The Jordan B. Peterson Podcast - 133. Maps of Meaning 5: Story and Metastory 1
Episode Date: August 23, 2020In this lecture, I make the case that we each inhabit a story, describing where we are, where we are going, and the actions we must undertake to get from the former to the latter. These inhabited stor...ies are predicated on an underlying value system (as we must want to be where we are going more than we value where we are). In addition, they are frames of reference, allowing us to perceive (things that move us along; things that get in our way), make most of the world irrelevant (things that have no bearing
Transcript
Discussion (0)
Welcome to season 3 episode 20 of The Jordan B. Peterson Podcast.
I'm Michaela Peterson, Jordan's daughter.
I hope you enjoy this episode of Maps of Meaning Part 4.
Sorry I haven't been around for the intros and wonderful ads from our sponsors for the
last couple of episodes.
And I'm sorry I'm back if you were glad I was gone.
My family and my dad and I are still in Serbia, although I think we're planning to come
home in the next month.
We're seriously missing Canada.
Not looking forward to the 14-day quarantine though.
Seems a little unnecessary given the fact we've all had COVID and have now been recovered fully for over a month.
If you guys didn't know about the COVID, now you know, he's okay.
It really wasn't that bad.
I don't have much else to tell you really.
Life isn't easy.
We're still waiting for Dad to recover more.
It's been very difficult and it's still difficult.
It won't be hard forever, but it is right now.
If you're interested in staying up to date with what's going on, obviously I'll be updating
you here as well periodically.
I have my own podcast.
I interviewed Representative Dan Crenshaw, and that episode is coming out Tuesday, which
is exciting.
We talk about mental toughness,
something I would argue isn't being taught well enough these days.
I got taught mine from dad.
He taught me to never feel sorry for myself,
and that was one of the most important lessons I've ever learned.
Probably the most important, actually.
It's been hard this year to stand by watching him recover.
Obviously, most of my feelings are empathy for him,
but I think that's the only
reason I've been able to help really.
Anyway, enjoy the episode, stay sane out there.
Sleep is really important for your health.
You know how awful you can feel with jet lag?
A lot of that is just sleep disruption.
Hopefully, you've tried to improve your sleep, if not you should.
There are a few key things you can do.
Blackout curtains are a sleep mask, not using blue light a few hours before bed, sleeping in a cold
room and a quality mattress. We spend half our lives on a mattress, so it should be tailored
to your needs. The most comfortable mattress I've tried is from Helix Sleep. If you go
to helix sleep.com slash Jordan and take their two minute sleep quiz, they'll match you
to a customized mattress.
A feature that's cool too is for couples.
Helix can split the mattress down the middle, providing individual support needs and feel
preferences for each side.
They have a 10-year warranty and you get to try it out for 100 nights risk-free.
They'll even pick it up for you if you don't love it, but I'm sure you will.
Right now, Helix is offering up to $125 off all mattress orders. Get up to $125 off at helixleap.com slash Jordan. That's helixleap.com
slash Jordan for up to $125 off your mattress order. Helixleap.com slash Jordan.
Season 3, Episode 20, Maps of Meaning, Part 4, a Jordan B. Peterson lecture. Now that you've had an opportunity to walk through a narrative, then hopefully some of
the things that I'm going to say that are more technical will make more sense.
And so what we're going to do today, at least in part, is to start to deal with conceptualizing a solution
to the fact that the world is too complex to properly perceive.
So what the problem fundamentally is,
is that there's a lot more of everything else
than there is of you, especially if you include in that
everything else, all the parts of you that
you also don't understand.
And so I want to walk you through how I think we solve that at least in part, and we do
that essentially by simplifying the world.
But I think mostly that we simplify it as a place in which to act rather than a place in which
to perceive objects.
And I really believe that there's a critical distinction between those two things.
And I think that part of the reason that there's been a continual tension, say, between
the claims of science, and let's say the claims of religion is because the idea
that the world has a place of objects and as a place to act have to be considered separately
isn't properly understood.
