The Daily - 'The Interview': Peter Singer Wants to Shatter Your Moral Complacency
Episode Date: November 2, 2024The controversial philosopher discusses societal taboos, Thanksgiving turkeys and whether anyone is doing enough to make the world a better place.Unlock full access to New York Times podcasts and expl...ore everything from politics to pop culture. Subscribe today at nytimes.com/podcasts or on Apple Podcasts and Spotify.
Transcript
Discussion (0)
From the New York Times, this is the interview. I'm David Marchese.
Maybe it sounds corny, but in my own little way, I really do try to make the world a better
place. I think about the ethics of what I eat. I donate to charity. I give time and
energy to helping those less fortunate in my community. And according to Peter Singer, those efforts pretty much add up to bupkis.
Singer is arguably the world's most influential living philosopher.
His work grows out of utilitarianism, the view that a good action is one that, within
reason, maximizes the well-being of the greatest number of lives possible.
He spent decades trying to get people to take a more critical look at their own ethics and
what well-meaning, comfortable people can actually do to make the world a better place.
His landmark 1975 book, Animal Liberation, helped popularize vegan and vegetarian eating
habits.
His new book, Consider the Turkey, builds on those ideas as a polemic against the Thanksgiving
meal. And his writing on what the wealthy owe the poor, which is a lot more than they're giving,
was an important building block for the data-driven philanthropic movement known as effective altruism,
which has gotten a lot of attention recently because of some of its high-profile adherents
in Silicon Valley, including the disgraced cryptocurrency entrepreneur Sam Bankman Fried.
But Singer, who is 78,
is as controversial as he is influential.
Some of his ideas,
like that parents should be allowed to pursue euthanasia
for severely disabled infants,
have led people to call him dangerous and worse.
Some of his ideas make me personally uneasy too,
but my discomfort and the way his work forces me
to reconsider my own ethical intuitions and assumptions
Is precisely why I wanted to talk with him
Here's my conversation with Peter Singer
Hi Peter, I'm David nice to meet you very nice to meet you David
You might be wondering why the journalist interviewing you today is sitting in a clothing
closet and just for your own context, I normally record in a normal room, but my neighbor has
decided today was the day to do some construction just outside my window.
Lovely.
Is there an ethical way I can get revenge?
No.
You should just let it go.
Well, that's not what I wanted you to say.
Just look at the Middle East, you can see where revenge gets you.
There you go.
Yeah.
I promise I don't mean this question at all in a facetious way.
It's a question about why you wrote this book, Consider the Turkey.
So it's a small book.
There aren't really new arguments in it. How do you decide whether writing that book was the best use of your time?
Could that time have been better spent doing something else?
Is that something that you think about?
This is an important issue.
We're talking about over 200 million turkeys who are reared in a way that comes close to
being described as torture. That is, they are mutared in a way that comes close to being described as torture.
That is, they're mutilated in various ways.
They're bred to live in such a way that it hurts them when they're getting near full
weight.
It hurts them to stand up because their immature leg bones don't bear the immense weight that
they've been bred to put on in a very short time.
They suffer at slaughter and then as I described in the book, if they get bird flu, the entire
shed is killed by heat stroke.
Quite commonly it's not the only method used in the United States, but it's used on millions
of birds.
The ventilation is stopped in the shed, heaters are brought in, and they are deliberately
heated to death over a period of hours. I think that's something that Americans don't know and it's really important. They should know because it should stop
So my concern is to reduce
Unnecessary avoidable suffering where I can that's one of my major goals throughout my career in philosophy and as an activist and
I think that that's definitely worth the time
it took to write this book.
But in reading the book, it feels pretty hard
to deny the unacceptable level of suffering that goes
into our Thanksgiving turkey dinners.
But millions of people are still going to have them.
So did you feel at all like you're
banging your head against a wall with this stuff?
No, I don't really feel like I'm banging my head against a wall.
I feel like I'm banging my head against something which is pretty hard but not completely unyielding
in some parts of the world.
We've made progress in the laws and regulations concerning animals.
