx is unique, important, and scientific.
Yep, absolutely. And this book is broken down into three main chapters. And so this first
part of the entire show is going to be an explanation of those basic arguments and ideas
and themes going kind of chapter by chapter. And then as Allison said, we'll later, we'll dive
into it, we'll criticize it, we'll analyze it, and we'll apply it. But for now, did you want to
start with Chapter 1 and just sort of talk about the history of socialism leading up to Marx?
Yeah, so Ingle starts by basically looking at the socialist movements that came before Marx.
So while Marxism, obviously, since Marxist's writing has been sort of the dominant form of
socialism that people have adopted in order to work on revolutionary projects, there was a long
period before that where people were thinking about socialism and trying to theorize it and coming up with
their own versions of it. And so Ingalls is going to frame these as utopian versions of socialism
or as bourgeois versions of socialism. And we'll get into specifically what's utopian about them.
But Ingalls' reading of them is interesting because he kind of looks at the way that each of them
makes a theoretical breakthrough that moves us closer to materialism while not quite getting to
materialism. There's three figures he focuses on in particular, which is,
St. Simon, Foyer, and Robert Owens, all of whom had their own approach to scientific or to
utopian socialism that fell short of being revolutionary, but started to progress us further
and would end up laying a framework that Marx could modify and adopt later on.
Yeah, exactly. And he also makes a point to kind of contextualize what Marx and Engels are
doing in the broader movement of philosophy and science at that time. And part of that is in
Chapter 1, Angles goes back and talks about the development of capitalism as an economic
system coinciding with the development of philosophy as capitalism was materially developing.
And so you saw alongside the development of capital these philosophies that really stressed
rationality and reason, you know, coming out of the enlightenment where, you know,
feudalism was really underpinned by superstition and theological domination, the divine
rights of kings, et cetera. And so, you know, in rebellion against the feudal order and alongside
the material development of a new mode of production was a whole range of philosophies that
tried to wrestle with reason and rationality. And in my opinion, sort of reflected an obsession
with rationality and reason by these early bourgeois philosophers. And so putting this
into work, you know, putting these ideas into praxis really came, really blossomed, I think,
the most in the French Revolution. The French Revolution was really a bourgeois revolution. It was
not a proletarian revolution. And inside the French Revolution, you really saw these ideas start
to be put into practice. I mean, the French revolutionaries, the bourgeois revolutionaries,
they wanted a revolution that aimed for a society and a government really rooted in reason
and rationality. And they thought that if, if, if, you know,
we could get beyond the superstition of the feudal age and toward a more rational, reasonable
interaction with our governments, with nature, with ourselves, that it would basically
usher in some sort of, you know, bourgeois utopia. I mean, that was sort of the hidden
promise of a lot of these ideas. And so I'm going to read from the text, Angles, talking about
this bourgeois obsession with rationality and reason, and then how it actually, you know,
played out in practice. So Angles says, but the new.
order of things, rational enough as compared with earlier conditions, turned out to be by no means
absolutely rational. The state based upon reason completely collapsed. Rousseau's social contract
had found its realization in the reign of terror, from which the bourgeoisie, who had lost
confidence in their own political capacity, had taken refuge first in the corruption of the
directorate and finally under the wing of the Napoleonic despotism. The promised eternal peace
was turned into an endless war of conquest.
The society, based upon reason, had fared no better.
The antagonism between rich and poor, instead of dissolving into general prosperity,
had become intensified by the removal of the guild and other privileges, which had to some extent bridged it over,
and by the removal of the charitable institutions of the church.
The quote-unquote freedom of property from feudal fetters, now veritably accomplished,
turned out to be, for the small capitalist and small proprietors, the freedom to sell their small
property crushed under the overmastering competition of the large capitalist and landlords to
these great lords and thus as far as the small capitalist and peasant proprietors were concerned
became freedom from property. The development of industry upon a capitalistic basis made
poverty and misery of the working masses conditions of existence of society. Cash payment became
more and more in Carlisle's phrase the sole nexus between man and man. The number of crimes
increased from year to year. Trade became to a greater and greater extent cheating. The fraternity
of the revolutionary motto was realized in the chicanery and rivalries of the battle of competition.
Oppression by force was replaced by corruption, the sword as the first social lever by gold.
The right of the first night was transferred from the feudal lords to the bourgeois manufacturers.
In a word, compared with the splendid promises of the philosophers, the social and political
institutions born of the triumph of reason were bitterly disappointing caricatures. And so I think
this is where Engels really breaks down the gap between what the bourgeois philosophy's promised
and what actually happened when bourgeois philosophy was able to be put into practice. And so
in response to the disasters and broken promises of bourgeois theory and practice came the
utopian socialists. And the utopian socialists were in the late 1700s, early
the 1800s. And Engel says,
To the crude conditions of capitalistic production and the crude class conditions
corresponded crude theories.
And here he's talking about the utopian socialist who came up in the wake of the
failures of bourgeois philosophy to be put into practice and fulfill its own promises.
And as Allison suggested, three of the main ones that Engels touches on here is St. Simon,
Fourier, and Robert Owen.
Each of them had a few impressive insights, again, as Allison alluded to.
St. Simon, for example, talked about economic conditions being the determinant factor in political conditions.
Fourier talked about a stagist conception of history as well as emphasized women's liberation.
And Robert Owen, perhaps maybe the most interesting of all three because he really went out of his way to sort of run experiments in his own factories on these grounds.
He came up with a real critique of private property and advocated actually the workers' ownership of the means of production.
So again, you start to see these little germs of ideas that would come to be basic principles for all socialists to this day.
But because of the way that they were organized and because of the rest of the systems in which they were embedded, they're still deeply utopian and there's no real basis by which to say, this theoretical tendency is better than this theoretical tendency, etc.
So, you know, Engels says that these were idealists and they saw socialism in terms fundamentally of ideas created.
in rare minds. And so what you saw as a result of this cropping up of different, you know,
schools of socialism was an eclecticism and a sort of a sectarianism, not so much in the sense
of how we use the word today, but in the sense of actual sex forming. Somebody over here
would come up with an idea and say, this is socialism and this is how we get there. Somebody over
here would say, actually, this is socialism and this is how we get there. And so socialism wasn't
a unified proletarian movement, but at this point, consistent.
in a lot of little sex running around, claiming that they had the best ideas about how to
achieve socialism. And so, again, going back to the text, Angles talks about these utopians,
and he says, to all these utopians, socialism is the expression of absolute truth, reason,
and justice, and has only to be discovered to conquer all the world by virtue of its own power.
And as absolute truth is independence of time, space, and of the historical development of man,
it is a mere accident when and where it is discovered.
With all this, absolute truth, reason, and justice are different with the founder of each different school.
And as each one's special kind of absolute truth, reason and justice, is again conditioned by his subjective understanding, his conditions of existence, the measure of his knowledge and his intellectual training, there is no other ending possible in this conflict of absolute truths than that they shall be mutually exclusive, one of the other.
Hence, from this, nothing could come but a kind of eclectic, average socialism, which, as a matter of fact, has up to the present time.
dominated the minds of most of the socialist workers in France and England. Hence, a mishmash
allowing of the most manifold shades of opinion, a mishmash of such critical statements,
economic theories, pictures of future society by the founders of different sex, as excite a
minimum of opposition, a mishmash which is the more easily brewed, the more the definite sharp
edges of the individual constituents are rubbed down in the stream of debate like rounded pebbles
in a brook. To make a science of socialism, it had first to be placed upon a real basis. And so this
is Angles talking about how utopianism inherently fells. It can't lead for a big movement. And so
the solution to utopian socialism is scientific socialism, is to put socialism on a real
material basis. And that's precisely what Marx and Engels set out to do.
Definitely. Yeah. And I think there's a few interesting things in this chapter that I want to
focused on on the end, in terms of the relationship between history and theory. Because I think
one thing that Ingalls points out that is really telling is that the crude early conditions of
capitalism produced crude theory, right? So it's not just a complete theoretical failure,
but it's also the fact that capitalism was a new thing that was emerging within history itself
and had not taken on super concrete forms yet and was still really difficult to theorize. And I think
what's interesting for Ingalls is that while he obviously condemns each of these theorists for
having a universal theory of truth grounded not in history but their own subjectivity, he also is
noting that there's useful things that they're realizing from the historical events which are going on
around them. And that sets a progression later on for Marxism to take up. The other thing that I think
is interesting with the text is also that it's sort of the emergence of the proletariat as a class
and the recognition of that class is a historical phenomenon that then allows Marx to make a
theoretical recognition of the role of the proletariat and the role of surplus labor is also
important, according to Ingalls. So there's this really complicated relationship between
history and theory, and part of the problem with the utopians is that they assume that they've
sort of stepped outside of history and simply impose the ideal, rational, universal truth
onto it, whereas what we're going to see is the few things they get right and what Marx will
later get right, is taking things from history and then applying them to history itself.
Absolutely. So, you ready to move into chapter two?
Yeah, so let's move on to chapter two, which is a really interesting chapter. And this chapter
is mostly devoted towards pointing out what the sort of traditional metaphysical theory that
Europe has relied upon to look at the world is, and then juxtaposing it with dialectics
and explaining why dialectics is a more useful and actually a more accurate understanding of how the world works.
So Ingle starts by criticizing what he calls the metaphysical mode of thought,
and he points to a few different people as an example of this,
and he specifically names Locke and Bacon as people who engage in sort of this classic form of metaphysical thinking.
And for Ingalls, what's important about this metaphysical thinking is that it is abstracted from processes,
and it tries to understand things in isolation.
There's a quote I want to look at specifically where Ingle says,
The metaphysician thinks an absolutely irreconcilable antithesis.
For him, a thing either exists or does not exist.
A thing cannot at the same time be itself and something else.
Positive and negative absolutely exclude one another.
Cause and effect stand in rigid antithesis.
And so you can look to a lot of early modern philosophy
and really see this view of the world start to come into being.
If you want to understand an odd,
the goal of philosophy becomes understanding the unique properties of that object in isolation from everything else.
And Ingls thinks that there's some problems with this, this idea of static isolation, of thinking of things outside of everything else,
actually forces us into really rigid and reductive thinking, where we can't understand the relationships between things.
And this will later on become really important for Marxism, actually.
And later Marxist concepts like commodity fetishism, I think, will really reflect.
the failure to think about things in their relationships instead of in their isolation.
But so Ingalls is critiquing this and actually argues that this view is not actually an
accurate reflection of nature and that when we move and look towards nature itself, we can
see that the metaphysical view doesn't hold up. Now Ingalls doesn't completely reject metaphysics
as a category. He does say there's contexts in which it's helpful and it allows us to understand
an idea better. And I think that's important to emphasize. But at the same time, to universalize
it as the only way to look at the world is really a problem. And it's a sort of view of the
world that has arisen alongside that bourgeois obsession with rationality and foundational
principles that we could extend more universally. Yeah, exactly. It's, you know, it's breaking
things down and exactly into their constituent parts and analyzing those parts to get a picture
of the whole. But by doing that, it is sort of static and it isolates different things from
everything else. So in opposition to what, you know, Angles is referring to as the metaphysical
mode of thought, which Allison just explained, is dialectics. And dialectics is a form of what we call
today process philosophy, whereby you understand phenomena, not by their individuated, sliced up
individual components, but rather by the mechanisms of change, evolution, development, and
transformation that takes place. It's sort of analyzing things as a state of constant becoming.