I don't know.
So I'm going to try to straighten that up to the degree that that's possible.
So I'm going to talk to you about stories and meta-stories.
And the story is this, I would say,
it's the simplest unit of useful information
with regards to action and perception
that you can be offered.
And then a meta-story is a story about how a story
like that transforms.
And I would say we'll concentrate on the structure of the story, and then we'll concentrate on the structure of the story and then we'll get into the structure
of the meta-story and that'll constitute today's class.
So the first thing I want to show you, I know many of you have seen this, but I'm going
to show it anyways. for the longest time it was presumed that the longest time say at least in the 20th century,
it was presumed that we make a pretty complete model of the world and then we act in the world
and we compare what happens to that model and as long as our model and the world are matching,
then roughly speaking,
we believe that everything is okay
and our emotions stay under control.
But if that model mismatches,
then we know that something's up.
Now, a lot of this work was done by Russians, especially in the early 60s, by two Russian scientists Vinogodov and
Sokolov, who were students of Alexander Luria, who was arguably the greatest
neuropsychologist of the 20th century. Luria spent a lot of time studying soldiers
from World War II that had received head injuries
and a various sorts.
And because of that, he could draw inferences
about how the brain worked and some of what we're going
to talk about over the upcoming weeks with regards
to brain function.
Much of it is predicated on Luria's work.
And Sokolov and Vinigred Over were his students.
And they were interested in this phenomena.
They were interested in psychophysiological measurement, right?
So as a way of inferring brain function and so psychophysiological measurement is
measurement of those physiological parameters, say like pupil width or skin
conductance or EEG that are in some ways directly reflective of how the brain works.
Now if you measure skin resistance, skin resistance changes with the amount that you sweat and
that can change very, very rapidly and it changes in response to physiological demands placed
on your body.
So for example, if your body assumes that you're going to leap
into action for some purpose, then it's going to open up your pores to prepare you to
keep yourself cool. And you can measure those transformations quite accurately by measuring
the electrical resistance of the skin. And so what you see, if you put someone in a lab
chair and you expose themselves to different stimuli.
You find that, for example, if you expose them to something that's threatening, say like
a picture of a snake, then their skin conductance will decrease because they're, sorry, their
skin conductance will increase because they sweat a little bit more.
It's quite a rapid response.
It can be a very rapid response. It can be a very rapid response. Now, one of the things that Sokolov or...
Yeah, that's right. Noted was that if he...if I sat you down, for example, and I put some headphones on you,
and I played a tone to you that repeated just exactly the same tone that repeated at predictable intervals,
that the first time you heard the tone, you'd produce quite a spike in skin conductance.
And the next time a slightly smaller spike, and then the next time a slightly smaller spike
until after maybe you'd heard it three or four times, you would not respond to it at all.
And that was often regarded as habituation.
And habituation is the same thing that you can see in snails, for example.
And I'm using snails as an example because they have very, very simple nervous systems.
So if you take a snail and you poke it, then like it comes out of a shell and you poke it,
it'll go back into a shell. And then it'll come out. And if you poke it again, it'll go back into
a shell, and it'll come out. But if you keep doing that, sooner or later, the snail will just stop
going in. And you might think of that. sooner or later, the snail will just stop going in.
And you might think of that.
It has been conceptualized as the simplest form
of learning habituation.
And the behavior is tended to presume
that if a human being manifested a response that could
be modeled by a simple organism, then the human being
was using a response that was analogous to that
of the simple organism.
And sometimes that's true. And sometimes that's true.
And sometimes it's not.
So for example, you have simple reflexes that,
if you put your hand on a hot stove, you'll jerk back.
And that's of quite a simple circuit.
You move your hand back before the message gets to your brain.
Because the spinal cord is smart enough
to mediate reflex like that all by itself.
So your brain is actually quite distributed throughout your body.
It's not just in your head, like people tend to think.
And so we have conserved fast acting reflexes
at various levels of our nervous system.
They aren't capable of sophisticated response.
