Rev Left Radio - The Politics of Friedrich Nietzsche: German Idealism, Nazism, and Freud
Episode Date: February 12, 2018Wes Alwan is one fourth of The Partially Examined Life, a podcast and blog dedicated to studying and teaching philosophy. Wes is a writer and researcher living in Boston who studied ancient philosophy..., Kant and Nietzsche in graduate school. Wes joins Brett to discuss the political relevance of the famous 19th century philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche. Follow, support and listen to The Partially Examined Life here: https://partiallyexaminedlife.com/ Follow Wes on Twitter @wesalwan Outro music by Father John Misty - Things It Would Have Been Helpful to Know Before the Revolution : Pure Comedy https://www.fatherjohnmisty.com Reach us at: Brett.RevLeftRadio@protonmail.com follow us on Twitter @RevLeftRadio Follow us on FB at "Revolutionary Left Radio" Intro Music by The String-Bo String Duo. You can listen and support their music here: https://tsbsd.bandcamp.com/track/red-black This podcast is officially affiliated with The Nebraska Left Coalition, the Nebraska IWW, and the Omaha GDC. Check out Nebraska IWW's new website here: https://www.nebraskaiww.org
Transcript
Discussion (0)
Please support my daddy's show by donating a couple bucks to patreon.com forward slash rev left radio.
Please follow us on Twitter at Rev. Left Radio.
And don't forget to rate and review the Revolutionary Left Radio on iTunes to increase our reach.
Workers of the world, unite!
Revolution
Revolution
Revolution
Revolutionary left the radio now
Oppose the system
Any way you know how
Unite the left against the capitalist lies
And liberate the proletarianist mind
Five for the working class
Five for equality
Against the right free
Fascist ideology
Turned it in and turn it out loud.
Revolutionary Left Radio starts now.
Welcome to Revolutionary Left Radio.
I'm your host, Ann Comrade, Brett O'Shea.
And today we have on Wes Allwin from The Partially Examined Life to talk about the political
relevance of Frederick Nietzsche.
Wes, would you like to introduce yourself and say a little bit about your background for
anyone who doesn't know who you are?
Sure, yeah.
So I'm one of four panelists on the partially examined life.
philosophy podcasts that we've been doing since 2009, I think, as the year. I always get confused whether
it's 2008 or nine. So I went to undergrad at St. John's College, which is a small great books,
liberal arts school. And then I went to grad school, University of Texas at Austin, and ended up
doing a master's thesis on Nietzsche and Marx, which does not make me an expert in either necessarily.
but we've talked a lot about Nietzsche on my podcast, and I do have a lot to say about him.
Yeah, so currently I'm also have studied a lot of psychoanalysis, and I'm currently finishing
a doctorate in psychoanalysis, and I'll be a practicing therapist, basically, and I'm already
kind of working in that field now as well.
That's extremely interesting, and for a lot of our listeners know that I have a degree in philosophy,
and I'm a philosophy graduate school dropout, but I've been a huge.
huge fan of the partially examined life for years and years. I used to listen to them as an
undergrad and a graduate philosophy student and learn from them. And I've always really had an
extra sort of appreciation for Wes's input precisely because some of what you focus on,
especially around psychoanalysis, I've always found extremely illuminating and interesting.
So I'm just extremely happy to have you on the podcast and to delve into this topic because
I think Nietzsche is sort of largely misunderstood. He's taken up by a lot of different
sorts of people and that kind of muddies the water around what his thoughts are. He kind of
becomes a pop culture symbol in some ways. So people kind of seen his image or might have heard
his name but have very little idea about who he is. And I think he is a foundational thinker.
And I think a lot of ways the 20th century in some ways was shaped by some of his philosophical
contributions. But before we get into all the history and the philosophy, maybe just let our
listeners know how you identify politically and sort of the orientation that you come at political questions
from? Sure. At this point, I tend to think of myself as a libertarian socialist that may not be the
right phrase or the best phrase. And it's interesting, even though I have so much to say about
politics, how difficult I find that question. I'm more of an agnostic in general. But when I say
libertarian socialists, I sort of mean in the tradition of someone like Orwell, who was a socialist,
but he was also concerned about Stalinism and the betrayal of the revolution essentially
by people interested in power, essentially by what he called nationalists who are
sort of devoted to the power of their own particular party or unit at the expense of the
well-being of everyone. So that said, I think of the socialist part. I think like Orwell,
I see hierarchy as inherently unjust, which is not to say that there are benefits to it or
that it can necessarily be completely done away with, but for instance, this is something,
you know, if I say to even my left-leaning friends, well, I don't think a busboy should make
less than I do. People are usually actually surprised by that, and I'm surprised that they're
surprised since they call themselves progressives or liberals. The terminology is obviously changed.
And so I do believe that. And people will have all kinds of the sort of meritocracy or meritocratic
minded society we live in. People will usually have explanations around hard work and other
sorts of what I think of as rationalizations of why they should make more than the busboy.
But I simply, I don't think there's, you know, I don't think that's a just situation. As far as
Socialism and practice, you know, the libertarian part, I put there not just because I'm
wary of any infringement on rights for the sake of the collective good, just like Orwell,
but because I don't think that simply seizing control of the means of production is a good
solution historically. In reading marks, I think the sort of historical progression part of it is
important and the role of technology is very important. So I think a lot of Marx is a thought
experiment around what happens when technology becomes so powerful that essentially it's
possible not to work or not to work so much and to do what we like, but still have a very
high standard of living. According to Marx, you know, there would be a phase where
there is pauperization where essentially the ruling class will be able to be able to
monopolize all the wealth produced by the leverage of technology, but that ultimately
historical forces will demand that the result of that productivity be shared. And I think
that's a compelling idea, but I think we sort of wait upon the right stage of technological
development before it becomes a possibility. Yeah. Our last episode, we interviewed the daughter
of Murray Bookchin, who was a famous sort of libertarian socialist thinker, and he kind of
had a synthesis of some of the best of Marx and the best of anarchism and called it libertarian
municipalism or communalism. So I think it kind of fits in the general political area that
you sit in. But let's go ahead and dive into Nietzsche and the history and the philosophy
there. We have a lot of ground to cover. So can you maybe give a quick summary of Nietzsche and his
place within the history of philosophy for those who may not know anything about him?