And this allows you a much broader understanding of things and their interrelatedness to all other
things. Early iterations of dialectics, which some of you may be familiar with, they occur in both
the East and the West. In ancient Greek philosophy, for example, you have somebody like Heraclitus,
and Heraclitus had that famous line where he was like, you know, you can never step into the
same river twice because the river has changed and so has the person stepping into it. And so right
there you start to see how change is the cornerstone of reality for Heraclitus. And this goes back
all the way again to ancient Greece. And then if you look eastward, you find in Buddhist
philosophy, for example, multiple dialectical ideas.
One is the idea of the self in Buddhism, which asserts that the notion that you have a core
static self at the center of your experience is actually an illusion and that there is no
actual core static self at all, but just changing contents of consciousness.
And then they also stress this idea of impermanence.
You know, all conditioned existence and experience is, without exception, transient and
impermanent. And then in Taoism, I think, you know, there's lots in Taoism we could talk about,
but I think everybody's familiar with the yin and the yang. And what the yin and the yang is,
is that there's a coincidence of opposites, right? Opposites coincide. And we're going to get
into angles talking about negative and positive pulls and really talks about how these two things
give rise to each other, right? You can't have the day without night because the concept of day
becomes incoherent without the other side of that coin. And so you're starting to see these things have
long been in the human mind and only now, you know, in modern science, are these things starting
to have to wrestle with the scientific method itself? And so with more modern examples and
scientific examples of dialectical understanding of the world, he points out two really big
examples. One is Emmanuel Kant. And most of us know Kant as a philosopher, you know,
critique of pure reason, et cetera. But Emmanuel Kant actually started his career with a paper on the
solar system. And in contradistinction to the ideas of his time, Newtonian mechanics, which talked
about the motion and the orbit of the planets and how those planets operate, what Kant did
is argue that the solar system itself goes through an evolutionary process. And he put forward
the theory of nebulous gases as a way to talk about this. And the basic idea, which has been
proven by science to be correct, is that solar systems don't just statically exist and circle their
sun, but rather that they evolve through condensing gases in nebulas.
And as they come and they form material objects, then the motions of Newtonian mechanics
start to take hold of those objects, so they get bigger and bigger.
And then you see the solar system that we have today.
But what Kant fundamentally did was say solar systems have a birth, they have a development,
and they have a death.
They're not static things.
And then in the realm of biology, I think this is the most famous example.
And again, I don't think Darwin's influence on marks and angles can be understated here.
It's very, very important to this entire project.
But Darwin did the same thing that Kant did with the solar system.
Darwin did to biology.
And he showed through scientific evidence that life forms weren't categories that people were born into,
but rather life forms evolved over time due to natural pressures from their environment,
mutations in their genetic code, which we'd find out later through science, sexual selection, etc.
So here you see both on the level of the solar system and on the level of organic beings on earth
this dialectical evolutionary understanding taking hold.
And I'm going to go back to the text and Angles talks about this.
Engel says, nature is the proof of dialectics.
And it must be said for modern science that it has furnished this proof with very rich materials increasing daily.
And thus has shown that in the last resort, nature works dialectically and not metaphysically.
that she does not move in the eternal oneness of a perpetually recurring circle,
but goes through a real historical evolution.
In this connection, Darwin must be named before all others.
He dealt the metaphysical conception of nature the heaviest blow
by his proof that all organic beings, plants, animals, and man himself
are the products of a process of evolution going on through millions of years.
And some angles goes on to talk about some of the essential aspects,
of dialectics he talks about biological death and says contrary to the way that some people
talk about this the process of death is actually a protracted process with no clear beginning or
end and he even interestingly way ahead of his time i think talks about pro-life arguments
where he talks about certain people of his time trying to i think he says cudgel their brains
in vain to try to come up with a point at which life begins and we see this debate today with the
moment of conception, right? These are arbitrary dividing points placed on actual processes. And by doing
that, you're actually not seeing the holistic whole that these phenomena operate in, but you're
trying to set end points where they actually don't exist in nature. He also talks about cells
and the human body, constantly taking in new things and expelling the old in a constant exchange with
the environment. He talks again about positive and negative poles, kind of like the yin and the yang,
the inseparability of these opposites and the fact that they mutually arise and interpenetrate.
And then lastly, he talks about cause and effect, where he says they're eternally changing places.
So you have a cause, you have an effect.
That effect then becomes the cause of the next thing.
And you see this chain of interaction.
And so the lines between this being a cause and this being effect really do get blurred.
So again, you see angles really trying to show how things are processes, that they're mechanisms that evolve over time.
And they're not static things that you can just break down.
look inside of and understand.
So, you know, kind of in summary, in dialectics, you see the historicization of phenomena
from biological organisms to the solar system, and finally, thanks to marks and angles,
to human society's history and modes of production.
In other words, historical materialism is what one discovers when you apply the dialectical,
evolutionary, and scientific lens to the development of human societies over time.
Yeah, so Ingalls has this really profoundly interesting view of dialectics in this text.
Reading through it, I was incredibly impressed with his ability to tie in Darwin, tie in these biological questions,
and you really get a complex understanding of what dialectics is.
So the next thing that's really important for Ingalls, though,
is talking about dialectics in relation to a specific philosopher who Marx was a student of,
which is Hegel.
Marx was originally part of a group of philosophers called the Young Higalian,
who were interested in reading Hegel in a radical manner,
most of them reading him in an atheistic manner,
and often juxtaposed to the right Hegelians,
who wanted to read him in a more politically conservative manner.
So Hegel's a very important theorist for Marxism,
and he's also an incredibly difficult theorist to explain.
So we're going to try to get into Hegel here,
but honestly, he is incredibly difficult,
and if you don't completely grasp it, that's okay,
because it takes a lot of time.
What is important with Hegel, for Ingl's at least, is that Hegel takes this understanding of dialectics and applies it to history itself and the entire world and tells us how we can look at everything through dialectics.
So he says that really the dialectical development culminates in Hegel in a way.
And he says, quote, for Hegel, the whole world, natural, historical, intellectual is represented as a process, i.e. as in constant motion, change, transformation.
development, and the attempt is made to trace out the internal connections that make a continuous
whole of all this movement and development, end quote. So for Hegel, all the sudden, dialectics
isn't just a thing that governs individual phenomena like life or like death or these other things,
but it actually is a guiding way of looking at the world. And Hegel also starts to look at dialectics
and trace out these ideas of contradiction, thesis, and antithesis, and the way these things relate to
each other, how something isn't composed just of itself, but the opposite of it, the thing that
negates it, is also a part of how we understand phenomena. And this is going to become extremely
important for Marx later on. Unfortunately, as Ingalls points out, Hegel is an idealist in
one of the most intense senses of the world, word. Specifically, Ingle's writes that for Hegel,
thoughts within his brain were not the more or less abstract pictures of real things and processes,
But conversely, things and their evolution were only the realized pictures of the ideas existing somewhere from eternity beyond where the world was.
And so for Hegel, we see that while the world is moving dialectically and it is a process and it's not a world of things in isolation, but is rather one of change in relationships, that still is one that's fundamentally driven by ideas.
History for Hegel is about the culmination of what he calls spirit.
and this idea that spirit and rationality are driving humanity forward towards their perfection
in a given society.
This is also why right-wing theorists also liked Hegel and read him, because many people
read Hegel as saying that reason and spirit and the sort of ideal movements had culminated
in Germany itself.
So there's certainly a right-wing leaning of Hegel that comes from this, and what Marx and
Ingalls are going to take from Hegel isn't that at all, but rather the recognition that
history is composed of movement, development, and process, and that that process is one where
different forces come to a head with each other and contradict each other, and some sort of
synthesis and resolution comes out of those contradictions that moves history forward.
And if this all sounds a little bit abstract, that's because due to Hegel's idealism,
it is fairly abstract in Hegel. And what's so useful about what Marx and Ingalls do is that
they take these concepts and apply them to real historical events that we can actually
turn to and analyze in order to understand what these movements of contradiction and synthesis look like.
And that's really where the big breakthrough is going to come from.
Marx famously says that he takes Hegel and he turns him on his head, which is to say that
he takes the general movement that Hegel isolates, but instead of placing the idea on top,
which then forms the world, he places the historical material and economic development of the
world and then analyzes how that relates to ideals. And so this recognition that
made actually sets us up to get to materialism while stopping short of ever actually becoming
materialism itself yeah exactly incredibly well said and so as angles zooms in on the end of chapter
two what he's done looking back is that he's traced the entire development of of these ideas of
philosophy how they how they manifest in bourgeois revolutions like the french revolution then he gets
into tracing the sort of history of science itself and talks about how the metaphysical mode of thought
has dominated for centuries, and then this new dialectical way of looking at the world is
emerging around his time with people like Darwin and Kant. And then he talks about Hegel as being
the first person to, as Allison said, really make history subject to this evolutionary process.
Given all the other things that Hegel got wrong, at least he offered that on the table,
and then Marx and Engels took that and ran from it. So you're taking the evolutionary ideas from
biology and cosmology. You're mixing them with Hegel's conception of history, stripped of its
idealism, incorporating the first ever class struggles of the proletariat, which are occurring
around this time. And by doing that, you're starting to see the historicization of the capitalist
mode of production, seeing where it's come from, out of what system it's grown, which we'll get
to in a little bit in Chapter 3. And then also at the end of the chapter, Engels talks about how
Marx discovered the mechanism by which capitalism was inherently exploitative, and that is
surplus value. So at the very end of Chapter 2, right before we get into Chapter 3, Engels writes,
and this sort of sums all of it up for folks.
The new facts made imperative a new examination of all past history.
Then it was seen that all past history, with the exception of its primitive stages,
was the history of class struggles, that these warring classes of society are always the
products of the modes of production and of exchange, in a word of the economic conditions of
their time, that the economic structure of society always furnishes the real basis,
starting from which we can alone work out the ultimate explanation of the whole superstructure
of jurisdicial and political institutions, as well as of the religious, philosophical, and other
ideas of a given historical period.
Hegel had freed history from metaphysics.
He had made it dialectic, but his conception of history was essentially idealistic.
But now idealism was driven from its last refuge, the philosophy of history.
Now a materialistic treatment of history was propounded and a method found of explaining
man's knowing by his being, instead of, as heretofore, his being by his knowing.
From that time forward, socialism was no longer an accidental discovery of this or that
ingenious brain, but the necessary outcome of the struggle between two historically developed
classes, the proletariat and the bourgeoisie.