It's pretty much stimulus response,
thinking about it from the behavioral perspective,
but they have as an advantage incredible speed
because there just aren't that many neural connections
between the stimulus and the response.
And so we have layers of response at different time frames
that help us match with the demands of the external environment.
So Charles Darwin, for example, used to go into the, I think,
was museum in England.
I don't remember the name of it.
They had a snake in there.
I believe it was a cobra.
And he'd stick his face up at the glass
and the cobra would strike at him.
And he'd jerk back.
And he tried many, many times to master
that reflexive response to the snake.
But there was no way.
Every time that thing struck at him, he'd jump backwards.
Well, you can imagine the survival utility in a reflex like that, but in reflexes in general.
Okay, so back to Sokolov. Now, what he decided thought, if you took that tone and you did anything
to it, that was perceptible, right? Because there are certain gradations of tone that you're not
capable of perceiving, but let's assume youations of tone that you're not capable of
perceiving. But let's assume you took the tone and you adjusted it enough so that it was
perceptibly louder, or it was perceptibly a different frequency or something like that.
Or even that the spaces between the tones, because I said they were predictably spaced,
even though if the spaces between the tones were changed, then when the change occurred,
the orienting reflex would be reinstated.
You'd respond to it again.
And Sokolov tried to vary the tone on many, many parameters.
But no matter what parameter he varied it on,
as long as you could detect it perceptibly,
you'd produce an orienting reflex.
So Sokolov's idea was that you must be producing
a complex
internal model of the world that's in concordance with the world across pretty much every
perceptible dimension. Because if you weren't doing that, how in the world would you know that
the tone had changed from what you had already learned about it? And so for the longest time,
and this was also true for people who were investigating artificial intelligence,
we had this idea that what people did was make a complex model of the world and hold it in their mind, so to speak.
And then they'd act in the world, and they'd compare what they expected to happen in the world with the model.
And as long as there was a match, then there was no orienting reflex.
Now, the orienting reflex turns out to be quite a complex reflex.
It's not merely an alteration in skin conductance.
What it is in essence is the manner in which you start to unfold your response to the unknown
and the initial stages of that are very, very quick.
But it's hard to tell when the orienting reflex stops and when more complex learning begins,
they sort of shade into one another.
So the initial stages of the orienting reflex are quite reflexive, but the later stages
can be extraordinarily complex.
So for example, well, I always think the example of betrayal is the best one because it's
so complex.
So imagine that you come home and you find evidence lipstick or something like that.
Evidence that the person that you're with is betraying you.
The first thing that's going to happen is that you're going to orient.
There's going to be a real shock and that's reflexive.
It's very much akin to the response that you're going to, that you would manifest if you saw
a predator or snake or something like that.
So that's very instantaneous, you know.
And then that'll prepare you for action.
You'll get ready to do whatever it is that you need to do next.
That would be very unpleasant thing.
But then it might take you even years to fully manifest the learning
that would be necessary in a situation like that,
because there's so many things that you have to reconsider.
First of all, the person might now appear to you as a threat.
That's pretty immediate.
So there's a biological, physiological response first,
your body reacts first, then you respond emotionally.
That's going to take a while and that emotional response
might extend over days or weeks or months or even years.
And then as you're doing that as well,
you're going to try to start to
resort out your interpretive schema so that it can adjust to the transformation that this
this error on your part say or this catastrophe or this betrayal it has to adjust to whatever
information that event contains and so the or Reflex can manifest itself over an extraordinarily
long period of time.
It's best to think about it as the initial part of what can be a very complex learning process.
Now that was a standard idea in psychology for the longest period of time that we created
a detailed internal model of the world.
We watched how the world was unfolding.
We compared the two.
And the physiology, the neurophysiology of this was even understood to some degree, even
by the Russians in the early 1960s, because they basically localized, you could use complex
EEG, electro and cephalogram technology to localize where the orienting reflex was occurring in the brain.