The entire European Union has legislation that provides better animal welfare conditions
for animals in industrial agriculture than United States laws do, with the exception
of a small number of states, California being the most notable, that have had citizens initiated
referenda to produce better conditions. So on the whole, yes, things are still very bad, but I think it's possible to make progress
and I think we have to keep bringing these facts in front of the public and getting them
to think about what they're eating.
And the Thanksgiving meal as it's a family festive occasion seems like a really good
place to start.
You know, there's a cliched journalistic trope of how to talk to your ideologically
opposed relative at Thanksgiving.
Have you learned anything about how we can talk to people who disagree with our ideas
in a way that doesn't just make them sort of roll their eyes and ignore you?
Like if someone reads your book and then thinks, well, now I have something to say about whether or not we should be eating this turkey at Thanksgiving.
What guidance can you give them about how to have that conversation?
Well, that of course will depend on who your relatives are, what sort of relationship you have with them.
So there's all different sorts of possibilities.
But I do think that you can make progress with many people, be civil and reasonable,
say have a look at some of these facts and say, do you really want to support this?
You know, do you really want to be complicit in these practices?
If somebody doesn't accept the argument and just insists that, you know, this is irrelevant or they're not going to listen,
at some point you might say, well, if you want me at your Thanksgiving, I don't want to be there with a big bird sitting on the table,
who I know has suffered in the ways that the standard American Thanksgiving turkey has suffered.
At some point you would suggest drawing that hard line for someone.
Yes, at some point you want to say,
and I mean, isn't that true of important moral issues?
And I think this is that you just say,
look, I'm sorry, I can't go along with that.
This is just a question I have about what it's like to be you.
There aren't a lot of well-known philosophers around.
Do you find that sort that in your life,
people come to you looking for ethical advice?
They certainly do. They come to me online a lot nowadays.
In fact, in order to provide that and save my time for more effective things,
I have set up Peter Singer AI.
So on my website, you can connect to a chatbot who has been trained on all of my
works and actually does remarkably well in terms of channeling my views to people with
ethical queries.
I didn't set it up.
I had some friends doing this who knew more about the technical side of it.
But I have to say they've done a remarkably good job.
How do you feel about the fact that an AI has been able to
adequately replicate your ethical responses to questions?
I'm really happy about it.
I mean, partly just for the time-saving reason that I mentioned,
but also in a sense, it means that I can be immortal.
I mean, this me is not going to be around for,
well, I hope another decade maybe,
but not too much more than that probably.
Whereas the Peter Singer AI could be around for indefinitely.
So that's great, it's a kind of immortality.
I'm sure this is arguable,
but I think of you as being best known
for your work on animals and ethics,
which I think flow out of utilitarian principles, which
basically the belief that the right action is the one that produces the least suffering
or the most good.
But you're also seen as one of the godfathers of effective altruism.
Can you explain what effective altruism is and how it's different or builds on?
utilitarianism Sure
so effective altruism is the view that
firstly
We ought to try to make the world a better place that ought to be one of the goals of our life
Doesn't mean that that you know that we all have to become saints and think about that in everything we do
But it should be an important goal for people to think, what can I do to make the world better,
which might mean to reduce suffering, might mean to reduce premature death,
and to think about that in a global way, not just for me and my family and those close to me,
but to think about it for people anywhere
in the world and indeed for beings capable of suffering who are not of our species.
So effective altruism then developed into a kind of a social movement to encourage people
to do that and to think in that way.
And effective altruists have done a lot of research to try to find which are the most
effective charities in different areas. So it's become an important social movement.
What is the connection with utilitarianism? I think if you are a utilitarian, you ought to be
an effective altruist because if you're a utilitarian, you ought to want to reduce suffering and increase happiness.
And given that we all have limited resources to do that, even Bill Gates has limits and most of us
have much tighter limits on what we can do to make the world a better place. Surely we should be
using those resources as effectively as possible to do as much good as we can with the money we can donate
or the time we can volunteer or whatever it is.
We wanna make sure that that isn't spent on something
that does less good than some other alternative open to us.
And I think the rationality aspect of effective altruism
is one of the reasons why it's been so broadly attractive,
but also why it's been particularly attractive among entrepreneurs and in the tech world.
I think these are people who are sort of interested in the idea of rationality and quantification
and return on investment.