The socialism of earlier days certainly criticized the existing capitalist mode of production
and its consequences, but it could not explain them, and therefore could not get the
mastery of them. It could only simply reject them as bad. Therefore, it was necessary, one, to present
the capitalist method of production in its historical connection and its inevitableness during a
particular historical period, and therefore also its inevitable downfall, and two, to lay bare its
essential character, which was still a secret. This was done by the discovery of surplus value.
The genesis of capitalist production and the production of capital were now both explained. These two
great discoveries, the materialistic conception of history, and the revelation of the secret of
capitalistic production through surplus value, we owe to Marx. With these discoveries, socialism
became a science. The next thing was to work out all of its details and its relations. So that's
him summarizing the entire, you know, first two chapters and explaining where they were at this point.
And with that, I think we're ready to dive into chapter three, Allison. Awesome. So chapter three is
really cool. In this chapter, Ingalls begins to develop what Marx's actual methodology itself is
and also starts to draw some of the economic insights that Marx has made in capital and condensed
them very extremely for us to understand in relation to that methodology. So the first thing that
we really need to get into is what is it that Marx changes about Hegel? And Brett has already
hinted at this that now we're not understanding how ideas produce man's body, but how man's
existence in the world produces ideas. And so the real fundamental change is that in our understanding
of history, which is still dialectic, we're giving primacy to economics and to the material
realities in which people live. And Marx has framed this in various different ways. In many of his
text, it's framed in the communist manifesto, in the German ideology, you'll hear slightly
different iterations of it. But Ingle summarizes it fairly nicely when he says, quote,
The final cause of all social change and political revolutions are to be sought not in men's brain,
not in men's better insights into internal truth and justice, but in the changes and the modes
of production and exchange. So this is interesting. What happens now is if we want to understand
what causes history to move forward as this dialectic process, we can't look at the ideas people
are coming up with, we can't look at the thoughts they're putting into the world,
but we have to look at production and exchange and the economic and material base of a society first.
So there's a few ways that this is a huge break from what came before, and especially the utopian socialism.
So for the utopian socialists, it was sort of the opposite, right?
The world is changed by coming up with perfect rational ideas and then imposing those ideas onto reality,
and from there being able to transform reality in line with those ideas.
And for materialists, that's not going to be possible at all.
And in fact, we have to start with reality itself and the historical development of how humans feed themselves, produce commodities, trade commodities, have all of these interrelations and processes which precede the ideas that we're forming.
And so there's this interesting approach to looking at the world where we get a sort of idea of what we could call imminent critique.
It's no longer that we step outside history and we impose our perfect utopian ideals onto it, but rather that we look at history and we look at the contradictory.
that are already occurring and emerging within history around us, and we understand how to get
critical insights from those. And Ingle's is going to focus on multiple contradictions within
capitalism and how it is that those contradictions actually create a scientific assessment
of capitalism. But I want to focus on the way that there is sort of a very imminent aspect to this
approach. Engel says that if we really adopt the Marxist's analytic and method, that, quote,
it follows that the means of getting rid of the incongruities that have been brought to light
must also be present in a more or less developed condition within the changed modes of production
themselves. These means are not to be invented by deduction from fundamental principles,
but are to be discovered in the stubborn facts of the existing systems of production.
So what Ingalls is saying there is that if we want to get rid of capitalism
and all the violent contradictions that come with it,
We don't make a radical break away from capitalism with new ideas, but we find the parts of capitalism that are already at odds with other parts of capitalism.
The solution to capitalism is actually created and produced by capitalist development.
And the real contradiction that Ingalls is going to focus on here is a contradiction between productive forces and capitalist appropriation, which we'll get into in a little bit.
But Engel's suggestion that's really interesting is that capitalism has created forms of production that,
already make capitalism irrelevant and outdated and that the trick to overcoming capitalism isn't
to build a utopia but to set those productive forces free and to take the good things that
capitalism has built and use it to resolve the contradiction with the more negative socially
harmful and individualistic things that capitalism has built yeah exactly and i think that and we're
going to get into those in the discussion questions we're really going to dive into to what some of
that it means and what are some of its implications but at this point in the text what angles
does is says, okay, now that we've sort of established a materialist conception of history
and what it means, let's sort of look at the evolution of capitalism. What came before it
and where is it going? And so they sketch out in really summarized form the transition
from feudalism or what Engels calls medieval society to capitalism, talks about all the
contradictions within capitalism, and then talks about proletarian or socialist revolution
in response to the contradictions of capitalism. So starting with feudalism, aka medieval
society. He just talks about some of the things that, that, you know, market as a specific
period of historical development. He says there's individual production on small scale. The
means of production were adapted for individual use. So you have craftsmen inside of a building
working through a product from beginning to end, creating it. The production was for
immediate consumption. Under feudalism, it wasn't necessarily for exchange. So you produced
goods so that you could consume those goods, basically getting by day to day.
But at some points, there were a surplus in production.
So at certain times, let's say, you know, I was growing corn and I had a particularly good season.
The excess amount of corn that went above and beyond me and my neighbors need to eat was put onto what would be considered a sort of proto marketplace and exchange with other people who had surpluses.
So that guy over there makes shoes.
He made too many shoes this month, you know, whatever.
I'm hyper simplifying, but you get the idea.
So I trade him my excesses of corn for his excesses of shoes.
we both mutually benefit.
But right here you start to see the seeds of commodity production.
And what commodity production is is creating and producing goods not for their immediate
consumption, but rather for their exchange on a market.
And only in the context of creating a surplus in this feudalist environment do we start
to see the inklings or the seeds of commodity production starting to occur.
And so here you can see some of the seeds that would eventually turn into capitalism.
And so he goes over to capitalism, talks about
the capitalist revolution. What happens at this point is there's a concentration of the means of
production, a transformation from individuals owning the means of production to capitalists owning the
means of production, but employing multiple workers, the division of labor, to make this product from
beginning to finish. So this is where you first see actual capitalists appear. They appropriate
the products and they turn them into commodities. So now, unlike in feudalism, you're producing
things, not for immediate consumption, but again, to exchange them on the market for profit.
So production becomes a social act at this point, right? It's not an individual craftsman
in his building creating something, but it actually requires a bunch of people coming together
to produce things from beginning to finish. So there's a fundamental contradiction that
arises here, which is the contradiction between social production and individual appropriation.
A workforce produces the products, and a capitalist, an individual capitalist, appropriates the product of that labor.
And so we see a contradiction, but I'll let Allison talk about that contradiction in a second here.
And the end stage, right, looking forward now, is proletarian revolution, aka socialism.
And in this stage of history, some of the fundamental contradictions begin to be solved, right?
Social production and social property.
So the things that are produced socially no longer go to benefit individual.
capitalists, but under socialism, they become property of everybody, and it goes out to meet
people's needs, not the profit motivations of individual capitalists. It allows for socially
planned production instead of having a bunch of different capitalist firms competing with each other
on an anarchic market. Societies can see what do we actually need? What is necessary? How do we
produce it in a way that has social benefits and decreases the environmental cost of producing
those things, et cetera? Over time, this reduces or eliminates the anarchy of
production. Angles talks about the anarchy of production under capitalism a lot. We'll get to
that in a second. But once you get to that stage, you begin to transcend class divisions and class
society as a whole. And looking even further, with class transcended, if you ever listen to me
and Allison's episode on Rev. Left Radio about state and revolution, you'll see Lenin giving a
materialist analysis of the state, talking about the state as a manifestation of class society and
class rule. So with class transcended, then the material conditions are such that the the material
base for the state goes away and thus the state itself begins to wither away. And so you can hear
you sort of see what happens when you take the materialist conception of history. You can truly
understand how feudalism turns into capitalism and what's required for capitalism to turn in
to socialism. And he ends this chapter very quickly. He says, to accomplish this act of universal
is the historical mission of the modern proletariat to thoroughly comprehend the historical conditions and thus the very nature of this act to impart to the now oppressed proletarian class a full knowledge of the conditions and of the meaning of the momentous act it is called upon to accomplish this is the task of the theoretical expression of the proletarian movement scientific socialism and that is how he wraps up that part of that book but did you want to talk a little bit before we go on to discussion questions
about some of those contradictions, especially that whole idea about productive forces and
capitalist appropriation? Yeah, definitely, because I think this is really what's interesting.
I mean, first, I just want to say that, like, that ending quote is really incredible, and I think
is one of the most profound moments in the text where Ingalls, I think, really gets at the
fact that the proletariat coming to understand capitalism scientifically is crucial and is not
an optional part of the struggle, but is necessary for understanding how we're going to combat it.
And I think that's a part of this text that's really important for Marxists today to think about.
But the other aspect of this I want to focus on is this relationship between the socialized
productive forces and capitalist appropriation and how Ingalls says that this is a contradiction
that's really difficult for capitalism to overcome. So we'll get into some of the ways that works.
So what Ingalls means by this, as Brett already hinted at, is again, when capitalism developed,
the means of production themselves were changed in that now you didn't have indifference.
craftmen producing goods, but you had multiple collective people working in usually a factory
context early on in order to produce a good. So there is a socialization which occurs there. And as we
know, also alongside this, there's primitive accumulation and the proletarianization of the workforce.
So people are forced to leave feudal society and become part of this laboring class that
collectively produces goods. And there's something interesting there in as much as this is a
socialization of production. Production's not an individualist enterprise anymore. It's something that
a class together undertakes in order to produce goods. But the problem is that, well, this is
probably a very useful and good social development. It's hindered by a contradictory aspect
to capitalism, which again is this idea of individual capitalist appropriation. So while one
person profits from the goods that are produced, many people produce them, and we have this
contradiction. On the one hand, you have a sort of primitive collectivization of production that only
benefits an individual. And so for Ingalls, this contradiction has a whole bunch of implications
within capitalism. One of the most important ones is he says that this contradiction expresses
the antagonism between the proletariat and the capitalists. If we look at this, we can actually
see how their interests are irreconcilable and at odds with each other. What benefits the capitalist
necessarily hurts the proletariat, and what would benefit the proletariat, which is to say
truly socializing both production and appropriation, would come at the cost of the existence
of the capitalist. And so what's important is that we're seeing that capitalism within itself
has this contradiction where these two forces can negate each other in order to move history
forward. And part of the problem in a sense is actually that capitalist appropriation is
holding back the really revolutionary aspects of capitalist production. And there's a number
of implications that this has for Ingalls. He thinks that this actually makes capitalism really
unstable, and that there's a couple of aspects of this. One is that the capitalist system creates
needs for new machinery to be developed and for constantly creating new more revolutionary
production methods. But as this happens, these butt heads with individual capitalists themselves.
And there's a crisis that can occur when revolutions in production aren't mirrored by
revolutions in exchange and appropriation. While production becomes more and more of a scientific
underpinning, you can even think of the development of Fordism, as evil as many of its effects are,
as this sort of scientific socialized production, capitalist exchange and appropriation remains
anarchic in nature. Trade isn't governed by central planning or universal laws, but rather is
guided by the invisible hand, as capitalists like to talk about it. And the appropriation doesn't go back
into furthering the benefits of the workers, but goes to enriching individual capitalists.