Sure. So German idealism became a big deal during the 19th century. So it began in the 18th century with Kant and epistemological theories, which acknowledge the role of consciousness and constructing reality, although some people would dispute that formulation, but ultimately with Hegel and other German idealists, you get sort of epistemological view, which might lead sort of as
on the edge of, well, it stands precariously between a kind, well, I don't know. I don't know how to
describe idealism. But anyway, I see Nietzsche as sort of a response to German idealism. Most
directly to Schopenhauer, who Nietzsche was a big fan of, but also, you know, Schopenhauer, of course,
is heavily influenced by Kant and Hegel. So at an epistemological level, Nietzsche, I think, is
sort of impressed by this distinction between appearance and things in themselves, which
come up, comes up a lot in his writing and which he critiques in a way, but he also relies on
or his, the idea is very influential with Nietzsche. And ultimately, what Nietzsche is focused on
is the moral implications, the moral and psychological implications of that sort of epistemology. So he's, he's
developed a critique of Western civilization and Christianity and ancient philosophy and
idealism.
It's sort of a radical universal critique.
But I think what he's most known for is the critique of morality as having its origin
ironically in nihilism and a hostility to life.
And I think if you want to really think about Nietzsche's place in the history of philosophy,
you have to see him as a response to the threat of nihilism.
So as society, as religion becomes a less prominent in Western society, and it becomes less
a source of meaning for people, I think there's a vacuum opened up where the question is,
well, what's going to fill that void?
And then ironically, it turns out that Christianity, even though it's sort of a attempt
of the solution to Nealism is also at its core a form of Nealism for Nietzsche.
Ultimately, his solution has something to do with the aesthetic and, you know, another idea
he's, of course, well known for is the Ubermensch, and what that means is also a big subject of
dispute, but in the context of his philosophy, it might mean something like a person who has
fully synthesized their rational or ascetic side with their, you know, what you might call
their Dionysian or artistic side, a kind of fusion. And we'll talk more about Freud,
but the sort of the similar idea that you see with Freud and psychoanalysis where the solution
to the problems of civilization, which amount to a repression of our instincts, is to
redirect those instincts towards something constructive.
All right. So that was kind of a mess, but it's a huge question. And so that's kind of my fault for throwing that huge of a question at you. But I mean, I would just add that you touched on it a little bit. The popular understanding of Nietzsche, and I think it gets reflected in like popular culture shows like Little Miss Sunshine where Nietzsche is portrayed as a nihilist. I think it's important for people to understand that he was kind of diagnosing the problem of nihilism before it really became a.
large, societal wide problem, and he was trying to find a way to overcome it or to get through
it and past it, because in the wake of the death of God, there would be a total lack of
sort of anchoring to what humans have depended on for centuries. Is that a fair way of
kind of thinking about? Yeah, exactly. He's an extreme anti-nihilist. And also ironically,
you know, that he's associated with fascism and even Nazism, but Nietzsche was also an anti-national.
and an anti-Semite, and the way in which that fits with his philosophy is just that
he saw those as the sorts of things that might arise, the very dangerous things that might
arise to fill in the gaps when you, you know, with the death of God and the decline of
Christianity and so on, the sort of the failure of the West's prior solutions to nihilism.
He's watching those solutions fail because they're also, they're, they're
simply covertly manifestations of nihilism themselves.
And I think there are hints in Nietzsche that he sees that the consequences of that could be
quite dire and nationalism and fascism are two of those possible consequences.
And I think it's pretty clear that he adamantly is opposed to them.
Absolutely. And we'll get it more into that in a bit.
But why just kind of baseline, why does Nietzsche, in your opinion, have such a broad appeal
from the fascist right to liberal individualists like Anne Randi and capitalist and even to many
strains of anarchism on the far left. Why is he so easily taken up by such a diverse range of
political philosophies, in your opinion? I think because he has such a sweeping critique of
institutions and society and, you know, regardless of where you stand politically,
all of those political philosophies you've mentioned, have their own critiques.
A lot of his critique is centered on the ways in which societies can ruin the individual through conformism and through a kind of warped set of values can deprive people of the ability to flourish.
So that idea, I think, appeals to a lot of people, but their definition of flourishing, of course, will be different and their definition of what society is doing wrong will be different.
And so with a liberal individualist, the focus might be on limiting the, you know, the ways in which a society might impinge upon one's rights or even one's property and things like that.
Whereas with a Marxist, it might be a critique of the, you know, the capitalist system and the ideology that associated with that system.
And then later on with neo-Marxists and critical theorists, it's a critique of the capitalist.
the culture associated with capitalism, and those cultural critiques, as it turns out,
will actually have some influence, you know, some Nietzsche influence as well.
So I think that's the, that's my basic view on that.
You probably have quite a bit to add to that.
I mean, yeah, I think there's a lot in Nietzsche, especially with his sort of fly-by-the-handle
writing style that pops up in a lot of his works, sort of aphoristic or hyperbolic way that
he speaks.
It can kind of lend itself to many sorts of interpretations, whereas,
somebody more concrete like Kant, you know, you can't read, like you have to follow him syllable
for syllable and really think about what he's saying in such a way that you don't have to
necessarily do with Nietzsche. And so I think that you can kind of pick from a bunch of different
parts of Nietzsche and kind of compile something to justify whatever you happen to believe.