But of course, we know that some pretty prominent advocates
have been highly irrational.
The most egregious example would be a Sam Bankman freed,
or you could even look at something like,
was it that the Effective Ventures Foundation paid
15 million pounds for an English abbey?
Surely that money could have been used in ways
that caused more well-being.
And my question for you is, what advice do you have for effective altruists to guard
against self-interested, self-rationalization?
Yeah, I think that is a serious problem and I think that may have been the problem with
Sam Ankhman Fried.
It's not totally clear. Perhaps it wasn't exactly self-rationalization,
but it was certainly maybe a sense that I don't have to follow
the ordinary rules that other people do because I'm such a whiz kid.
I've been possible that there was some of that sort of thinking.
And I certainly think anybody who is very successful needs to guard against that belief that somehow they are above the rules.
But I don't see that generally as the case in the Effective Altruism Movement and the people who I talk to.
I think most of them are genuine and they're not self-deceived.
And yes, there may be a couple of conspicuous exceptions or mistakes that have been made.
So I think you need to take a hard look at that.
But I really think that they're the exception.
And I don't think that that's a reason for rejecting effective altruism as a positive
social force.
And, you know, an offshoot of effective altruism is a long-termism.
Basically, the idea that we have as much ethical responsibility to address
threats to humanity far off in the future as we do to threats to human lives
in the present. And I'm just curious, what do you make of long-termism? I accept the idea that when suffering occurs
is not affected by time.
So if I could be certain that something I did now
would do more to reduce suffering in a hundred
or even theoretically a thousand years than anything I could do to relieve suffering in 100 or even theoretically 1,000 years than anything I could do to relieve
suffering in the present, then sure, I would think that would be the right thing to do.
But of course, we don't have that certainty about the future.
So I think that's a big barrier to making a real priority to think about the future
as more important than thinking
about the present.
The other question that needs to be raised is quite a deep philosophical question about
the risk of extinction of our species, because that's what a lot of long-termists are focused
on.
They're saying, if our species sort of survives, gets through the next century or two, then it's likely
that humans will be around not just for thousands, but for many millions of years because by
then we'll be able to colonize other planets.
And you say, yes, but if we become extinct, none of that will happen.
So we must give a very high priority to reducing the risk of extinction of our species.
And that raises the question of, is it as bad that beings do not come into existence
and therefore do not have happy lives as it is that an already existing being who could
have a happy life is prevented from having a happy life or even has a miserable life?
And what's the answer?
Well, as I say, that's a really difficult philosophical
question.
I think it's still an open question, really.
Personally, I do think that it would be a tragic loss
if our species became extinct.
But how do we compare that tragedy with tragedies that might occur now to a billion people,
several billion people?
And I can't really give a good answer to that.
So in other words, what I'm saying is it might be reasonable to discount the future of these
beings who might not exist at all.
I think that's possible.
I think it could be reasonable to say,
no, we should focus on the present
where we can have greater confidence in what we're doing
than focus on the long-term really distant future.
I mean, I'm just a ding-dong,
but for me, it sort of seems like there are
common sense objections to long-termism.
You know, it's like, what would be an example be like?
If I see there's like an immediate fire in my yard that I could put out and save some people,
like shouldn't I obviously do that rather than say,
well, I'm working on a fire retardant system that could save millions
of lives at some undefined point in the future.
That's always what the long-termism stuff sounds like.
It sounds like sci-fi philosophizing.
Do you think there's like a common sense problem it runs into?
It runs into what appears to be a common sense problem because our intuitions obviously are
to help the people right there now, right?
We've evolved to deal with problems that are right there and now, and our ancestors survived because they dealt with those problems.
They didn't survive because they had strong intuitions that we ought to act for the distant future, because there was nothing that they could do about the distant future.
We now are in a position where we have more influence on whether there will be
a human future or not. So I'm inclined not really to trust those common sense intuitions.
My answer would still be, sure, you should put out the fire, not because that's just your common sense
intuition, but because you can be highly confident that you can do a lot of good there.
And anyway, you can put out the fire and go back to your work on the fire retardant tomorrow.
I think not trusting your common sense intuitions is sort of Peter Singer's whole bag.