And so you have this relationship where these things are constantly at odds and can come to a
crisis where the interests of the proletariat and the interests of the capitalist often come to a head.
And one of the things that I think is really interesting in this text is that Ingalls says
that these crises are something that capitalism attempts to combat.
So on one level, you have companies that will choose to get rid of crises of competition by forming monopolies.
When companies merge together, they no longer have to compete against each other, and an attempt
can be made to try to stabilize the anarchy of capitalist markets by doing that.
But Ingle says this isn't a long-term solution to capitalism, because as other crises arise,
capitalists part ways again.
And the other thing that Ingalls talks about is that the state often can try to intervene
and create central planning for capitalist production in order to avoid these sort of crises,
but that doesn't actually resolve the underlying antagonism that creates the crisis in the first place,
which is the contradiction between collectivized production and individual appropriation.
So while the liberal state might try to come in and might try to essentially make peace between these antagonizing forces,
they always are going to rupture over again because it's at the central core of capitalism.
And this contradiction can't be resolved with capitalist fixes,
but needs to be resolved through proletarian revolution,
and proletarian rule.
And I think that's the very important insight
that Ingalls is getting at here politically.
Exactly.
And so I think that summarizes part one
of our three-part approach to these texts.
So right there, we just explained the entirety
of chapters one, two, and three
of socialism, utopian, and scientific,
just sort of elucidating and explaining
what the main arguments are
and the thrust of the arguments.
And then here in part two,
we're going to dedicate ourselves
to sort of analyzing and criticizing
some of the ideas in here through the form of discussion questions.
So Allison and I both created questions.
We're basically asking one another to spark dialogue and discourse about the implications of this text
and what it means for us regarding, you know, thinking through those implications and those
assumptions, et cetera.
Did you have anything to say about part two before we jump into the questions, Allison?
Not really.
I think we're good to go.
Okay.
You want to ask the first one?
Awesome.
Yeah.
So this is a question that I thought of.
because I think it's really interesting.
So Ingle's argues that nature itself confirms dialectics,
and that scientific inquiry shows us that dialectics is true.
So when we turn to nature and we use science to investigate it, dialectics is confirmed.
And as we already talked about, he uses Darwin in cellular biology
and the idea of death and life in order to demonstrate this.
So the question that I have is, you know,
does further scientific development confirm this claim?
As we've gone on in, you know, the decades since Ingalls,
have we realized that this is true with further scientific investigation?
So this is a very, very good question.
And I was trying to rack my brain about, you know,
when did angles, you know, live and right?
And then what sort of scientific discoveries have happened since his death
that could either confirm or negate some of these claims he's making
about a dialectical approach to understanding the cosmos and on our place within it.
And, you know, my interest in cosmology and theoretical physics kind of took hold of me.
And I was like, that's a great place to sort of think.
about some of these ideas because, you know, modern cosmology, general relativity were developed
after Engels' time. And so they would either provide evidence in support of angles or evidence against
his idea that a dialectical approach is a more scientific approach and a more well-rounded approach.
And so modern cosmology, for example, asserts that the universe is in a constant state of evolutionary
expansion. Think about the Big Bang theory, which says not only do solar systems have a birth,
but the cosmos itself has a birth time.
And moreover, the recent discoveries of dark energy,
which says that not only is the universe expanding,
but it's actually expanding at an accelerating rate.
So all of this, I think, is in line with the dialectical
and evolutionary ideas of marks and angles,
especially when you think about how Darwin applied it to biology,
Kant applied it to our solar system.
A lot of modern cosmology applies it to the universe as a whole.
In addition, general relativity, which was put forward by Albert Einstein, I think, like 30 to 40 years after Angles died, also confirms, I think, a dialectical process-oriented account of the cosmos in contradistinction to static theological claims about the nature of the universe.
General relativity suggests that space and time itself can only make sense in relation to all other space and time.
If you, for example, approach the speed of light, time itself slows down to a halt.
There is then a dialectical relationship between how fast one travels through space and how time itself functions.
Every object in the cosmos, according to these new theories of cosmology and general relativity and physics, is embedded in the space-time fabric.
And therefore, they're not separate, discrete objects fundamentally individuated from one another, but rather they are interconnected, eternal.
interacting phenomena which share an ontological foundation, namely the fabric of space and time.
So I think that especially when you look at all of the advancements made in the last century
when it comes to physics and cosmology, that these are very much in line with angles
conception of what science is and what science does and has only provided more support for
his claim rather than taking it away. I think that puts angles on really good footing.
And again, it gives us a way to sort of falsify, to a small degree, Angles' claim here.
If science, after his death, moved in a different direction and we're actually able to have more coherent understandings of the cosmos with a metaphysical approach to these questions, then that would have been borne out by now, and we would see that Engels was fundamentally wrong about something.
But I think all of the advancements in major scientific fields point in the direction that Engels was actually correct in his assessment and is still correct.
in that, you know, ultimately it bolsters the idea of historical materialism,
being applied, you know, applying that same scientific evolutionary lens to history and societies,
etc.
Did you have anything to say in response to that?
Yeah.
Yeah.
So, I mean, I think the one other interesting place is that one of the examples Ingalls uses,
I think has actually become significantly more poignant is this fact that it's hard to identify
the line between life and death and what those concepts mean.
One of the interesting things is that as medicine has developed further and as we've had to develop also corresponding legal definitions, we've become more and more incapable of defining what death is and where the bright line for death is at.
And I think actually more contemporary developments really push back against this. The concept of brain death, for example, which has been taken up as a very popular definition of death for a lot of legal purposes, also has turned out to be kind of dubious with further scientific.
investigation. And with some of the people who really proposed it early on, now saying that it's
sort of an arbitrary bright line and can't be deduced from the data itself, but is a bright
line that we just kind of had to impose to make sense of it, because death doesn't have a clear
delineation from life that we can draw that easily. So I think that, yeah, like, even on that
issue, medicine has really confirmed a lot of Engel's claims and shown that as we've developed
better scientific tools and insights, we've found the universe to be more and more dialectical.
Yeah. And I think, you know, there's a human impulse to categorize things. And I think the metaphysical mode really reflects that. But sometimes just by virtue of our habit to categorize things, we sometimes forget which categories are actually backed up by, you know, hard science and which ones are things that we project on the world so that we have a better ability to make sense of a fundamentally or seemingly fundamentally chaotic world. And sometimes I think people confuse those lines and they'll take what is ultimate.
ultimately a subjective delineation point and objectify it, make it, you know, actually ontologically
true. And again, I go back to the whole pro-life debate. You do see people trying to set an
arbitrary standard of when life begins. Well, you know, to the pro-lifers, it begins at conception.
Therefore, since life begins at this point that we've said it begins to get rid, to, you know,
to engage in an abortion, for example, is tantamount to murder itself. And so we see how this is
not just abstract. This doesn't even just operate on the level of hard science, but rather it
infects a lot of our political debates as well. And so having that sort of dialectical
understanding of things, I think really bolsters a more robust analysis of current events
and politics than a metaphysical mode of thought would. And I'll get in a little bit to the
exact ways that the metaphysical mode of thought infects our society today, right? If I just told
you, if Allison and I just explained to you some ways in which the dialectical interpretation
makes sense. I'm going to show you in a little bit about how metaphysical modes of thinking
still exist in our time and how they manifest in our current time. But we're not there yet.
So the next question, and you touched on this a little bit. I just think the term itself may
need some clarifying and then expounding on it. But Angles talks a lot about the anarchy
of capitalist production. And the term anarchy is definitely loaded on the left. Suffice
it to say we're using the colloquial pejorative sense of being synonymous with chaos.
here, but it does raise an interesting question. What does anarchy of production really mean?
Why is it bad? And what are its consequences? Yeah. So, okay, yeah, there's definitely a semantic
question to be raised here. So when Ingalls is talking about the anarchy of production,
he's not talking about political anarchism. As, you know, we've come to understand it as a
revolutionary current. I think this idea of the anarchy of production does raise questions about
political anarchism that we might want to get into to some extent. But I don't think that
that's what he means. So what is it that he means when he talks about the anarchy of production?
Well, under capitalism, you don't really have planned production, right? What is it that causes
certain commodities to be produced? Well, traditionally, capitalists have said, on the one hand,
market demands create that, and then you produce in response to that. Exchange produces that,
and all of these forces that are decentralized and not focused in a specific set of
imperatives, and that almost can't even be observed, create incentives for capitalists to produce
certain commodities over others. So part of the problem that you get, actually, is that there is
a chaos to capitalist production. Things aren't being produced to suit human need. They're being
produced on the basis of a bunch of market forces that no individual really has control over.
And quite frankly, that's just a bad way to run a society that causes you to develop shortages
of food or certain other commodities or overabundances of certain commodities there you then have a
high level of surplus that you can't do anything with and so for ingles the anarchy of production
points to sort of the silliness in a sense of capitalist production being totally unguided and really
just happening based on a bunch of forces we can't even totally pin down yeah exactly it loves to
like defenders of capitalism love to promote this idea that you know capitalism really gives
structure and organization to our lives and that through the invisible hand of the free market,
things work themselves out. And, you know, if you take away that market, if you take away
that invisible hand, then, you know, you'll see real anarchy as there's no ability to structure
the market and structure what needs to be produced, et cetera. And I think perhaps in earlier times,
central planning was made much more difficult by the lack of instant communication that we
currently have. But as technology is developed and we're looking at, imagine if the Soviet
Union had all of the technology that we currently have today, the ability to instantaneously
communicate across space and time and plan production about, you know, using that technology,
it would be much easier than it was at that time.
And a lot of the problems with central planning that people point to and say, hey, socialism
doesn't work, you can't plan this stuff, et cetera, I think can be alleviated or outright
eliminated by the introduction of modern technology.
I think that's an important part of this as well.
But certainly the anarchy of production under capitalism,
them produces, as Allison said, a bunch of really sparkling gadgets, right, consumer goods.
We have 300,000 different types of potato chips and deodorants, right?
But look how much food we waste.
You know, look how much food rots in the garbage bins behind restaurants.
Look at how the anarchy of oil production causes a complete destabilization of our environment.
And so maybe the anarchy of production was really good at a certain time in historical
development and certainly it allowed for an explosion of consumer goods but at this point in history
when we're facing down global problems like climate change which i'll get to in a second here
the anarchy of production actually starts to become an existential threat and we have to overcome
that um in order to to you know avoid i think the the fate that we're staring down the barrel of
right now if this anarchy of production is not you know ended and we can we can implement some
sort of rational planning that does not care about how much profit you can generate in a competitive
free marketplace, but rather cares about how can we organize production and distribution such that
the most amount of goods that people need are given to them and that people all over the world
can have the highest quality of life possible. That incentive system of structuring your society
to ensuring that everybody has their basic needs met and has the highest quality of life
that we can possibly give them is antithetical to capitalist production.
It can't happen, and whenever you talk about planning, capitalists hate it, because what it means is that you'd have to get rid of the anarchy of production. You'd have to get rid of the 300,000 types of potato chips and instead use that productive capacity and that distributive capacity to ensure that human beings had, I don't know, health care and education and childcare, for example.