And basically it appeared to occur roughly speaking in the
hippocampus and the theory arose that your brain, your cortex,
let's say, produced a very complex model of the world, an
internal model, and your senses were producing a model of the
external world. And the hippocampus was watching those two
things to see if they matched. And if they didn't match, there was a mismatch signal, and that wouldocampus was watching those two things to see if they matched.
And if they didn't match, there was a mismatch signal, and that would be the orienting reflex,
and then your body would start to prepare itself for whatever that mismatch meant, and then
you would engage in exploratory behavior to try to update your model.
That was the standard theory.
It was very well accepted theory. It has elements of cybernetic theory in it,
but it was well accepted enough so that when people first
started to experiment with artificial intelligence,
that's how they tried to make artificial intelligence systems.
They tried to make ones that would model the world
and then act and then compare the changes in the world
to that model.
But that didn't go anywhere, as it turned out,
because it turned out that it's so difficult to see
and model the world that people had no idea
how complex that was.
It was impossibly complex as it turned out.
And so that's part of the reason
we don't have robots wondering around
doing apparently simple things,
like walking in an environment like this.
Now, when we look at the environment,
we think, well, it's not that hard to look at,
it's full of objects, and they're just self-evident,
there they are, and we can just wander through it.
And we don't even do that consciously
to any great degree, because so much of that perception
is presented to our consciousness without effort,
in some sense.
But the AI guys learned pretty quick that perceiving the world was way more difficult than anybody had guessed.
And then this experiment really in some sense put the phenomenological,
put a phenomenological punch behind that observation.
Because one of the presuppositions of the orienting reflex theory that I just laid out was that
you were very good at detecting changes
that your nervous system would automatically detect change,
anomaly, right?
Any mismatch between your model and what you expected.
And then, well, the AI guys, I think, figured out,
first of all, that that was a big problem,
that the problem of perception was much more complicated than that.
You know, it's actually, it's out of that same set of observations in some sense that postmodernism
emerged in literature, because in literary criticism, because, well, it turns out to be hard
enough to see a normal object like a chair. And part of that is, you know, if you just do that to
the chair, it's really different
than it was before. You could imagine how different it would be if you tried to paint the
chair under both those conditions, right? And if you were really good at looking at it, you'd
find that even though, if I asked you what color this is, you'd say white, if you were actually
painting it, you'd find out that the colors of the chair, when it's in that location, and the colors in the chair, when it's in that location,
just because of the difference in lighting are substantially different.
I think it was Monet, I think, who painted a very large series of haystacks in the French countryside,
right, under in different seasons and under different conditions of illumination,
just because he was exploring how radically different the same object could be
as it moved through contexts. And so it isn't even obvious why we how radically different the same object could be as it moved through context.
And so it isn't even obvious why we think this is the same object when you move it.
And the answer is something like, well, you can sit on it in both positions,
which is not a description of an object, by the way.
Right? That's a description of something that's useful, something that's a tool,
something that exists in relationship to your body.
It's not an object. of something that's useful, something that's a tool, something that exists in relationship to your body.
It's not an object.
And so, if you think that just looking at something like a chair is almost impossibly difficult,
and subject to interpretation, then imagine how difficult it is to perceive something like a text,
you know, like a novel, because a novel obviously is subject to multiple interpretations. And the interpretations are going to depend on, well, at least in principle,
on the intent, conscious and unconscious of the author,
of the time, of the place, of the culture, of the language.
Then that's just on the side of the production itself, but then there's the reader.
It's like, I've read books when I was 16 and then re-read them,
say when I was 40, and the book was almost completely different
as far as I was concerned, partly because I knew what was
in it the second time, and I didn't know what was in it
the first time.
And so the meaning that manifests itself out of a book
is a consequence of all the complexity of the book,
plus all the complexity of the book plus all the complexity
of the reader. And so, you know, if you're reading Russian literature, for example, and you've
already read 50 Russian novels, you're going to be in a much more different, you're going to be
in a different interpretive space than you are if, say, the Russian novel is the first novel you've
ever read. And so, and the postmodernists were grappling with this,
as well as with many other ideas that I think contaminated their thinking,
and their conclusion was, well, you can't extract out a canonical meaning from a text.