I think that's right.
I think a lot of my work, you know, don't trust your common intuitions to think that you ought to help your
neighbors in your affluent community rather than distant people elsewhere in the world that you
can't relate to. That's part of what I talk about. Don't trust your intuitions in thinking that
really it's only humans that matter or human suffering that always is a higher priority than
any number of non-human animal suffering. Yeah, I think you're right.
I'm somewhat skeptical about trusting those moral intuitions.
Yeah. So you take these subjects or these moral intuitions
about things that people really hold closely, like what we eat
or how we spend our money, or even the notion that we're good.
And you say, like, well, hold on a second.
Are you really?
Where do you think your impulse to do that comes from?
Well, it's something that came gradually, I believe,
that I started thinking about particular issues where
it was obvious that you could reduce suffering, but people had intuitive reasons
for not doing so. And one of those was actually in the area of biomedical ethics, because I got
involved in those questions because I was interested in issues about death and dying. And I've, for a very long
time, been a supporter of medical assistance in dying. And when I started talking to people
about that, especially doctors, they would say, look, it's all right for us to allow people who are suffering to die by not treating them, but we can't cross
that line that actually assists them in dying because, and some of them would quote this little
thing that said, thou shalt not kill, but need not try officiously to keep alive.
And they would just trot that out as a kind of thing that, yes, that's obviously
true. And I would say, well, why? So I think that example was one where I was critical of intuitions.
They were perhaps religiously based intuitions. That was one part of it. So the fact that I
wasn't religious may have led me to challenge those intuitions.
But then I started thinking about a whole range of other intuitions that are probably
not religious, but may, like the example I gave, be based in what is it that helped our
ancestors to survive in the circumstances in which they were trying to survive and reproduce
when those circumstances may no longer apply to us.
I was reading the academic journal
that you edit, which is called The Journal
of Controversial Ideas.
The idea, as I understand behind the journal,
is to give sort of a rigorous academic treatment and platform
to ideas that might be seen as beyond the pale
for other outlets.
And there are plenty of what seems to be relevant arguments to do with public health and sort
of learning and academia.
And then there are also, you know, there are multiple pieces about when blackface should
be allowed, or I think the specific term is cross-racial makeup.
Or there's another piece in there in one of the issues about arguing for zoophilia.
Probably more people know as bestiality.
And I thought, well, who's clamoring for deeper arguments
in support of either of these things?
What is the point other than provocation?
I think both those issues, although they're certainly far less significant than many of
the other issues that articles in the journal discuss, I think they both have some significance.
The question about blackface, which was the word that was used in the journal, is relevant
to drawing lines about what are people going to get criticized for and
the article takes a nuanced approach to that. It acknowledges that there would be
cases in which you know using blackface would be offensive and say inappropriate
but it also refers to other cases in which it's not objectionable and so if
people are going to be sort of outed in some way for doing this,
and I know it happened to Justin Trudeau, I think, for having done that a long time ago,
then you do need to say, well, what are the cases in which this is not such a bad thing to do,
and which are the cases where it should be? And in the case of Zufilia, I mean-
Yeah, tell me that one.
Well, this is a crime. People go to jail for this and they may not be causing any harm.
I think that it's reasonable to say if somebody is going to be sent to prison to ask, have
you harmed any sentient being?
Should this be a crime?
Why should it be a crime?
Now there's maybe a very small number of cases would get prosecuted. But I think that's enough justification
for airing the issue.
And I know that people have criticized you
for not taking enough into account
aspects of personal experience
about what you might be fundamentally ignorant.
The example I'm thinking of here is the idea
that parents should have the right to terminate babies born
with severe disabilities that might cause them
to suffer terribly.
And the critics say that, you know,
you just can't wrap your head around the fact
that life is very different from your own,
might be just as valuable or involve just as much happiness.
And also that, you know, sort of these ideas
might be stigmatizing or objectifying
of non-normative bodies.
And I don't have a particularly insightful way
of putting the question, but do you think there's something
to that criticism that just sort of rationally theorizing
from a distance is missing something essential?
I think that rationally theorizing from a distance is missing something essential. I think that rationally theorizing from a distance easily can miss something essential,
certainly.