Yeah, definitely. And I think this leads into the next question well, too, because one thing that I think Ingalls gets at is that that anarchy holds capitalism back, right? Engels points out that this is why monopolies form or why capitalists try to make state intervention into markets is because it's really unstable and it creates a crisis over and over again for capitalism when you don't have centralized planning that's actually tooled towards making your society work in the first place. So the next question that I had is that,
Ingalls argues that state control over industry is not the same thing as socialism. And he says
that state regulation and planning can actually be a way that capitalist attempt to quell the more
turbulent effects of capitalist contradictions while not actually resolving those contradictions.
So what I'm interested in is what implications this has for socialist strategy today
as it relates to the capitalist state and capitalist state projects of regulations and
interventing into the market. Yeah, I think one thing that this really calls the mind
is the way that liberals and social Democrats and increasingly these people are calling
themselves socialists, how what they do is not fundamentally about transcending class
society or transcending capitalism as such, but is rather about maintaining it through
regulation, right? The idea of social Democrats and liberals, for example, is that the
capitalist system is worth protecting the political institutions that it vomits up are
worth defending and therefore we don't want to transcend capitalism we actually want to make it work
better and that requires regulation etc fDR right the new deal this was after the great
depression and you know fDR did a whole bunch of you know enlarge the size of government to make
sure that the anarchy of capitalist production doesn't lead to such a horrific crisis again and
what was he called by the leaders of industry and the mainstream media at that time he was called
a socialist a bolshevik a communist etc but when they asked fdr at the end of
his life, what was your greatest accomplishment? What did FDR say? He said, my greatest accomplishment
was saving capitalism. So the social Democrats, the liberals who like to put on this facade of
being super progressive, and maybe they even might convince themselves that they really do want
to transcend capitalism through these mechanisms. And certainly there is an importance to reforming
and regulating the free market so that it doesn't hurt people as much as it can and as much as it often
does, right? I'm not saying that all forms of regulation and reforms are meaningless and should
just be dismissed. Of course not. But you have to see what's actually going on and how the state
in a capitalist context actually serves to bolster it and perpetuate it, not overcome it,
because it literally can't. The other thing that brought to mind was thinking about China, right?
now China has no I mean I'm trying to phrase my words here we'll edit this out here
so one thing about China is that it's a one-party rule and there are benefits to that
as much as we're taught to recoil at that term the benefits of that is that it doesn't
necessarily go through the horrific you know ups and downs booms and bust cycles on these tight
cycles that we're dealing with here in the US it doesn't happen as often in China and moreover
they can actually plan long term in a way that social or in a way that capitalist democracies
literally can't. Not only are we talking about the underlying economic situations I just touched
on and the role that the state serves, but even bourgeois electoral systems has this
chaotic spin to it where because we're dealing with Democrats and then Republicans and
Democrats from this back and forth thing, you can have somebody like an Obama that comes up
and tries to do the bare minimum to basically protect capitalism, right?
when it comes to climate change.
How can we enter into agreements?
How can we build up a green economy, et cetera?
Try to blunt the sharper edges of capitalism.
But then the next election, the system vomits up a Trump who says,
forget all of that, toss all of that to side.
I don't even believe climate change exists.
And then now, let's say a new Democrat gets elected, comes back in.
They have to start from scratch trying to address these problems.
So on every level, you know, the bourgeois democracy doesn't work for long-term planning.
And China, you know, for whatever you're.
views on it, whether it's socialist or state cap, whatever you want to talk about China as,
you have to see that the ability to plan long term is something that China has been able to
accomplish in a way that the U.S. and Western democracies can't and won't ever be able to
accomplish. So I do think that's important. And I also wanted to touch on the idea of markets,
right? If we're talking about the implications that this has for socialist strategy,
and if we're talking about socialism as a process, not a list of things you check off,
then the question of markets comes up.
Are markets inherently capitalistic?
Does a society that has any market presence at all
immediately exclude itself from the label socialism?
Or are markets simply a tool?
And in the transitionary period,
as long as we assume that there's an actual dictatorship
of the proletariat, right?
The working class is in charge of the state,
that markets themselves can become tools
in a broader strategy of transition.
How does that strike you, Alison?
and do you think that that's more or less right, wrong?
What are your thoughts?
Yeah, so I think there's two questions there that I want to comment on.
So one is, obviously, the China issue is very tricky,
and this is where probably even we personally disagree on this question to some extent.
But I think, yeah, the focus on how not having the political instability of capitalism
alongside the development of productive forces is a really good takeaway there, right?
Because even the liberal impulse that might, you know, sort of get over some of the contradictions
is instantly undone when you have a new president or a new politician.
And so part of what's important about proletarian rule, and again, people will debate whether
or not China is that.
But what's important about it is that you have a party that is stable and constantly
in place, which can make sure that productive forces are being developed and are being
developed towards socialist ends, which I think then leads into the next question, which is
important, which is, yeah, do we just get rid of markets?
Is it impossible to have markets in a socialist economy?
And I think the answer to that historically is no, that, you know, we can't simply make a complete
break from them and that markets can't exist alongside socialism. The question of socialism isn't,
you know, one day we have a revolution and we immediately get rid of everything related to
capitalism. It's we have a revolution and we create a dictatorship of the proletariat that will
push society and the productive forces of society towards the end of communism and proletarian rule,
where Engel says the proletariat eventually abolishes itself as proletariat through this process.
But in order to do that, especially in places which haven't seen total capitalist production,
it can be necessary to maintain aspects of capitalist productive forces
in order to increase the economic viability there so socialism can be built.
And there's a very dangerous utopianism, I think,
that thinks that we can just break from all of this immediately get rid of markets
and have a perfect, pure socialist economy tomorrow.
When the real question for us isn't whether or not we make that complete break, but whether or not a dictatorship of the proletariat has been established to guide the transitionary phase.
Right. Yeah, exactly. And it's not only underdeveloped countries, too, like if tomorrow, you know, there is a socialist revolution of proletarian dictatorship of the proletariat was established in the U.S.
On day one, you couldn't just say, destroy the entire economy and start from scratch.
It would be a transitionary process where key industries slowly were, or quickly, hopefully, like health care and oil production, etc., were nationalized straight out the gate, but certain markets would still have to operate when it comes to certain consumer goods.
I mean, you don't want to cause chaos in a transitionary period.
You don't want to just burn everything down with no plan on how to strategically and systematically move forward.
You have a set of goals, you prioritize those goals, and you go about meeting those goals one by one.
And that's going to mean that some, you know, leftovers from the capitalist state, even leftovers that we find repulsive, will still exist and we'll have to wrestle with them in a strategic and tactful way.
And it's really unhelpful in that context if somebody says, idealistically, hey, I'm inherently against the idea of this thing that you're using to transition.
Therefore, this isn't actually real socialism.
You have to, you have to cause, I mean, what would the argument would be you would have to cause severe economic chaos and, and, and, and, you have to cause.
throw people's lives in complete turmoil in order for us to establish overnight the sort of
society that we want. And I think Marxists are just not willing to throw that many people
into the gutter just because we have ideas about how things should be on day one. And I think
that's important to think about not only when you're analyzing other countries and their quote
unquote level of socialism, but also when you're thinking about our own socialist strategy here
in the imperial core. So next question. I think one of the least
helpful strains within Marxism, in my opinion, is the overly deterministic and mechanistic
strains that I think you see less and less of today, but which have been dominant at certain times
in the past. So, Alison, in what ways, if at all, do you think angles, and this work specifically
contributes to that strain in the Marxist tradition? Yeah, so this would be my one concern with this
text, I think, which I think is a really great text, and it's partially an interpretive question, right? I think
in this text, Ingalls, frequently it sounds like he's not talking about the proletariat as the
revolutionary force, but production itself and the productive forces as the revolutionary force.
And if we were to make a crude reading of this text, one might almost get the sense that
capitalism is necessarily deterministically going to go away absent any individual revolutionary
strategy because of the fact that the productive forces, as Engel says, are constantly revolting
against capitalism. And I think if we read the text carefully, that's not what Engel's claim is,
because he also says that the proletariat's antagonism towards the bourgeoisie expresses
that contradiction. So the presence of those classes and their struggle against each other is
important, but I can really easily see how someone who's not paying attention to that
could come away with a very deterministic read of Marxism from this text. I'm kind of reminded
of the analytical Marxist tradition and this particular theorist Cohen, who argues that the Marxist
theory of history isn't so much a theory of class struggle, but a theory of productive forces
developing over time. And I see how you could come away with that mistake. And so when
reading this text, I think it's very important that we acknowledge that Ingalls is saying that
the productive forces and the socialized productive forces don't exist on their own. Those have a
relationship to the proletariat as a class who expresses the intro.
of socialized production, and that socialized production can only really win that struggle
through proletarian revolution. And I think that's an important thing to read into this text.
Definitely. And just to the general claim that Marxism is deterministic or mechanistic,
I think you could actually go back to Marx and angles and find a lot of evidence to the contrary.
I mean, Marx believes that insofar as this transition to a socialist state of affairs,
a transition away from capitalism is to happen at all, it's going to happen through people.
And also, it's not guaranteed.
He talks about the, you know, it could just as well end in the common ruin of both classes.
Rosa Luxembourg talks about socialism or barbarism.
We're looking down the face in our own time of an insurgent fascism and climate change.
And if we don't get our shit together soon, it's not that these things will naturally,
organically take place, but it's that we have to become conscious of ourselves as members of the proletariat,
right, the class becoming conscious of itself and understanding what its historical role is and then beginning to organize along that basis.
So this can happen, but it requires people to understand the situation where we come from,
understand what needs to happen in the future, i.e. be guided by theory and to take it upon ourselves to be the mechanisms by which history pushes in this direction.
We can't just sit back and think, well, with technology advancing, the productive forces will change such that socialism is an inevitability
in the next century or whatever.
First of all, we don't have that time.
And second of all, you fundamentally don't understand the mechanism by which a proletarian
revolution comes to the fore.
And that is through human beings being conscious of their role as the proletariat and, you know,
behaving thusly.
And I think that's essential, not just for this text, but for that critique of Marxism broadly.
Definitely.
Okay, so let's see.
The next question that I had, and so this is sparked by the recent,
JMP article, this ruthless criticism of all that exists, which deals a lot with this question of
Marxism as science, and I'm really interested in the relationship between science and philosophy
and Marxism. So the question that I have here is, what is the relationship between science and
philosophy? English, or sorry, Ingalls distinguishes Marx from the philosophical projects
which preceded him, so metaphysics. But does this mean that Marx breaks from philosophy in favor of
science or does Marx create a scientific philosophy? Okay, well, first of all, Alison, this is a huge
question. Why'd you ask me? Right. No, it's very, very difficult. It's one that I've struggled with
a lot in my life. I came up not only, you know, through philosophy, but I also was very into science.