It's so dependent on the situation that, to say the text has a interpretable meaning,
is actually an error.
Now, just because it's difficult to do something doesn't mean it's impossible.
And there's massive holes in the postmodernist view as far as I think it's an unbelievably
pathological view personally. But the thing is, is that there are reasons why it emerged.
And the reasons were analogous to the reasons
that the AI project initially failed.
And analogous to the reasons that this experiment
turned out the way it did.
So I'm going to show you this.
Many of you have seen this already, but as I said,
it doesn't matter.
So the job, your job here, is to count the time.
See, there's a team of three people here dressed in white.
And there's a team of three people here dressed in white and there's a team of three people
here dressed in black and your job is to count the number of times the white team throws the
basketball back and forth to the white team members, okay, so we'll just run that. Okay, well so
obviously, or perhaps not so obviously, the number of times I believe that they threw it back,
they threw it back and forth was 16, if I remember this correctly.
But of course, that's not really the issue,
because what happens in the middle of the scene
is that guy wearing a gorilla suit comes out
into the middle of the screen and pounds his chest three or four times.
And he comes out quite slowly, as you saw.
How many of you, is there anybody here who didn't see the gorilla? No, well, you and I presume all of you knew about
this video anyways. So Dan Simon who produced this video has got a couple of other ones
where he shows that, you know, even if you're smart enough to see the gorilla, because you've seen
the video before you've heard about it, if you make other changes in the background, you'll count
properly and you'll catch the gorilla, but you'll you make other changes in the background, you'll count properly and you'll catch the grill
but you'll miss the other changes in the background
and they're not trivial either.
And it's really quite remarkable.
He's produced other short videos, for example,
where you'll be looking at a field
and a road will grow in it,
occupying about a third of the photograph space
and you'd think, well, yeah, you're gonna see that.
It's like, you don't, you don't, well, yeah, you're gonna see that's like you don't you don't so
Okay, so this through this through a big spanner into the works this sort of experiment along with the AI failures
And we could even say the postmodern dilemmas like well
everyone virtually
every psychologist
What have predicted before this series of experiments that there's no damn way you'd miss that gorilla.
Because your nervous system was actually attuned to change in the environment, and like that's
a big change, and it's also a gorilla.
It's something you would really think that you couldn't miss, you couldn't possibly miss,
especially when it's occupying the center of the visual field.
And so, well, this is part of a phenomena called
change blindness, and it helped psychologists
who had been studying the visual system
for a very long time figure out,
well, mostly figure out exactly how blind human beings are
because we're way blinder than we think.
And so we actually focus on much less of the world
than we think.
And we do that partly.
It's not exactly obvious how we do it.
It's kind of like we hold a still picture in our imagination
and then fill in the details by using our central foveal vision,
which is always dancing around like a pinpoint or a laser beam
moving back and forth.
And we're assembling those little snapshots from the fovea
into a relatively coherent picture.
Maybe what happens is that I look at you, and then I look at you,
and I've still got the information from looking at you,
so my brain can sort of infer that that's
remained stable, but if I look at you, and I try to learn how
to do this, because you can look at something,
and then pay attention to the periphery.
It's annoying, but so if I'm looking at you,
I really can't make out your eyes.
I can more or less make out the fact that you have a head.
I can see that you're, and especially if you move it.
And so that's what your periphery,
sort of like frog vision or dinosaur vision,
it's much better at picking up movement
than it is at picking up something that's staying still and that makes
sense because well if it's staying still then and it hasn't already hurt you then
it's probably not going to hurt you but if it's moving then you know that's a
good thing that you might pay attention to and so if your periphery catches
movement then you'll focus your fovee on it it's like you go from really low
resolution to really low resolution
to really high resolution.
And so the center of your vision is incredibly high resolution.
But then it fades into low resolution
as you move towards the periphery until it's out here,
which would say be about 170 degrees.