But I don't think that applies to my views about these cases because I formed those views
after having discussions not only with doctors in charge of treating infants born with
severe disabilities but also some of the parents of those of those infants or
parents of those children who were no longer infants. I had discussed
this with a number of people and both in person and and in letters that I had
from people who I remember one who said something,
it was really bitter, said,
the doctors got to play with their toys,
meaning their surgical equipment and their skills
at helping my son to survive.
And then they handed the baby over to us
and the result has been that my child
has suffered for nine years.
So I do think I find it strange that people in the disability or some people I should
say in the disability movement who are mentally as gifted as anyone but happen to be in wheelchairs
think that the fact that they are in a wheelchair gives them greater insight into what it's like to be a child with severe disabilities that are not just physical,
but also mental, or what it's like to be the parents
of children like that.
But I don't know that they're saying necessarily
that it gives them particular insights
into that specific example.
I think they're saying they might have specific insights
into what it's
like to live a different kind of life that you, for example, don't have and can't have
access to.
Yeah, that's true.
But that's generally not the kind of case that I'm talking about in suggesting that
parents ought to have the option of euthanasia in cases of very severe disabilities.
But do you think there's any way in which airing some of the more controversial philosophical
views you have has maybe been detrimental to your larger project?
You know, and this is the idea that people might be turned off by what Peter Singer has
to say about people with
disabilities and therefore they're not going to pay attention to what he has to say about
animal rights.
Do you think there's any trade-off there between saying what you think is true and saying what
you think will have the most impact?
I think there is a possible trade-off, yes. But it's particularly difficult as a philosopher
because I will always get asked these kinds of questions.
If I start to prevaricate or to try to be fuzzy about the answer,
I think my reputation standing as a philosopher falls because of that.
I think it's important to try to follow the argument wherever it goes.
Yes, there may be some costs to it, but it's hard to balance those costs against the
fact that you're regarded as a rigorous, clear-thinking philosopher.
And so people pay more attention to what you say for that reason.
I read your memoir, and I thought it was interesting.
Three of your four grandparents, I think they were living in Vienna, died at the hands of
the Nazis in the Holocaust.
And you write about your grandfather, was his name David Oppenheim?
That's correct, yes.
David Oppenheim, who was a collaborator of Freud's.
And you have a line in there where you say, or you write that, he spent his life trying
to understand his fellow human beings, yet seems to have failed to take the Nazi threat
to the Jews seriously
enough.
Maybe he had too much confidence in human reason and humanist values."
And I just wonder what the connection is between your grandfather's work and your work.
Do you see them as sort of interacting with each other or paralleling each other in any
way?
Possibly paralleling, but not really interacting because I didn't read my grandfather's work
until the late 1990s.
And I'd already written Animal Liberation, I'd already written Practical Ethics, I'd
already written Rethinking Life and Death.
So those books expressed my ideas relating to animals, relating to global poverty,
relating to abortion and assisted dying. But what you could point to, I suppose, would be that some
of my grandfather's general attitudes were passed down to me by my mother. She may have got them from
her father. And that would include the fact that I'm not religious. So some of that, I think, did get passed down to me, but not in terms of my specific views
about suffering.
Now, were they influenced by the knowledge of the suffering that the Nazis inflicted
on my grandparents and other members of my extended family, and indeed on my parents
by driving them out of their home in Vienna, of course. Yes, perhaps. Perhaps the brutality of what the Nazis did, the horror of that has
had an effect on me and that might have led to why trying to reduce suffering, trying to prevent unnecessary suffering
has been a very leading impulse
in the work that I've written.
You say it might have led,
are you just being nice to my line of questioning
or do you think it did lead to that?
No, I honestly don't know.
I mean, I think it's,
I don't have this sort of self awareness to say to what extent was
this knowledge of the Holocaust background of my family decisive in leading me in that
direction.
Would I have not have had that if I had not had that background?
I think, you know, that's, it's really impossible to answer that question.
And this is a self-awareness question.
When your mom was dying from Alzheimer's...
Yeah, it was some form of dementia.
I don't know if it was Alzheimer's exactly, but she certainly had dementia, yes.