I think that plays into it too. Right. And there's a lot of internal conflict in his writing as
well. Sure. And I would also add on the anarchist side of things, you have some, you know,
insurrectionary anarchists or nihilist anarchist or egoist anarchist and there's a heavy individualist
strain of sort of overcoming as an individual the sort of constraints that a capitalist society
or a state a statist sort of situation and places on the individual so I think there's yeah I think
it's just you can pull from a lot of different directions so Nietzsche had had something negatives to
say about virtually everyone including socialists and anarchists and nationalists and liberals and but
you can find bits and pieces including for liberalism where there's a um there's something in there which
will you know where nietzsche some of his thought will actually provide some support for liberalism so
for instance or for any of those other positions right so it's not just it's not just people
reading the tea leaves in whatever ways they want there's there actually are i think real
tensions in his philosophy and and if you isolate one little bit here or there you can find
something that supports your your political position, whatever it is. And I think that's a great segue
into this segment about fascism, because whether we like it or not, the fact is Nietzsche was used
by the Nazis as sort of their philosopher of choice, and a lot of it was because of his sister.
So can you talk about how Nietzsche spent the last decade of his life and how his sister took his
writings and helped shape them for consumption by German Nazis? And also, like, what would you think
he would have thought of this had he lived long enough to see it? So yeah, I don't know a great
deal about the details of this. But in 1889, he basically went insane and essentially lived out
the last decade of his life for 11 years, suffering from severe dementia. So he was really
completely incoherent for those 10 years. And during that time, his sister, who was a notorious
anti-Semite and married to a notorious anti-Semite, compiled the remaining parts of Nietzsche's papers
and put them together in a book called Will to Power.
So this is the part, I don't know a lot of detail about how this was done.
So there's a lot of little bits and pieces, little, it's the way Nietzsche writes anyway,
and these aphorisms.
But the way she's compiled them, I think some of them, the authenticity of them is questionable.
And then otherwise, just the ordering of them and the framing of them so that they can be taken out of context.
And then just the way she sold them.
So ultimately, I think it's the way she sold it, and it's the way the Nazis ended up using Nietzsche.
And then they did this very consciously, from what I understand.
They very actively boulderized his works so that the anti-nationalist stuff and the pro-Semitic stuff was just not there.
And then used the pieces that they wanted to make it look like he was a, you know, the sort of philosophical father of a Nazi party.
Yeah, and after he died in 1900, his sister Elizabeth kind of constructed the house into a Nietzschean shrine or sort of a Nietzschean museum.
And there's actually a photograph of Adolf Hitler going to that location and doing a walkthrough and meeting Nietzsche's sister.
That's very surreal to see that those photographs disturbing, really.
Yeah, he gave her a wreath for Nietzsche's grave calling and something calling Nietzsche a fighter or something like that.
it's really not clear that Hitler ever really even read Nietzsche, although Nietzsche was very
widely read at that point. And so it's the kind of thing you would hear people talk about.
But from what I've read, it's pretty likely that Hitler wasn't sitting around reading Nietzsche
thinking about it. But as far as what Nietzsche would think, I think Nietzsche, of course,
would be unhappy with his appropriation pretty much by anyone.
There'd be no circumstance in which he'd be happy with how.
he was being used, but the Nazis in particular, because they represent the culmination of
a trend that he was railing against, this sort of romanticization of the German Volk and
the German tradition, which he was highly critical of, and the nationalist element. And he saw
some of this, you know, in the gay science and elsewhere, you see him predicting some of this stuff
and the negative way it's affecting Germany and just hints of that, you know, that no good will come
of this. And so I think it's extremely ironic that the culmination of this, this trend to which
he was essentially opposed, that the leaders of that, that movement would, would use him in the way that
they do. It's, you know, based purely on these, much of it, very superficial resemblance to their
own ideology around will and things like that. But some of it, of course, because Nietzsche was,
in fact, an elitist in some ways. And, well, you know, there's a strong elitist.
element to his philosophy and a harshness and lots of places where he can be misinterpreted as
well. And I also think he would have been sort of appalled at sort of the collective, the collectivist
nature of Nazism and of fascism generally. And then of sort of the sort of nihilistic unleashing
of violence that was inherent to fascism and to Nazism specifically is sort of like
what he was warning about. He was warning about trying to replace, you know, after the death of
God, the sort of replacing, they're trying to fill that vacuum with something. And in some
respects, you know, the Nazis did that. But very specifically with political movements, yes,
but filling that vacuum. And I, yeah, I just want to say that the politics of this stuff is
something he thought about. Certainly there were aspects of his philosophy that if isolated from
the whole could be leveraged in a fascist direction, especially with regards to certain notions
surrounding power, degeneracy, decadence, et cetera. Can you talk about what aspects of his thought can
and have legitimately been embraced by fascist
and what aspects of his thought
also oppose fascism and Nazism,
which we've touched on a little bit.
Nietzsche's critique of morality is, you know,
what he calls slave morality,
which includes Christianity,
with their elements of it that he sees in ancient Greek philosophy
and the later ancient Greek playwrights.
And in Western society in general,
even not just in Christianity,
but in the way that science is sort of used
as a quasi-religious way,
Scientism, let's say. The critique of those things, a lot of it sounds very harsh. He talks about
the herd and herd animals and lower sorts of types of human beings. And it seems like, by contrast,
he's talking about a master morality that predates slave morality. And if you're not careful,
you might think that he's actually talking that up and praising it is something that we ought to
return to. He also calls it a morality of breeding. So, for example, a Hindu caste system is
one example of that morality of breeding or sort of pre-Christian pagan hierarchies where the strong
ruled the weak and so on, including Rome and all of that stuff. And that's definitively not the
case. It's not the case that he's, and he also talks about, so for instance, in the context of master
morality, talks about the blonde beast, the Germanic blonde beast. And you might think it's the type
the thing that he's calling for a return to. So this rule of this sort of a ethos of might makes
right and the rule of the stronger and all that sort of stuff. I don't think that's the case.