I, you know, I operated in a neuroscience lab as an undergrad, and so science and philosophy were
always very close to me, but you always heard this claim that Marxism is not a science. And, you know,
to say that Marxism is science has almost met with, with, you know, mockery, like how absurd?
How could you say that, et cetera?
And I'm not going to be able to address every single aspect of this argument in this one little
question because, again, this could be 10 episodes.
And on Revolutionary Left Radio, we are having JMP come on at the end of the month and talk about
his new essay and really flesh a lot of this out.
But I think a good starting point is to ask, what is science?
And I went on, you know, online and found just a couple of the most succinct.
non-controversial definitions of science as my starting point.
One definition was a method of procedure consisting in systematic observation, measurement, and
experiment, and the formulation, testing, and modification of hypotheses.
And another definition was the intellectual and practical activity encompassing the systematic
study of the structure and behavior of the physical and natural world through observation
and experiment.
And then the question asks itself, how does this differ from philosophy?
Well, in my opinion, philosophy is much broader and is not confined by the scientific method.
Philosophy can engage in a whole array of speculation without ever needing to feel tied to empirical evidence.
It can engage, for example, in the formal deconstruction of logic.
It can talk about the best way to live one's life.
It can talk about the existence of God, how many angels dance on the head of a pin,
and it can even take a meta-prospective on science itself,
examining many of the assumptions and conceptual framings within science.
So philosophy and science are deeply related, they stem from the same basic intellectual and reflective urge in the human animal, and they often inform one another, but they're not the same thing.
So taking a step back and looking at the problem, given these two basic definitions, it would seem as if historical materialism falls far more neatly into the category of science than philosophy, as it is dedicated to the systematic observation of history and society.
It then analyzes and researches the empirical data of political economy and history in order to formulate its hypotheses.
It does have a mechanism by which to test those hypotheses in the empirical natural world, namely proletarian revolutions and class struggle.
It records the intricate data and empirical outcome of said revolutions in order to test its hypotheses against the evidence,
and then it modifies and or keeps aspect of the theory that were successful and roots out and discards aspects of the theory that have been proven to,
fail in the crucible of those class struggles.
It takes those lessons and then it formulates new hypotheses, right?
It updates theory, if you will.
And then it tests those again in the crucible of the next proletarian revolution.
So in this way, Marxism, unlike other purely philosophical, theoretical tendencies,
has, in my opinion, an in-belt mechanism by which it is constantly updated and tethered
to empirical outcomes.
Marxism is inherently open-ended and continuously being updated by new data and experiments
in class struggle.
It is not confined by cultural conditioning in the way that speculative philosophy often is,
which is why we have East Asian philosophy and European philosophy and indigenous philosophy
and feminist philosophy, et cetera, et cetera.
But we don't have these geographical and cultural qualifiers to science, right?
There is no distinction between Chinese science and German science.
It's just science.
The way that sciences contextualize, how it's applied by certain societies, et cetera,
does and often has led to the tool of science being abused,
and pressed into the service of, you know, oppression, colonialism, et cetera.
But it's from within science that those deviations can be made to, or can be seen to be
failures, right?
They're failures of science and they're rectified by science.
Think of phrenology or race science, for example.
So in the same way, or did you have something to say there?
Oh, no, I was just a great with how good that example is.
Okay, yeah.
And in the same way, Marxism has within it mechanisms by which it can be developed internally,
and its past failures are short-sightedness.
can be overcome. So both science and Marxism can be held in a dogmatic way, right? We all know
dogmatic Marxists who adhere to doctrine more than dialectical materialism, and we all know how
science is often fetishized and used dogmatically by people like the new atheist, for example,
or technocratic neoliberal's who solution to everything is more Silicon Valley tech
startups and more apps. Hell, there's even a whole movement based around overcoming death by
uploading one's consciousness into a computer. The idea that science can solve all of our social
problems, including the problem of death, is an example of dogmatically fetishizing science.
But just because something can be used dogmatically by the ignorant doesn't mean that the
thing in and of itself inevitably gives rise to dogmatism or that it is in and of itself
a dogmatic approach to the world, right? So ultimately, I do think Marxism broke away from
philosophy and towards science. When he said, when Marx said, the philosophers have hitherto
only interpreted the world. The point is to change it. I think he signaled his
frustration with the limitations of philosophy proper and realize that only a scientific approach
to these questions can give us the clarity, direction, and open-endedness that we needed to fight back
against our historical rulers.
So I'm going to wrap it up here, but given the, I think this is an important part too.
This talks about the distinctions between hard and soft sciences, and this catches a lot of people
up.
I know in my earlier periods of development, it caught me up a lot.
But given the vague, hard-to-control and cacophonous nature of society and history and
history, compared to, say, physics and chemistry, where the variables being studied are much
more precise, isolatable, and can more easily be tested inside the confines of an actual laboratory
where the scientists can control the conditions and variables of the experiment, there is an
urge for people to set hard boundaries between what we know is hard and soft sciences.
But this dichotomy is ultimately unhelpful and arbitrary, as it merely props up a wall between
certain types of things studied, not walls inside the field of science itself, which has no
such boundaries. Science only has to end when the thing in question doesn't exist inside the natural
world or can't otherwise be scrutinized according to the scientific method. Marxism does not make
this error. Marxism is all about analyzing the material and natural world in an attempt to
empirically investigate the internal laws by which societies developed and their connections
to the ways in which human beings materially produce and distribute the necessities of life.
The goal of Marxism, as is the goal of all sciences, is to demystify the natural
world and provide natural explanations for natural phenomena. This is a criteria for science, which
I think Marxism absolutely meets. Alison? Yeah, I mean, I think that really said it fantastically.
And I think very importantly to this distinction between hard and soft science, which is where
a lot of more sort of crass positivists, I feel like push back on this question, you know,
that serves a ideological bourgeois function to make sure that science can never get applied to
the political in the first place, right?
And to create this false division that stops us from doing exactly that demystification,
which is our task.
And so I think Marxism as a science really offers something revolutionary for saying,
no, science can be applied to the political and has to be applied to the political and concludes
in favor of socialism.
Yeah.
And I just want to, before we move on in the next question, I think the issue of falsification
is really important here.
and in this
in the J. Malfiad Paul's latest essay
it's entitled the ruthless criticism
of all that exists. Marxism as a science
I really highly recommend people go
and check that out
but talking about falsification
he writes, this is JMP writing
in that essay he writes
Reactionaries and liberals who reject Marxism
because they laugh at the notion
that it could ever claim to be a science
might understand what is at stake
Carl Popper theorized science
so as to exclude Marxism
and place it on the same level as the failed scientific attempts of Freud and psychoanalysis.
As I have pointed out elsewhere, though, Popper unintentionally rendered a small service to Marxism
thanks to his unscientific grasp of social categories.
His conceptualization of falsifiability did not exclude historical materialism from the privileged domain of the sciences,
but because he was too lazy to grasp Marxism as a historical process,
cinched its inclusion.
Historical materialism can indeed lay claim to falsifiability as one of its craft
criteria for scientific veracity, i.e. revolutions are the crucibles in which the unfolding
theoretical terrain is tested and whereas hypotheses can possibly be rendered false. And this is how
we judge its development as a discrete science. So there you have JMP reacting to the Paparian
critique of Marxism that is not falsifiable. And so what I took that as is like, hey, Brett, could you
think of some things that would make Marxism falsifiable? Like what are some things that could
happen that would say, hey, Marxism is either totally wrong or fundamentally flawed and it needs
to be updated, right? And so I came up with some ideas and I'm going to bounce them off you
and, you know, Allison doesn't know what these are. So I would like to hear her like, you know,
intuitive take on it, but also people listening. If you find any like flaws in what I'm about
to say here, bring it to my attention. I think they're interesting. But again, this idea is how can
Marxism be falsified? What could happen that would say, okay, Marxism is definitely fundamentally
flawed. One example, anarcho-capitalism gets established somewhere, right? Because a core
claim of Marxism is that the state is a manifestation of class society and that capitalism
literally cannot exist without it. You might be able to start up the beginning, the beginning
possibilities of anarcho-capitalism, right? You might, like, have a new territory and go there and say,
okay, no state, no government, no bureaucracy, we're just going to let the free market dictate
everything, but that will either crumble into revolution or the bourgeoisie will find ways to
to, you know, protect, you have like little private fiefdoms where the rich and the wealthy
can, you know, defend their own interests through private security, or you would have more
than likely the bourgeoisie coming together and establishing the basics of a state that would give
rise to more state, etc. We talked about FDR earlier in capitalist crisis and how the state
is an essential component in correcting it.
So anarcho-capitalism is implemented and succeeds over a period of time, Marxism is false.
Another example, if liberal democracy successfully mediates class conflict out of existence, right?
If bourgeois democratic institutions over the next, you know, a couple of decades or a century or whatever,
somehow manage to overcome class contradiction, to mediate class conflict, and to take away that as an historical engine of progress,
then it would say, hey, Marxism, you have something fundamentally wrong with you.
How is liberalism, the ideology of capitalism, able to mediate class conflict out of existence?
So that's one way liberals could also prove us wrong.
Another one, a non-Marxist theoretical tendency successfully builds and defends a global proletarian movement, right?
Some tendency on the left completely divorced fundamentally from Marxism actually goes about, you know, creating and developing, leading a world revolution and be able to defend.
defend it, suppress the capitalist oppressors, transition towards communism. If somebody using
a non-Marxist approach can do that, and even a lot of tendencies on the left are really rooted
in Marxism. And so you have to be very careful here. You can't just say, oh, I call myself this
tendency, but I'm fundamentally using Marxist analysis. But if somebody that truly rejected
Marxism built and defended a global proletarian movement, that would be like, wow, Marxism
wasn't the best tendency on display. It wasn't actually scientific. Somebody else came up
with ideas out of the blue and we're able to, you know, compete with Marxism as the leader of
the proletarian movement. And then lastly, this might be a little bit more of a stretch, but I actually
don't think it is. If fascism and imperialism are rooted out of all capitalist societies, never
to return, right? You talk about Lenin talks about fascism being capitalism and decay or
imperialism being the highest stage of capitalism. These two things from a Marxist analysis,
fascism and imperialism, are fundamentally parts of capitalism. And so if you could root those
two things out, never for them to return inside the confines of a capitalist society. It might not
overturn Marxism completely, but would certainly strike a heavy blow against some of the
absolute pillars of Marxist analysis and Marxist theory. So those are just a few ways in which
Marxism could be falsified. What do you think about that, Alison?
Yeah, I think those are really clever. I mean, I think each of those challenges a central
tenet of Marxism, especially the first two challenge are central views on the state and the state's
relationship to class contradictions. And yeah, I think if you prove those things, yeah,
that would probably falsify the Marxist claim. And actually, yeah, I think that last example is
really good, actually, because I think it's pretty central to our theory that fascism and
imperialism cannot be separated from capitalism and our necessary developments. And yeah,
somehow as unimaginable as it is to me, you and to accomplish that, it probably would falsify it.
But, yeah, no one has come close to accomplishing any of those claims. So, exactly.