You spent a fair amount of money on providing her care towards the end of her life, which
is obviously completely understandable. But was that the most utilitarian use of your money at that time?
And if not, did that teach you something about the limits of rational thinking when it comes
to helping people?
I think it was probably not the most utilitarian thing to do with those resources, but there
would have been personal costs to me, both in thinking that I hadn't looked after my
mother and also I had a sister.
If I had said, you can pay for my mother's care, but I'm not going to, obviously that
would have totally disrupted the really close and
warm relationship that I had with my sister all the way through her life and that would
have been a really heavy cost to me.
Now you could argue that okay, but the money could have helped many people in important
ways and therefore I was being in a sense self-interested in not wanting to cause that
family rupture.
But no, I think it was, yes.
So I guess that gets to your second question.
Does this say there's limits?
Yes, I think there are limits.
And certainly, I'm aware that there are limits to things that I am prepared to do in order
to produce the greatest good.
So to give a philosophical sort of mock example, if I'm at a beach and the
current has swept a number of people out to sea and I'm a strong swimmer and I can jump
in and save my daughter who's being swept out to my left, or I can jump in and save two
people, strangers who are being swept out to the right. Am I going to save more people and let my daughter drown?
No. So yes, in that sense, there were limits, but these limits
still allow us obviously to do much, much more good than most people are doing
because generally we don't have to make those tragic choices between
saving our children and saving a larger
number of strangers.
So yes, I'm working mostly in that area between those extremely demanding things that ethics
may require and where most people are where they don't even make very small sacrifices,
arguably not even sacrifices at all, given the fulfillment and meaning that
people get out of helping others. Are those limits you just described, are they a version of common
sense? Well, I think they're a version of what we can reasonably expect people to do, and maybe
it's not good to ask people to do more than we can reasonably expect them to do. So,
to put it in ethical terms, I think there's a distinction between what would be the right
thing to do to the extent that we act in a perfectly ethical way and what is the right
thing to ask others to do and perhaps even to do yourself, to think about or to feel
guilty if you don't do yourself and
that might take more account of the fact that we are not perfectly rational
beings not perfectly ethical beings that we are to some extent self-interested
and it's not going to be very productive or effective to ask people to do more
than those limits.
After the break, I asked Peter Singer about the places where his heart is in conflict with his head.
Let's say I'm punishing people who are really evil and have done horrible, cruel things using the death penalty. I can feel the pull of that. I feel the retributive sense of that. Hi, Professor Singer, how are you?
I'm very well.
I pulled up AI Peter Singer and was messing around with it.
You know, it punts on questions that I bet you're willing to have more definitive answers to.
You know, just for example, I asked it, you know, is it okay to kill one innocent person in order to save two?
And it doesn't give an answer. It just suggests I consider different perspectives, you know,
the perspectives of virtue ethics or the perspective of utilitarianism.
What's the point of AI, Peter Singer,
if it's unable or unwilling to answer specific ethical questions related to
your work with definitive answers like real life Peter Singer can?
Well, thank you for trying it out.
We are still in the trial stage.
We've been getting some feedback.
And I am actually aware of what you've just described.
And I am in contact with the person
who does the actual tinkering with the algorithms.
And I think that's a good point.
Obviously, we don't want Peter Singer AI
to make very definitive statements on areas,
on questions where I would not be prepared
to give a definitive answer,
but certainly I think it should give
straighter answers than it does.
It made me wonder if legal considerations
are baked into AI Peter Singer.
Not as far as I'm aware.
Or you think somebody might sue it?
Well, not sue it, but maybe there could be liability issues or uncomfortable issues
might arise if someone were to ask AI Peter Singer for ethical advice, you know,
in matters of life or death, and then went ahead and...
I see.
So it would become an accomplice to the crime.
I don't know.
I mean, interesting.
I've touched that would depend on the free speech, the constitutional
situation of freedom of speech in the country in which the person was.
Really interesting issue, which I've never, I haven't thought about yet.
We need to get your legal team on it.
If I had a legal team, yes.
And one of the things that I find myself struggling with about your
philosophical ideas is, you know, it relates to what Derek Parfit called
the repugnant conclusion, that if you follow some of your ideas
through to their logical conclusions,
you can wind up in some sort of morally disturbing places.