One of the things he says actually in Twilight of the Idols is that as brutal as master morality is,
and it is very brutal, slave morality actually carries on that brutality. So it's sort of, even though
it's slave morality sort of seems to rebel against that and to put the interests of the weak above
the strong, and, you know, as Christianity does, the meek shall inherit the earth and all of that,
it is actually something equally as brutal and worse in a way because it's hidden behind this
ideology of loving thy neighbor and all that stuff, when really it's a doctrine, a doctrine of
hate. And then this, you know, there's all the elitism and the, with this critique of the average
human being and talk about an ubermensch, a Superman, who will transcend that, you might take
that, and especially in light of his talk about the morality reading, you might think of that
as an argument for a certain kind of racism, the superiority, for instance, of people, maybe the
Aryans or something like that. Again, I don't think that's the case. The elitism part, you know,
the thing I don't think you can get rid of with Nietzsche is that he is thinking of a higher type of
human being, a genius or a great artist slash scientist, someone who fuses those two things. For me,
it's actually quite hard to decipher and figure out, and I think it's the weakest part of his
account. But that tone of elitism and contempt for the broad swath of humanity and his focus on
the good of the individual over the good of the collective is where, of course, you can start
to make ill-use of him, so politically. Right. And in a lot of Nietzsche's work, there's a lot of
talk about conflict and overcoming and war. And part of the notion of Ubermensch is this very
notion of sort of overcoming. But you've talked about how you can sort of interpret that in a more
literal and sort of crude physical way as an actual call to arms in a sort of way. Or you can
interpret it more subtly as a psychological metaphor of sorts. Can you flesh out this idea for us
touching on his ideas regarding those subjects in the process? Yeah, he talks a lot about war
and the utility of having enemies and praises struggle, praises agonism and victory and defeat and all
those things, which, again, it's pretty clear in the context of what he's writing about that
he's thinking of these now at a spiritual level. So it's one thing to have peace on earth
in the sense of abolishing war, but peace of spirit, I think, he doesn't think is a good thing.
He thinks that that's sort of the moment at which we become these passive herd animals who are no longer fully actualizing themselves, no longer flourishing.
Because to flourish and to be fully actualized, you have to be struggling, including to overcome oneself is the way he puts it.
And, you know, I can't find a place where he's literally praising war itself.
Yeah, I think this, there's something here when it talks about a sort of, if you live,
if you have a life of too much comfort, of no need for struggle, there is a certain sort
of, it's almost antithetical to our nature as social apes, as, you know, descendants of chimps
in some way.
When you have, for example, maybe this will clarify a little bit, but when you talk to military
veterans who come back from brutal war zones, and they see some of their best friends
get blown up and killed, they come back to civilian life, and a lot of times they will
talk about wanting to go back, wanting to go back into the fray, not because they
enjoyed the violence or the conflict or watching their friends die, but because they
enjoyed the sort of collective struggle of being inside a military platoon, fighting against
enemies, in some ways, coming back to civilian life is a meaningless sort of endeavor.
You come back to just grocery stores and gas stations and going to work and coming back
every day, and there's a sort of meaninglessness there. So I think Nietzsche might be onto something
when he talks about the need for a psychological struggle or some sort of, I don't really know
how to phrase it.
How do you think about that?
Yeah, I think that's right.
So I think this goes back to the question of status, which I mentioned at the beginning
of the podcast.
And I've thought about this with respect to Orwell, because he emphasizes in his definition
of nationalism, this focus on power and status, or prestige, as he calls it.
And it's a problem because I think it's a problem for social.
as well, because even if you equalized everyone's material conditions, that in and of itself
is not an abolition of the hierarchy. It could be the case that in a future society, everyone is
essentially wealthy and doesn't have to work to have a high standard of living. And you could even
completely equalize material conditions between people, but it's still conceivable that in that
society, say a doctor, someone who wanted to do that, although it could be done my machines,
I guess theoretically in the future, but, you know, that that person would have much greater status
than, say, a, someone who wanted to be a janitor. You could still have those sorts of hierarchies
and those sorts of differences in status, even once you've equalized material conditions.
So Orwell saw this and, you know, he went to Catalonia to the fight in the, you know,
Spanish Civil War. And what he saw was that the revolution, initially workers had control.
And then it was taken away by communist party bosses and by bureaucratic organizations where
status was very important. And so that's the one thing that, you know, a meritocratic,
and it's something that's really important to a meritocratic society with a large middle class,
because the rat race becomes essentially about status. A lot of work is about establishing your
your worth in the in the eyes of others climbing to the top of an organization getting power
in that way and that tendency to focus on status and power can undermine the revolution as it did with
Stalin according to orwell's the flip side of that is it's not entirely clear how you would get rid of
status and then that there are elements to status that are actually quite useful we work a lot harder
with it with the idea of obtaining some sort of recognition or glory
there are ways in which it's possible that that actually transforms us for the better,
makes us harder workers, makes us want to achieve great things, pushes us, you know,
again, is more akin to Nietzsche's idea of agonism and struggle and self-overcoming
and truly becoming who we are through that struggle.
So if there's some way in which you could abolish the external structures of status and
hierarchy and power and internalize them,
psychologically, I think that would be ideal. And that may be what he's on to with the ubermensch,
right, an individual who doesn't need to rise in middle management or even be the head of a
country or an army to have some sense of power and to have some sense of status. It's sort of
status and power unmoored from those structures. That's the way in which I see its relevance here.