Exactly. I thought that was a fun thought experiment, and I really, if people want to, like, add more ways in which Marxism could be falsified, I'd be really fascinated because even, like, I have friends who are, you know, post-doctorates and neuroscience, like high, high-level scientists that are my friends that, you know, adhere to the Paparian concept of falsifiability and exclude Marxism on those grounds. And so, okay, we can play your game. You tell us those are the terms of the game. I'll play it and I'll still show you how you're wrong, Popper. And so I think that's an important thing.
But this also leads into the last question for part two.
And I think this sort of sums up what we were talking about in the last question.
And my question to Allison is this, why is understanding Marxism as a science and not just another theoretical system among many essential to the integrity of historical materialism and the Marxist project as a whole, in your opinion?
Sure.
So, yeah, big question as well.
And I think I'm going to have to draw on the answer that J&P gives in that newest article.
one, the obvious reason is that this is what gives Marxism acclaim to the truth, right?
If Marxism isn't scientific, then it's one more interpretive philosophy among a huge
catalog of interpretive philosophies. And this is very frequently how we see Marxism get
treated in the humanities, right? Where Marxism or Fucodianism are treated as just different
interpretive modes that we might take up that give different angles and ways of analyzing
the world that aren't themselves totalizing or scientific. So part of the reason that it's really
essential for us to say Marxism is scientific is because it gives us a reason to favor Marxism
over these other methods and techniques that have been developed by people like Foucault. So I think
that's a very, very important reason. But also, I think that you can't separate Marxism from its
claim that it is scientific, right? One of the starting points that Marx and Ingalls make is
this is a science and we can demonstrate it's scientific and this is not made from fundamental principles
but from an analysis of the world and again what ingles calls the stubborn facts and so in one sense
I think it's also just sort of rude to the legacy of ingles and marks to say okay we'll adopt
Marxism but we won't adopt the scientific view of Marxism because central to Marxism is that claim
to science itself and the claim that that can differentiate it and make it better than the utopian theories
which came before it and also which have preceded it.
So I think that you really can't disentangle that claim
from what the Marxist methodology is.
Yeah, and just sort of wrap up this part two
and especially talking about Marxism as a science.
I was talking on Twitter today about how, you know,
me and Allison are doing work on this front in this episode
and then I'm having JMP to do a whole episode on Rev Left
because I think that this is such an important issue
and I know from my own development, right?
I'm about to turn 30 years old.
I've been a radical for over a decade, and a lot of that radical period of my life, I've been
fundamentally confused about this exact topic.
I've refused to, you know, even when I started calling myself a Marxist, I said, yeah,
but it's actually not a science, you know.
I even contented myself with saying, well, it's a scientific approach, you know, whatever.
But what you're doing is you're seating the ground to the enemies of Marxism, and you're losing,
as Allison said, what makes Marxism the thing that we uphold, which is it's, it's,
It's inherent superiority of methodology compared to all other tendencies.
It's not just a set of ideas about the world that we came up with in a vacuum.
It's actually a methodology and a scientific assessment of proletarian struggle over time,
which then can be synthesized into new theory, which guides our actual activity on the ground day to day.
And that is an essential component of Marxism and of the proletarian movement.
And to say, even as a Marxist, that is not actually a science, is to basically say that Marxism,
is just another, you know, thing you can choose between.
It's just another option on the table, whatever fits your subjective fancy, go ahead and
pick it up and you can claim that that is just as legitimate as anything else, where I think
so many Marxist theorists and so many Marxist revolutionaries have put in such huge amounts
of work really applying the science of Marxism to understand their conditions and then operating
successfully in those conditions because they took Marxism serious as a science.
And that is our strength.
And to hand that over is to cripple what makes Marxism so useful and what has led so many movements on every continent and on the planet to pick up Marxism as a tool by which to liberate themselves from national oppression or to build socialism in their part of the world.
And so, yeah, I think it's a fundamental pillar.
And people, if you're still, if you call yourself a Marxist and you're still fundamentally confused about this issue, I don't blame you.
It's very difficult.
but Allison and I are doing work to try to illuminate that,
and I really encourage you to go take this concept seriously
and dive into it and learn for yourself
why it's an essential part of what we're doing here.
Awesome. Yeah, no, I strongly agree with that.
And also sympathize with historically not understanding this question
and having to work really hard diving into what Marks and Ingalls say
to come to terms with the question of science.
Do we want to go ahead and move on to the application of theory section?
Absolutely, yeah.
So now we're going to go ahead and move over to Part 3.
which is our application of theory. So again, what's really important for us here isn't just
that we're giving you theoretical explanations, theoretical texts, and then we stop there.
The question is, what does that mean strategically for us as communists? Communism is not
having the right beliefs. It's the real movement for the abolition of the present state of
things, and we are supposed to, as communists, be a part of that. So we want to move beyond just
having this theory to how it applies to our strategy and our work that we're doing today,
And I think this text can do that.
So the first real point of application that I had is I think this text speaks very, very interestingly
to debates about the capitalist state, reform, and regulation, and how we relate to it.
So while there is a large movement of self-described socialists on the left who want to just sort of
reform the capital state, we as Marxists need to push back against that.
As Brett said, it's not that all reforms are useless or that there's no place for reform.
But I think what's crucial that we get from Ingalls in this text is that the drive to reform and regulate capitalism isn't just not socialism.
Sometimes it can itself be a way of recuperating and trying to save capitalism.
In response to crises, it is not enough to simply paper over the contradiction.
We have to resolve it through proletarian revolution.
And the FDR example that Brett brought up is really a fantastic example of this.
You can save capitalism by socializing certain things.
and by regulating markets and pushing back against the anarchy of production.
And strategies which call themselves socialist, but ultimately don't have a plan for socialist revolution,
won't get us anywhere for resolving the contradictions which are creating crisis in the first place.
And I think this is a real thing that needs to be considered in the context of communist organizing in the United States.
There are times when we will overlap with social Democrats and calling for strategic reforms that will just literally save people's lives.
But we need to make sure in all of our work that we're doing that we don't confuse those reforms or those regulations on capitalism for socialism itself, and that we make sure that they're strategically adopted and not instances where they can actually be used to rehabilitate capitalism and keep it moving on its destructive historical path.
We need to remember that revolution is the only actual way to resolve these things.
And that proletarian rule, not as some abstract thing, but as a real concrete political reality is the only path going forward.
And all of our strategic organizing work needs to be geared towards that end.
Yeah, absolutely.
And I'll just say sort of like incredibly well said and piggybacking off of that, I wanted to point out that, you know, a lot of times people will online and stuff go really hard against people like AOC or Bernie Sanders for using the term socialist.
And, you know, there's really a hard line leftist that will just have no mercy when they criticize.
these folks and there's people that's like, yeah, I get it, you're right, but at the same time,
they're trying to make the system a little bit better for people, and in the meantime, they're
destigmatizing the term socialism. But here's the problem with that, is that socialism as a term
may be destigmatized through people like AOC and Bernie Sanders, right? And that may ultimately
prove to be beneficial to people who want actual socialism, but at the very same time that it
destigmatizes it because it's liberals claiming to be socialists, it dilutes the meaning
of socialism, and it confuses and muddies the water around the discourse concerning socialism.
So when you see comrades going hard as fuck against AOC or Bernie because of something they
said about socialism, it is not because they're purists who just want to shit on everything
that isn't really revolutionary, but it's that they're taking it upon themselves to do
the refining and clarifying work of concepts so that these terms don't get taken away from
us and made into something they're not. No, socialism is not the fire department. You know,
So, and it's important that we push back on that.
At the same time, we can be leading these reforms, pushing these reformers leftward
and making them, you know, have these reforms be more robust and meet people's material
needs.
Radicals have always led reforms in this country and elsewhere.
But at the same time, that conceptual work of clarifying what these words actually mean
and that, hey, theory is actually important.
And, hey, it is actually important that we don't get the definition of socialism wrong
now that so many people are finally for the first time in decades opening their
ears to the idea. And so I would urge people to just have more patience with your comrades
when you see them working on one of these two fronts, right? I think that's important.
Okay, so moving on to my first point. I was really thinking about the metaphysical outlook,
right, and ways that we could really teach people what it looks like by tying it to contemporary
situations, situations that people that live today would immediately understand as like, oh, yeah,
I'm familiar with that.
And so the question I asked myself was what sort of errors are produced today
when one assumes the static metaphysical outlook over the process-oriented, a dialectical
outlook, as Engel says in quotes, in the contemplation of individual things, it forgets the
connection between them.
And so that is, you know, sort of angles quick and fast definition of the metaphysical outlook
and its problem.
So I was thinking some examples that we'd all know that would reflect this.
And I think the obvious example is one, bourgeois individualism where atomized workers and consumers operating according to their own will and quote-unquote rational self-interests,
detached from responsibility, a sense of community, and a cooperative economic environment have to compete in order to gain and keep resources.
So, I mean, you know, this is just one way that all of society and the way that wealth is produced is social, but under liberalism, under the metaphysical out,
outlook. These things are reduced to individuals. And we talk about individual rights, the individual
right of a capitalist to own a factory and profit off his workers, etc. But that individualization
affects all spheres of our life and the sense of alienation and lack of community that we often
feel, I think is a product to some extent of that sort of outlook. Number two would be the idea
that capitalism and bourgeois democracies are the end-all, be-all of economic and political
systems. It's just a matter of refining them. I think,
Lots of liberals, lots of people invested in the status quo have that idea, people that are invested in capitalism and in bourgeois democracy, really do, even if they won't admit it or think through it consciously, assume that this is the best that we can do. And it's just a matter of, you know, blunting the edges and making it work a little better as time goes on, but that there's nothing beyond this. That idea of, like, capitalism is human nature is basically a call to say there's no more progress needed. We've achieved what we need to achieve. Now we just need to make it as good as we can.
The third idea that I came up with is a liberal conceptions of truth, property, and justice.
A lot of times, bourgeois rights, liberal conceptions of rights, liberal conceptions of abstract ideas like truth and justice and property are talked about as if they exist outside of real conditions in some platonic realm.
And by individuating these things and saying we stand for truth and property and justice, but you don't actually analyze them in their connections with how they actually operate in class society is one way that this metaphysical mode of thought.
infects our world today. The next one is the post-Cold War triumphalism that announced the end of
history. I mean, the end of history, to claim that history has come to an end, is a complete
abandonment of dialectics as such, and is this idea that we can segment human history with an
end point, in the same way that you place an arbitrary, you know, block on when the person lives
or dies, they're trying to do that with history itself. The next example is, since class struggle
implies a process and a continuous one in the Marxist tradition, it must be either de-emphasized
or ignored completely in bourgeois culture and politics in favor of something more static
like the reliance on enduring bourgeois institutions to resolve competing interests, i.e. to
resolve fundamental contradictions. As Engel says, the lies of the bourgeois economy are that the
interest of capital and labor are the same and that the universal harmony and prosperity will be
the consequence of unbridled competition.
so we hear that all the time to this day next one is that the state is often seen as something inherent to societies and civilization and not as a manifestation of underlying class antagonisms which develop change and can be transcended along with the need for a state as such i think the the liberal conception of the state rejects the idea that it that the state is fundamentally a manifestation of class society and second to last is that our subjectivity is dehistoricized and our behavior is
desocialized and tied to one's individual and presumably inherent natural characteristics and moral
fortitude.