I really, if I concentrate on this hand,
I can tell it's a hand mostly when it's moving.
I have no idea what color it is.
This one I can't see at all.
And then I can probably see my fingers now.
And then I can clearly see them if I look at them with my fovea.
And so your vision is a very, very, very strange thing.
And it's focusing on something very specific.
And so you're pointing your eyes at something, very specific, and that's what you seem
to see.
And so then that opens up a whole new universe of questions.
It's like, how do you decide what to point your eyes at?
That turns out to be an insanely complicated problem.
John Verveki talks about that all the time as the problem of relevance.
But, and the issue is, well, there's many, many things in the world. There's an infinite number of things, let's say. And you're not going to be able to see them. That's for sure, even if they
happen to be changing, as it turns out. And so, out of this mess, first of all, how do you pick
what to look at? And second, even if you do pick it, how do you see it? Because it's so crazily complicated.
So that's the problem that we're going to try to unpack.
Now, roughly speaking, what seems to have happened
with the gorilla video is you have to take that first theory
that you make a complete model of the world
and then a complete model of the world, which
is the objects in the world and how they're interacting.
And you compare that to the objects in the actual world and how they're interacting.
You have to modify that model.
You say, well, no, you're certainly not making a complete model.
And people should have known better anyways, even subjects to the limits of your perceptions.
Because there's all sorts of things in the world that you can't directly perceive.
But what you're doing instead is it's something like,
you're making a partial model of the world,
but you're only making a partial model of the world
that you're currently operating on that,
on, on, with some goal in mind.
And you're also comparing that to a model of the world
as it's currently unfolding.
Because the other thing that was implicit,
this is really tricky, this is where you have to watch
your implicit assumptions. The other thing that was implicit, this is really tricky, this is where you have to watch your implicit assumptions.
The other thing that was implicit in the original cybernetic theory was that you have a model
of the world that's complete, and then what you're watching is the actual world as it
unfolds, and that's not a model.
That's just your perception of the objects, but that also turns out to be wrong because your perception of the world has it unfolds
is also a model.
And so what's happening is you look at the world,
the world you see is a model,
and a very partial model at that,
and then you compare it to the model
that you expect or desire more accurately,
desire, although the initial models were expectation.
Because if you're in the lab
listening to tones, it's not like you desire anything, but mostly when you're
acting in the world, you have desires, and so the experimental constraints skewed
the data in some sense by making people assume that what people were doing when
they walked through the world was expecting instead of desiring. Anyways, you have
a model of the world that's generated as youiring. Anyways, you have a model of the world
that's generated as you look at it.
You have another model of the world
that's something like the world that you desire.
Then you compare both of them and they can mismatch
and they can mismatch in a way that upsets your current pursuit.
That's the critical issue.
You don't see the anomaly unless it upsets your current pursuit.
And you kind of know that too,
because when you're like,
while I'm lecturing to you guys,
you know, mostly you're sitting still,
but people are moving their arms
and they're moving their glasses
and they're shifting their feet.
And generally, I don't see any of that
because what difference does it make?
You know, it's not relevant to the ongoing,
to the ongoing what? On going contract, the ongoing series of interactions.
It's something like that.
So as long as you keep your movements bounded within a range that doesn't interfere with
whatever it is that we're doing, then it's going to be as invisible to me as the gorilla
was when you were counting the balls.
And the cool thing is about the gorilla experiment, or one of them, is that the reason you were
blind to the gorilla was because you were counting the balls.
And so that's so fascinating because what it shows to a huge degree, an unfathomable
degree, to unfathomable degree, is that the value structure that you inhabit determines what you perceive.
It doesn't just determine what you expect or want.
It bloody well determines what you see.
And that makes the world a completely different place.
No one really expected that.
And so if you watch the basketballs, you see the basketball, you see the basketball.
If you stop watching the basketball, well then you see the gorilla.
And so the first question that arises from an experiment like that is, well, just exactly
what is it that you don't see in the world?