Does that make, does that actually speak to the question? Yeah. I mean, I think that's a fascinating sort of
set of ideas and to struggle with struggle with as no matter what your politics are but obviously
we're talking to a left-leaning audience to struggle with some of the implications of achieving the
goals of socialism of creating that material equality or on the anarchist side of things destroying
unjust hierarchies there's still something about the human being that's going to be left over
that you're going to have to contend with and I think it serves us well to think really deeply
and hard about what those are and what we can separate out about the human animal from the
social conditioning of that human animal and try to try to wrestle with some of those
implications. So yeah, I think it's extremely important. And it's something I struggle with a lot
too. I don't have the answers, obviously. But I would like to move on to sort of his
thoughts on liberalism and maybe democracy. He was living in the mid to late 1800s, clearly
the rise of industrial capitalism and the sort of overarching ideology of capital, which
liberalism and bourgeois democracy? What were Nietzsche's sort of critiques of liberalism and
democracy? And how do you think we should understand his views in relations to today's so-called
liberal democracies? The basic critique is he thought that it essentially elevates the herd and the
society's sort of lowest common denominator to a position of the highest. So democracies can have
the effect of a cultural level limiting individual potential. And he's thinking about
about how potential geniuses or how truly potential, you know, Uber mentioned people or,
or anyone who might achieve self-actualization is going to do that in the context of democracy
and the sort of bourgeois culture associated with that, which sort of undermines the spirit
and tends to focus more on the material and turns us into people who are concerned more about
money and our jobs and things like that, than the development of our spirits. And to the extent
that, you know, the democratic impulse is to make everyone alike or to level things out, again,
that's something that he's not so happy about. There's a sort of hostility to, again, these
potential great human beings who are handicapped by that sort of society. Right. And it kind of
extends, that critique extends a bit into his critiques of Christianity and slave morality.
and then also into socialism.
So can you maybe talk about some of the critiques of Christianity and socialism
and how they overlap in Nietzsche's thought?
So for Christianity, he critiques Christianity as a sort of reaction to what he calls master morality
and the morality of might makes right or what he calls a premoral set of values
in which what's celebrated is strength and beauty and power and ascendancy and all that stuff.
And the reaction to it is to say, well, those people,
the winners, the more powerful ones, they're just evil. So we have to do something about that.
And so you get a whole set of morals in which it's evil to exert power. And in a way,
it's almost evil to be in a higher place within the hierarchy. And the impulse is to say the ideals
that we're all equal and we all love one another and so on and so forth. Underneath that
is concealed what Nietzsche calls Rizantamah, which is essentially,
unconscious revenge fantasy. So the Christian, the supposed religion of love, there's a lot in it
about heaven and hell and the ways in which the faithful will be rewarded with heaven, and then
all the bad people will be in hell. So that's the sort of fantasy of revenge against those who
are more powerful. And what I think he does at a psychological level, it's sort of an extension
of what civilization does anyway, which is it has us repress and feel guilty about and feel
ashamed of our instincts. And I think the result of that is to curtail people's chances at
happiness. So Christianity is just a larger manifestation of these sort of internally, psychologically
repressive mechanisms that ultimately make people sick. And this is one another place where Nietzsche is
prefiguring some of what Freud will have to say. So I think his idea is just that that sort of way
of thinking is simply not good for us psychologically. It doesn't really allow us to flourish.
Even if we want a society where, of course, people aren't just running around killing each other
and being unjust to each other, that sort of ideology can be damaging to us. And socialism, you know,
there's enough overlap between socialist ideals and Christian ideals as far as the recognition,
for instance, of the problems with hierarchy and inequality. Well, Nietzsche is,
here to say that actually, at least at a spiritual level, we need hierarchy and we need
inequality, even if that's just a structure within ourselves. And he uses biological metaphors a
lot. So the ways in which the body is essentially a hierarchy where different organs serve
the larger purpose of the whole, I think at a very fundamental level, he thinks we can't do without
that. We can't do without that physiologically. We can't do without that psychologically. And I'm not so
sure what he thinks about, strangely enough, even though he's one of the greatest, the great
political philosophers, it's unclear, it's always unclear what he thinks we should do about that
at a social political level. And so it's conceivable that there's a socialist, you know,
it's conceivable that there's no society that really is in harmony with that. That's why
Nietzsche can be, you know, used by people of so many different political persuasions.
It's also conceivable that there's a socialist society that's consistent with Nietzsche's way of thinking as long as one's comportment towards the socialist ideal doesn't go too far or doesn't become so extreme that it fails to acknowledge the reality of the necessity of, say, things like hierarchy and striving and struggle and all of that stuff.
Yeah, so that's interesting because it makes me think about a sort of view that I have that might be conducive to Nietzsche's idea because you're talking about he doesn't really give a sort of positive idea of the exact sort of society he would want.
He just kind of critiques societies as they are and you have to kind of take the implications of what that means.
And I think you touched on it a little bit, but in my view, I think self-actualization is a goal that most liberationists on the left today aim for.
And in some sense, it's a goal that Nietzsche himself lauded, though not in those terms.
terms, could not an egalitarian society based on democratic and socialist principles
provide a social context in which individuals could more easily flourish and self-actualize,
or maybe put another way, compared to, like, repressive fascist regimes which slaughter people
and oppressive capitalist regimes which coerced most of us into spending the vast majority
of our lives, toiling away of meaningless jobs for wages?
Wouldn't a system dedicated to ensuring everyone had their basic needs met in which
employees maybe automation technology to free people from the drudgery of wage labor,
provide a better chance for more people to rise to their highest potential in a way that
Nietzsche would approve of? What do you think of that argument? I think that's true. I think,
in fact, that's the best, you know, best chance for a society that's amenable to individual
flourishing and even for, you know, if you take the elitist route, even for those who are
society's geniuses, what kind of society would they flourish best in? I think, yeah, a society
where you could follow one's passions rather than be chained to unsatisfying work that doesn't
actually pay all your bills. Yeah, I think that you'd be way better off. On the other hand,
a lot depends on the kind of culture and ways of thinking that go along with such a society. So,
know if that society is also is simply hostile for instance to those who stand out or are different
because it's conceivable right that an egalitarian society might might embrace difference
but it's also conceivable that it would want to make everyone the same so i think uh you know
it's hard to you'd have to figure out what's going on at a at a at a cultural level i think certainly
yes if you'd have the best chance socialist society yeah and then
There's that famous Einstein quote where he talks about he's not so much impressed with the geniuses that have come before him,
but he thinks more about all the people that have toiled away in fields and factories that could have been, you know,
even bigger geniuses than the people that made the biggest impacts in science and philosophy.