You know, example would be that, you know,
and tell me if I'm wrong, but according to your thinking,
a large number of people with lives barely worth living
could be considered better than a smaller number
of people living great lives.
And your response to that is what? My response on that particular case is that I'm actually, that's not,
now I'm being like you said, Peter Singer AI, that's not my clear view.
I'm still somewhat open-minded on that issue, but maybe you're asking a broader
question about whether views of this type, whether I might hold views that leave me uncomfortable in
some way or other. And yes, I think there are such views that I hold that will leave me quite
uncomfortable. Like what?
Why don't I come to you? Like what?
Uh, views about distribution of wellbeing.
Suppose, suppose that you have the choice of helping
people who are very badly off, um, by a small amount
or helping people who are reasonably well off already
by a much larger amount and you can't do both.
I mean, I think you can imagine cases where you spend a vast amount of resources making people,
a small number of people who are really badly off, slightly, barely perceptibly better off,
or you make, let's say, 95% of the population very significantly better off.
I think the right thing to do is to make 95% of the population significantly better off,
but I'm uncomfortable about the thought that, well, here are these people who are worse off,
and you could help them, but you don't.
But I'm trying to understand if there's ever a scenario in which an action is warranted simply
because we believe it's the right thing, regardless of what the empirical balance in lives lost
or not might be.
I mean, do you ever, can you, is there an example of an ethical place where your heart
wins out over your head?
Oh, I was just giving you one, right?
I mean, I feel-
Well, but not in like a thought experiment way, like a practical-
Oh, I see.
Real life way.
Let's say I'm punishing really people who are really evil
and have done horrible cruel things
using the death penalties.
I can feel a pull of that.
I feel a retributive sense of that,
but I'm not a retributivist.
sense of that, but I'm not a retributivist. I think most people, or I suspect most people,
see themselves as trying to make the world a better place or
on balance a net good for the world.
But how does someone know if they're
doing enough to make the world a better place?
Very few people are doing enough to make the world a better place. They're probably not. I
don't think that I'm doing enough to make the world a better place. But if you wanted to know
how would you know, you would look around for other ways of doing more to make the world a better place.
And you would say, there aren't any, that's the extreme position. As I say, I can't claim
to live up to that myself. But that would be the ultimate limit where you could be confident
that you've done everything you could to make the world a better place.
So where's the line short of that? The line short of that I think is to say, I'm doing a lot.
I'm thinking about how to make the world a better place.
I'm doing a lot more than the current social standard is.
I'm trying to raise that standard.
I'm setting an example of doing more than the current standard is. I think if you can say all of those things,
you can be content with what you're doing.
Professor Singer, thank you for taking the time
to speak with me. I appreciate it.
Thanks very much, David.
I've enjoyed both the conversations.
Hey, wait, one last bonus ethical question.
I'm in the closet again.
Yeah, I've noticed.
Because a different- Different neighbors is reconstructing noticed. Because a different neighbor is reconstructing that.
Different neighbor is reconstructing that?
Do you give me permission to have sweet revenge on that guy?
No, no revenge, but maybe more double glazing would help to keep the sand out.
All right, that I can do. That I could do. Thank you very much.
Great. Thanks a lot, David.
That's Peter Singer. His latest book,
Consider the Turkey, is available now.
This conversation was produced by Wyatt Orm.
It was edited by Annabel Bacon,
mixing by Afim Shapiro.
Original music by Dan Powell, Diane Wong,
and Marian Lozano.
Photography by Adam Ferguson.
Our senior booker is Priya Matthew,
and Seth Kelly is our senior producer.
Our executive producer is Allison Benedict.
Special thanks to Rory Walsh, Renan Barelli,
Jeffrey Miranda, Matty Masiello, Jake Silverstein,
Paula Schuman, and Sam Dolnik.
If you like what you're hearing, follow or subscribe to The Interview wherever you get
your podcasts.
To read or listen to any of our conversations, you can always go to nytimes.com slash The
Interview, and you can email us anytime at theinterview at nytimes.com.
I'm David Marchese, and this is The Interview
from The New York Times.