And the answer is, all of it.
You see so little, it's unbelievable.
You see that tiny amount that's necessary for you to undertake the next sequence in your plotted movements,
something like that.
But then that becomes very complicated too because it isn't obvious how you can conceptualize
or how you can determine what your next movement is because it's not like you just add up
movements and make up your life.
It's not that simple. And it's related to the novel problem,
the problem of meaning in a literary work.
So you imagine, you're trying to specify
the meaning of a literary work.
Well, there's meaning in the word,
and then, but the word is dependent,
the meaning of the word is dependent on the phrase
within which it's embedded.
And then the meaning of the phrase
is dependent on the sentence that it's embedded embedded. And then the meaning of the phrase is dependent on the sentence that it's embedded in,
and the sentence in the paragraph, in the paragraph, in the chapter, and the chapter,
in the book, and the book, and the corpus of that sort, and then within the culture,
and then within whatever your peculiar personal experience is, all of those things nested
are operative to some degree when you're extracting out the meaning at any level of analysis.
They're all operating simultaneously. So you might say, well, what are you doing in this classroom?
Well, the answer is sitting in a chair. But that's obviously that's a very short term and context independent answer. But you're also attending to what I'm saying hypothetically,
and you're attending to some of it and not to other parts of it.
You're thinking about some parts of it and not other parts.
And you're also attending a class and the class is a sequence of lectures.
And that's embedded within your desire to finish up the semester and then to finish up the year and then to get your degree.
And then you nest that inside whatever it is,
whatever the reason is that you're getting your degree.
And then maybe that's nested inside your career goals
and that's nested inside your life goals
and that's nested inside your ultimate values
which you may or may not even be aware of.
And so I could say, well, you're sitting here
because it serves your ultimate values.
Well, that's true. It seems a bit abstract to be useful, right? It gets so vague out at
the outer most levels that it doesn't really have much specificity, right? So it seems
to lack information. But by the same token, if I said what you're doing is sitting there,
it has the same problem of
two restricted meaning because of overspecificity.
And so there's some level in there that you would interpret as meaningful, God only knows why, and that's the level
there's a natural level of perception for that sort of thing. So for example,
when children learn
to name an animal, for example, they'll
name cat. They don't name the species of cat or the subspecies of cat. And they don't
confuse cats with dogs, even though they're both in the category of four-legged furry
mammal. So why not call a cat and a dog a furry mammal. Well, children don't do that.
They go to cat and dog, and people who've studied
the acquisition of language have found
that there are basic level categories
that children pick up first, and they're often represented
with short words.
And the words are short because they've been around
a long time because they seem to reflect the natural level
at which people perceive the world.
But none of that's obvious.
You could just lump all the animals together for that matter and just call them animals, which we do sometimes.
So anyway, so it's very difficult to specify the meaning level,
and it's not very easy at all to figure out how we do it.
And so that's partly what I'm trying to unpack.
So here's part of the issue. So let's say that you have a computer. Yeah, I have a story
for this. So one time when I was in Montreal, I was using my computer is in my apartment.
And I was typing out an essay and it crashed.
And so what happens when your computer crashes?
Well, usually you utter some sort of curse.
And it's interesting that you do that because the circuit
that you use to curse with is the same circuit
that monkeys use to detect eagles or leopards or snakes.
And so when there's a bunch of monkeys together, they're not all preyed on by eagles and leopards
and snakes, but there's usually a predator in that category for every single monkey population.
And so when the monkeys are watching, they have an emotional adherence that the most nervous
monkey might utter first that basically says, you
know, hide from the eagle, get out on a thin branch so the cougar can't eat you and look
the hell out for the snake.
But there's a circuit that's linked to emotions that produces an instinctive utterance that
represents that category.
And that's the same circuit that you use when you curse.
And it's not the same circuit that you use when you curse. And it's not the same circuit that you use for normal language.
And we know that because that circuit is activated
in people who have Tourette syndrome
because they preferentially swear.