And so that kind of reminded me of that.
There is a historicity in Nietzsche's writings and thought that echoes, in some ways at least, the historicity of Marxism.
How does he view history with regards to its shaping the present and the future?
And how does that sort of echo some of the historicity in Marxism?
Nietzsche is famous for genealogy.
So in the genealogy of morals, his critique of Christian morality and more broadly of Western morality
depends on tracing its origins of looking at its history.
And the history, again, that he identifies is this sort of reaction among Roman Christian slaves to a master morality.
that was being used to oppress them.
And unfortunately, it was a reaction that incorporated the worst of the master morality
and let it fester and sicken society.
So it's a different way of analyzing morality.
It's not like an approach in which he's going to analyze along the lines of a Kant
or a more systematic philosopher.
He's not going to start with some analysis or some first principle
and try and derive abstractly.
what it is we ought to do in order to, whether it's in order to flourish or in order to fulfill
basic obligations, he's taking a negative route, he's taking an existing system of values
and identifying its sort of its pernicious origins and using that as an argument, using that
as a way of pointing to its perniciousness, which by the way doesn't necessarily follow.
Philosophers call this the genetic fallacy, just looking at the saying that, well, Christianity
arose because of, um, out of X undesirable motives, certain undesirable motives means that
Christian morality is wrong. It's actually not the case. It could have, you know, we could still
accidentally be right. Um, but at the, at a deeper level, uh, the, the genealogy is
psychological. So the genealogy has implications for the actual structure of that morality. So
it's not just that historically Christian morality has its origin.
in this, what he calls Rizantamah, this revenge fantasy against those who are stronger.
It's that it incorporates that revenge fantasy and that it's essentially dishonest.
It essentially cloaks itself in the opposite of what it actually is.
So it presents itself as this religion of love when it's really a religion of hate.
And that structural conflict, that tension makes us sick.
It's at a psychological level.
the genealogical tension, you know, at a historical level, it gets internalized, and it's bad for us.
So as far as the resemblance to Marx and historicity there, you know, I think so for Marx, so if you look at his critique of class ideology, right, it's that the tendency in a capitalist society is to make capitalism look like it's sort of the natural order of things.
Or let's just say more generally, whatever kind of hierarchy you have in the society, the ideology of the ruling class is to say, well, look, some people belong in this class and other people belong at this level of the hierarchy, and that's just the way things are and it can't change.
Whereas for Marx, it's actually something contingent and part of a historical process that actually not only can change, but necessarily will change.
you need the historical account in the same way that Nietzsche uses the historical account
or the genealogical kind of morality to cast doubt on a certain system of values.
With Marx, I think it's the same thing.
For him, if you expand to this sort of historical account, the development of history
and specifically economic conditions, you will see that the ideology is just a product of
certain material conditions, those material conditions will necessarily change, and it makes one
less prone to simply buy into that ideology. I mean, I think that's perfectly said, and I also
want to draw another parallel between, in the same way that for Nietzsche, you know, Christian
morality gives rise to sort of deceitfulness that gives rise to a broader sickness, the parallel in
Marx would be the sort of alienation that arises out of the capitalist system and, you know,
the psychological suffering that that causes. There's a deep parallel there. Right. Yep.
Well, that leads very well into what I know you care a lot about, and I find very fascinating. I
don't get a lot of opportunities to talk about it, but that's Freud and Freudism, you know,
Nietzsche influenced Sigmund Freud heavily, and then Freud went on to influence a whole host of
leftist intellectuals, perhaps most notably those out of the Frankfurt School, but also thinkers like
Zhijek and others. Therefore, you can draw a straight line from Nietzsche to many Marxist intellectuals
of the 50s and 60s and beyond through Freud. Can you talk about Nietzsche's influence on Freud
and highlight some of Freud's primary ideas which he inherited or kind of took from Nietzsche?
So Freud himself would deny that he took anything from Nietzsche. Freud denied reading Nietzsche.
And there are some accounts that he said he didn't want to read Nietzsche because he didn't
want to be confronted with the fact that someone had thought of a lot of these things before he
did. But apparently he also had a lot of praise worthy, you know, he had a lot of praise for
Nietzsche, just from what he had heard about Nietzsche, despite the fact that he claimed not to
have read him. There are subtle, subtler ways that someone can be influenced by someone than reading
them, of course, and Nietzsche was very widely read among German intellectuals, and Freud would
certainly have heard Nietzsche being discussed. You know, beyond that, it's just possible that
they're just converging on the same sorts of insights in different ways.
You know, Nietzsche calls himself a psychologist.
That's precisely the turn that he's taking and the turn that Freud is taking.
I think the most obvious thing, the most obvious parallel is that they are both focused on
the sickness producing elements of civilization, the ways in which civilization affects instincts
by leading to their repression
and leading to guilt and shame and things like that
and the negative effects of that.
So they're both, I see them as both sort of,
you know, in the history of thinkers,
they're the first lawyers that the instincts ever really had.
I mean, they're, you know,
there are, of course, philosophers that come before
who are their hints of this.
But really, it's reaction against the simple repression
and disavow of instincts
that even those that would be destructive if they were you know we simply let them have sway
there are elements of nietzsche where you you see him talking about what's what's unconscious and
forgotten his talk about bad conscience is sort of parallel to freud's talk about the super ego and
you can even think of nietzsche's ubermensch as sort of the person who has succeeded in achieving
freedom by reconciling instinctual urges with the necessity of functioning socially and
in a society. So the parallel as far as the solution goes is that Freud will talk a lot about
sublimation and the redirection of instinctual urges, including both libidinal urges and destructive urges
into something constructive, so into work, even into love in one's relationships, into
arts and science and all of that stuff. And I think Freud, you know, in a way, is more of a pessimist than Nietzsche.