This outlook results in justification for punitive approaches to crime and moralizing approaches
to poverty.
This is behind the bootstrap rhetoric, for example, and focuses our justice system on
punishment rather than rehabilitation while refusing to acknowledge how underlying
socioeconomic conditions are connected to and give rise to poverty and crime in the first
place. And then finally, and this applies to many leftists as well, I think, just like the entire
world is a process, so too is the transition to socialism. It doesn't happen overnight. And when
it does happen in this or that part of the world, it only begins a process of more change.
You know, they have to defend their gains. They have to struggle with contradictions that arise
in the transitionary period, etc. Socialism, contrary to the way that many talk and think about
it is not a state of affairs that one reaches or a list of things one checks off, but is a
process out of capitalism and toward communism. To view socialism as anything but a process like
this is an example, in my opinion, of a static, metaphysical idealism. And so those are just
some of the examples I came up with to sort of, you know, to make contemporary this mode of
thought and this work and show how it still operates with us today and how, in fact, it's a huge
part of capitalism overall.
Definitely, yeah. And I think
it's so relevant for the left
today, especially. I mean, one thing
that I think is really crucial, too, is this idea
of socialism as a process,
right, and so much
progress that is being made in socialist
development in a lot of instances does get
rejected for not being seen as this perfect
instant theoretical break
from capitalism. And that's a huge
problem because it takes away our ability to
learn from attempts as socialist
development, even when they don't work out,
super well. If we just completely dismiss them out of hand because they don't live up to our
utopian interpretation of socialism, then they're not productively useful for us getting better
strategy. And I think another point where this sort of metaphysical idealism comes in is often
how the left, and more the liberal left, will talk about identity without focusing on how
identity is constructed through social processes, and instead taking identity to be something
that is just sort of an apolitical inherent fact to individual people, rather than a reflect
of structures that have relationships to capitalism.
Yeah, incredibly good point. Absolutely.
All right, you want to go to the next one?
Yeah, so the other thing I wanted to talk about somewhat is this idea that socialism isn't
really about coming up with the right ideas from the perfect deductible truths,
but comes as a result from dealing with, again, the stubborn facts of reality and interacting
with them and theorizing from those.
And I think what's really important here is that this ain't that.
theory alone isn't enough and that the goal of socialist isn't to produce the right theory,
but actual mass work that begins with the realities of the masses is really the task at hand.
And emphasizing that mass work doesn't mean that we get rid of theory, but it rather shows
the relationship between theory and praxis in the first place. And this is obviously an important
theme in Marxism. But a lot of the times, I think especially in the imperial core, where we have
these very academic versions of Marxism and socialism, we treat this like it's about having the right
ideas. And it's about coming up with the perfect, irrefutable theory, regardless of sort of how
that theory plays out in practice and in organizing and in strategy. And what Ingalls is telling us is
that this is actually an idealist way to approach the world. And that Marxism, by its nature of being
scientific, doesn't start by trying to come up with the ideas first, but it embeds itself within the processes
of revolution and within revolutionary organizing, and it comes to theoretical insights from that.
It's the movement of the proletariat as a class that gives us the insight into capitalism in order
to critically approach it and figure out how to overcome it. And I think this is something that
the U.S. left is really bad about, actually. We have a lot of tendencies whose distinctions are defined
not on the basis of the kind of work they're doing or the scientific credibility of their approach
to capitalism, but by a list of doctrines that they believe and have tried to divine from
fundamental principles in the abstract. And that's an interesting way, I guess, to look at the
world that's very philosophical, but it's not a materialist or a scientific way of understanding
the left today. And I think, you know, both of us are members of organizations that have
relationships to base building and this dual power approach that sort of says it's not so much
about having the perfect ideas as doing the mass work on the ground to create the conditions
were proletariat revolution. And when we go out and we do that, when we're working with
the masses, when we're hearing their needs, and when we're synthesizing those with Marxist
approaches to strategy, that's when we're going to start developing scientific insights into
capitalism today. This is the insight from this text that I really want to hit home today.
It's not enough for you to listen to this podcast and say, okay, I understand Marxism as a science
now, and that's that. And it's another intellectual thing to check off. If you take what this
episode is saying seriously, it means you need to go get out there and be doing
work organizing involved in the actual revolutionary movements that exist today and helping to build
that movement now. And it's only then that you actually understand what it means for Marxism to be
scientific. Absolutely. And I would just add to that is that, you know, as you alluded to,
there is this dialectical relationship between theory and practice. One informs the other and turns
back around and informs the other, et cetera. So that dialectical thinking, even in our own organizing,
is absolutely essential and a crucial part of of praxis of engaging in actual work is also coming
back after engaging with that work and synthesizing new ways forward as an organization.
You don't necessarily need or even can synthesize brand new revolutionary theory that's
universalizable globally, but in your own little, you know, communities where you're organizing,
taking stock of the material conditions and letting that influence the programs that you create,
then going out, carrying out those programs coming back and adjusting your theoretical orientation locally to see what can be the next move, I think is an essential part.
These two things cannot ever be separated and operate.
They're absolutely embedded together and they must operate together in this dialectical fashion.
So my last point, and I think this is the last point of the entire show, is that eclecticism in revolutionary theory is not, as it's sometimes thought to be by those who improve.
embrace it a strength, right?
Nor is it a sign of a more advanced understanding of the situation.
And by eclecticism, I mean what Engels was talking about with the utopian socialists and this mish-mashing
together of ideas and theories to come up with your own unique approach to politics.
Oftentimes, eclecticism is a product of idealism, whereby one picks and chooses the ideas
they subjectively prefer and mashes them together into a political philosophy all their own.
Now, when I was younger and before I became a Marxist, I would actually do this,
myself all the time. So, like, I know, I'm not just criticizing other people. I'm saying
I've learned from my own flaws in my past. So, yeah, I would do this all the time with
political ideas. And the sad thing is that I often felt superior because of it. I wasn't
adhering to anyone else's dogma, right? I was a free thinker. And the fact that my eclectic
ideas were eclectic was seen by me as evidence that I'm actually thinking outside the confines
of any dogma and doctrine and being a revolutionary in my own way. And this, this idea is
very tempting. It's also very bourgeois and individuals.
It's the political equivalent of being a cafeteria Christian.
What Marxism and historical materialism offer is a concrete analysis of concrete conditions,
a methodology that can be applied across space and time,
a critique of capitalism that undercovers and explains the specific mechanisms and internal laws by which it came to be,
by which it operates, and by which it inevitably enters into periods of crises.
Marxist theory is then tested in the crucible of real-world revolutions.
The results are studied using a moment.
materialist analysis, and parts of the theory are, as I said earlier, updated, discarded, or
universalized depending on their real world successes or failures. In this way, Marxism as a
tradition develops and gets refined over time as more and more experiments, i.e. class
struggles and revolutions are attempted and thus analyzed. On the opposite end of this approach,
which we still see plenty of today, are idealist and eclectic conceptions of socialism and
revolution, whereby ideas about the world are tested and accepted not on the basis of their
successes or failures in real world conditions, not according to the results of testing theories
in the laboratories of world historical revolutions and refining them based on their objective
results, but rather on the basis of whether or not those ideas coer with one's subjective
preferences. This idealism can only lead to dead ends, like the utopian socialisms before them,
because they are not rooted in empirical investigation and practice, but rather in the subjective
mind. And subjectivity, as we know, is historically and culturally shaped, limited, and
contingent. You can never unite the geographically international and culturally diverse proletariat
and successfully assist them in overcoming their bourgeois pressures on these flimsy, subjective,
and arbitrary grounds. And I think when you look back over the entire history of proletarian
movements, when you analyze which ones succeeded and which ones lasted for more than a few
weeks or months, when you ask yourself whether said revolutions offered material support to other
proletarian movements or isolated themselves and little territories cut off from the rest of the world,
you will find that, even with all of its flaws and excesses and failures, it was and still is
Marxist movements that have successfully conducted, defended, and developed proletarian
revolutionary movements better than anyone else. So it's by embracing a materialist analysis
and a Marxist methodology that we tether ourselves to the real world and its real conditions,
rather than floating away in our own subjectivity
by picking and choosing an assortment of radical ideas
that we personally find compelling.
So I think that's an important point to make
and I think it's very much in line
with what Angles is telling us in this work.
Definitely. Yeah, I mean, I think that's really the important thing.
And like, what the takeaway that I want, you know,
in addition to the need for mass work,
is this idea that materialism is not just another option
among a bunch of other options.
When you look at how it's played out in history,
you can see that it is scientific
and that it has a dialectical
understanding of how the world works
that's confirmable.
Okay, so that wraps up our first ever episode
of Red Menace on Socialism, Utopian, and Scientific
by Frederick Engels.
We would love to hear your thoughts and feedback
on our analysis, so reach out to us on Twitter
or Patreon and let us know what you think.
And remember, this is important.
We do not cover theory for its own sake.
The point of this show, as Allison and I have both said throughout,
is to explain, analyze, and critique theory with the single-minded goal of putting this stuff into
practice. So take what we taught you today and organize. Solidarity and good night.
Like when my wife's like to rock and when it's the branch is why.
I cried to the morning, I swore I wouldn't do I.
The next thing you need the devil brought me to end.
The wigs of the hands wrapped around my throat.
Whoa, love me.
Baby, they won't let me.
Wrong, wrong, wrong, wrong, let me go.
I wouldn't have a way from my devil, but devil.
me wrapped in your eyes
Because when the devil gets a hold of the devil
Let your cradle to cry
I know I want you
I'll let me let me go
I know I want to
talk about you
I'll let's my hand
wrapped around my phone
won't let me
No, you're up and let me
Go, whoa
Go, let me go
Get her out, gotta get her out of me
Her out, gotta get her out of me
Get her out, got to get her out of me
Ooh, I know you think you know me, tell me devil,
Do you know my night?
Or am I just another heathen screaming while you play your little guy?
It is a certain kind of noise you've got me feeling.
feel you swine like when the wives get to rock and in the way and it makes the branches
sway and beautiful hands wrapped around my throat walking like me baby what like me go
oh let me go
Got to get out of me
Get her out
Get out
Get out
Hold it out
Go ahead
Get out
Get her out
Get her
out
Get her out
to get it out of me
We're going to be able to be.
Spreece.
inside.
What does your fear of light?
Is it a crow cutting across the sky?
I know the first clip of the coming earth
I believe that I remember.
Which that all this happens to be quickly
I cannot account
but the flowers all along together.
What I do know is that
After the glass I knew I should see
But the fire in the scene is hollow
a little bit from the open
and the dark eyes and buys
in my window
where he said in
The truth of the day I live in the air
I arrived in the room and my life is strong to love.
The wrong.
I don't know.