I think that for him is a solution, but it's not an ideal solution.
We're all bound to sort of be unhappy, but you can minimize the suffering and unhappiness,
and you can have moments of transcendence, let's say, through sublimation.
I think for Nietzsche, there's, strangely enough, there's more of an idealism there.
There's more of the sense that one might truly perfect oneself by becoming this ubermensch.
a lot of people today kind of dismiss Freud as of an older time maybe he contributed some good things
some even go so far as to say he's he wasn't a psychologist he was a philosopher in your opinion
what does Freud still offer today what what what did Freud give us as a way of thinking about
the human mind that is still as relevant as ever and has not been displaced by advancements
in certain fields of science that are relevant to to his field yeah so if you go into the average
psychology program, you will read very little Freud, if any Freud, and there's a lot of
contempt for Freud. You'll read a lot more Freud if you go study literature, let's say. And you'll be
reading lots of Freud in an English department. But on the other hand, the way a lot of therapists
work these days, they'll call themselves psychodynamic or eclectic. They might use cognitive therapy
and psychodynamic therapy.
When they talk about psychodynamic therapy,
they really are talking about something
that's basically predicated
and on a Freudian conception of the psyche
and what ails the psyche
and how one solves that problem.
So most critical here is the concept of the unconscious mind,
the idea that there is an unconscious
and that we repress taboo or forbidden
or just dangerous, frightening ideas
and disconnect them from our emotions and that that disconnection can create symptoms
and that the solution to those symptoms is to help reconnect those ideas and those feelings
and to become more conscious of what's been made made unconscious so and the average therapist
will at least to some extent even if they think of themselves as as antifroidian or even
anti-psychic analytic will be doing some of that.
So they will, in a very rough way, function as if they buy into some of these very, very basic ideas,
even if they don't read all the sorts of stuff that I read at a psychoanalytic Institute.
Personally, I think, you know, I read a lot of psychoanalytic literature.
I find it insightful and perceptive.
And I think Freud himself is someone everyone should read, even if you just want to read him as a philosopher.
If you read him carefully and honestly, his brilliance and even his artistry,
his just his greatness as a writer will be very clear.
But yeah, psychoanalysis is not dead.
There are still a lot of psychoanalytic institutes, especially outside of America.
You know, there are countries like, I think it's Argentina,
where virtually everyone still has a psychoanalyst, where psychoanalysis is very popular.
In general, regardless of what you think about Freud and psychonelysis specifically,
talk therapy is still enormously popular at this point insurance companies pretty much are required
to allow people to do as much of it as they want and many studies have come out to show that it's
just as effective as medication and so on so there's something there and i think if you think talk
therapy works if you really want to explain why it works you have to at least appeal to uh to some
sort of psychodynamic idea that has its origins in Freudian ideas Freudian innovation
around the unconscious mind and repression and all that sort of stuff.
Yeah, I honestly couldn't agree more.
I totally agree with you.
One thing we do on this podcast is we analyze film and sort of,
especially when it comes to the horror genre,
analyzing horror films as a way of sort of understanding societal subconscious fears
as they manifest themselves in popular culture.
And I think that that draws a very clear cut line
from the Freudian notions of the individual mind.
And do you think that that jump from individual neuroses and individual subconscious to collective neuroses or collective subconscious is a legitimate one?
Or is that, I mean, how do you think about that?
I think it is legitimate.
So for Freud, the point of conflict is essentially is between collective societal values and then one's own personal impulses and one's makeup and even one's character.
You know, that's something that he thought a little bit about.
But psychoanalysts have thought a lot more about since then.
It's a concept of personality and character and individuality and the way.
way societal values might conflict with that. So at an internal level, at a psychodynamic level,
the thing that's doing the repressing right is in part the superego, and that depends upon these
identifications, not just with ones where the super ego essentially consists of identifications,
not just with one's parents, but with societal values and authority figures within society,
teachers and even political figures and so on. So that's one way of, that's one way of thinking
about it. You were talking about looking at films. So for instance, I wrote about Back to the Future
on our blog. It's a piece called Back to the Father. And I, you know, it's a film that very
explicitly includes this theme of incest. This is one of the things that people find so unsavory
about psychoanalysis is, and Freud is this focus on, focus on the idea of incest. And so when I wrote
that a lot of the reaction I got well was you know well this is crazy you're just reading into this
as a psychoanalyst even though it's explicitly a film about a guy who goes back to a time where his
mother starts hitting on him and where he's not going to be born unless he can rebuff his mother's
connections and get him to like his father right it's pretty obvious and it's pretty obvious
it you know in that film but in also more subtly in other films that that at some level
The incest taboo, whether we'd like to admit it or not,
it's something that plays an important role in structuring our psyche.
And if you pay attention, you will see that our cultural artifacts and including films reflect that preoccupation,
even if it's become completely unconscious and other sorts of similar preoccupations.
So, yes, I think you can interpret any text, including a film, in terms of those basic fears and so on.
Yeah, and I think incest as the content of dreams, incestuous dreams, are the most uncomfortable
dreams, but I think they're more widespread than people like to admit, and that also I think
hints at some truth there.
Well, I was being a little indulgent on the Freud question because why I had you here,
I kind of wanted to go down that alley, but thank you for talking to me about that.
Let's go ahead and wrap it up.
Maybe the last question I could ask is just what, in your opinion, can modern-day progressives
or revolutionaries who seek to create a better world ultimately learn and take from Nietzsche?
I think the most powerful lesson in Nietzsche is the anti-nationalism.
I think of him in a way, and this is, although it might sound strange, to people who are
unfamiliar with Nietzsche, but I think of him as one of history's most important anti-nationalist
philosophers, and I think any movement can fall into that trap.
So, in other words, and so this is something Orwell talks about in his notes on nationalism.
No matter how well-meaning and aligned with the correct ideals, one's movement is,
it can serve as a psychological and social function.
It can really serve the impulse to power and status.
And again, for Orwell, he learned the hard way.
He saw the revolution in Spain betrayed by people who were simply grabbing at power.
And he saw, you know, the revolution in Russia betrayed in the same way by
Stalin. In his notes on nationalism, he treats sort of any group identification or identification
with a political position as a potential form of nationalism. So he talks about pacifist nationalism,
for instance, strange as it sounds. One could be a nationalist on behalf of the idea of pacifism
or even, which is to say one's identification with one with that group of pacifists might become
chauvinistic. It might become focused on the idea of the superiority of my pacifist group to
those people about me, those despicables who are not pacifists. And then all I care about is the
prestige and power of my group. And I might still give lip service to the ideals, but really it's
sort of degenerated into that concern for power and prestige and status. So I think that's a, you know,
that's a danger for for any movement no matter how well meaning no matter how aligned with the
right ideals so internal critique is always necessary one must and and by the way orwell applied
this and to himself he essentially said even this essay notes on nationalism it's just anti-nationalist
nationalism same way you can be a pacifist nationalist you can be an anti-nationalist nationalist
And the reason why he says is because, you know, he was generalizing about broad groups of people.
He was sort of asserting his own superiority of his way to theirs.
And inevitably, at a psychological level, it's just almost impossible to not become tribal about it.
And that's the thing we have to guard against.
And the way to do that is to try to maintain some sort of internal critique and work against the tendency to demonize others.
and try to examine oneself to see if am I still really focused on the good of whether it's
my group or society as a whole or has this become about power struggle and um establishing my
my superior already to others so if you look at so for instance a lot of it goes on twitter which
I think of as you know the the telescreen of uh you know sort of 1980s for till 1984's telescreen
Twitter is a lot like that because it allows people to have these moments of triumph over
the over their enemies that allows them to really fully engage in that fantasy by one upping
someone so someone who claims to be for you know anti injustice and blah blah blah
they might spend a lot of their time just insulting people essentially so that they can feel
superior to them so that that's an example of what I what I mean absolutely yeah
Yeah, well said, and I think that's extremely important.
I would also say before we end, to be aware of liberals and progressives and Democrats,
they're not often explicit with their negative nationalism,
like attacking other countries because they're not Americans,
but by propping up a sort of positive nationalism
and echoing nationalist myths about being the city on the hill
and we're the freest, most democratic country in the world,
that is a covert form of nationalism that liberals and Democrats embrace all the time.
So be aware of that.
Yep, absolutely.
Thank you so much for coming on, West.
It's been a fascinating conversation.
I really, really appreciate it.
Before I let you go,
can you maybe give some recommendations
for anyone who wants to learn more about Nietzsche
and then point listeners to where they can find
your work and your podcast?
I think listeners could start with Walter Kaufman's Nietzsche,
a philosopher, psychologist, Antichrist,
the sort of philosophical biography of Nietzsche.
So you get a biography,
and then you get an explanation
of a lot of his ideas.
And Kaufman is a great translator of Nietzsche
and really was sort of the guy,
one of the people who rehabilitated Nietzsche
from the sort of cartoonish idea of him
as a, you know, as a fascist philosopher.
So, yeah, so that's one place to look.
If you're looking for more analytical stuff,
if you're interested in Nietzsche's epistemology,
Moe-Marie Clark's, Nietzsche on truth and philosophy is really great.
or an analytic explication of his morality, Brian Leiders, Nietzsche on morality.
There's a book called Introductions to Nietzsche by Robert Pippen.
He's at the University of Chicago.
He's really great.
He writes about Hegel and German idealism in general as well.
So it's just a book of introductions to various Nietzsche's texts.
I'll just give one more.
Kathy Higgins and Robert C. Solomon or
Nietzsche scholars, they're actually husband and wife, and they're at the
University of Texas when I was there.
They wrote a book called What Nietzsche Really Said, which might be
helpful for beginners.
And where can listeners find your work?
Oh, the small amount of work I've done is available at the, it's partially
examined life.com.
And I would really encourage anyone to go listen to partially examine life.
If you're interested in philosophy, if you want to learn more about these things,
they're a great way to get into this topic.
Even if you don't know anything about philosophy, it's a really interesting way to get into
a lot of these ideas and a lot of these thinkers and the whole history of thought that comes
with it.
So thanks again, Wes, for coming on.
It's been a pleasure.
I really appreciate it.
Let's keep in touch, and maybe I can have you back on one day to do a whole episode on Freud.
Sure.
Thanks for having me on.
It was a lot of fun.
And so we overthrew the system
Because there's no place for human existence, like right here
On this bright blue marble orbited by trash
Man, there's no been that
There's no big thing to give up the way of life we have.
My social life is now quite a bit less hectic
The nightlife and the protests are pretty scarce
Now mostly spend the long days
Walking through the city
Sometimes I miss the top of the food chain, but what a perfect afternoon.
common
Top of their knees
The gears of progress haunted
Underclass set free
The super-ego shatters
With our ideologies
You've seen injunction
To enjoy life
Disappears as in a dream
And as we reach up
To our native state
To our planet's
Temperature it started dropping, the ice flows began to freeze.
From time to time we all get a bit of rest.
we all get a bit restless with no one advertising to us constantly the tribe at the phone
airport some nights has me to dancing if you don't mind gathering and hunting we're all
still pretty good at eating on the run
Things it would have been helpful to know before the revolution.
Though I'll admit some degree of resentment for the sudden lack of convenience around here,
But there are some visionaries among us
Developing some products
To aid us in our struggle to survive
On this godless rock that refuses to die
Thank you.