You think, well, why in the world would you
have a neurological condition that makes you preferentially
curse?
Well, that's the reason.
You don't just have one linguistic circuit.
You have one for, oh my god, there's a predator.
And that's the one
that will get activated when something happens like your computer crashing. Because, you
know, you're an evolved creature. And so those old circuits that were there say 30 million
years ago to deal with exceptions are the same circuits you're using now to deal with your
computer. Why else would you want to hit it? Because that's what you want to give at a whack.
It's like it doesn't behave whack, aggression right away.
Well, that's some clue as to the category system
that you're automatically using to encapsulate the event.
OK, so fine, what do you do when your computer crashes?
Well, first you curse, and then you
do the stupid things that idiot primates do when they're trying to deal with something
that's way too complex.
And maybe you turn it on and off, right?
And that doesn't work.
It didn't work.
And so then I thought, well, maybe the power bar went.
So I checked the power bar.
I turned it on and off, and nothing happened.
And so I brought a light behind the computer.
The light wouldn't go on.
And so I thought, aha, I must have blown a fuse.
So I went to the fuse box and took a look,
but the fuses were fine.
And so I thought, oh, the power's gone out.
So then I went outside and the power was out.
None of the street lights were working.
The power was out everywhere.
And it was seriously out because this was the time
that almost the entire Northeast power grid
in Quebec collapsed.
And the reason it collapsed is because there was a solar flare.
That happens reasonably often.
And the solar flare produced a huge electromagnetic pulse
because it's basically like a billion hydrogen
bombs going off at the same time, 93 million miles away.
Produces this tremendous electromagnetic pulse, passes through the
earth's atmosphere, produces a spike in current in the main power lines and blows the whole
system.
And so just so you know, an event like that happens about every 150 years, and if we had one
now it would take out all of our electronics, like one of the big ones.
There's a big one back in the late 1800s. Everything.
Satellites, computers, cars, everything.
Gone.
And so that's a big problem.
And no one knows what to do about it.
One missed us by about nine minutes, I think, two years ago.
So that's something else to worry about if you're inclined to worry about those sorts of things.
Okay, so what did I conclude from that?
Well, the function of my computer
was dependent on the stability of the sun.
It's not the first thing you check out when your computer
crashes, right?
You don't run out and go, hey, well, yeah, the sun's still there.
No problem.
I can cross that off the list.
But to me, it's an extraordinarily interesting example
of the invisible interdependence of things,
and our tendency to fragment.
What we seem to do is to look at things
at the simplest level of analysis that actually functions.
So for example, when you're interacting with your computer,
you're not interacting with your computer at all, really.
You're interacting with the keyboard, sort of one key at a time,
and you're interacting with the symbols on the screen, but as long as the
computer is working, you don't care about it at all.
You don't give it a second thought, and you certainly don't care about the fact that
it's dependent on, well, the electrical power, for example, and the electrical power is dependent on,
you know, I don't know, how many men are out there right now, or we're out there last night when it was freezing rain,
fixing power lines and freezing to death while they're doing it so that your stupid computer doesn't malfunction while you're watching cat videos.
You know, I mean, there's this incredibly dynamic living system
that's social and economic and political
that has to remain dead stable in order for us
to have access to functional and like pure non-fluxuating
electricity, 100% of the time.
Because you also don't think, well, the stability
of your computer is dependent on the stability
of the political system, but of course it is, because if the political system mucks up
and the economic system goes, then people don't go out and work to fix things, and things
are breaking all the time, that's their normal state is broken, not working.
And so, and that's all, in some sense, folded up, not only inside your computer,
but actually inside your conceptions of the,
your tiny conceptions of the computer while you're using it.
And you only get a glimpse of what the computer is really like when it doesn't work.
Then it's when it becomes a complex object, right?
As long as it's working, then your stupid perceptions are perfectly fine to get the job done.
And that's another indication that what you're using your perceptions for is to get the job done.
And how you specify exactly the level of resolution that you should be operating at,
I haven't sorted that out, but it's something like you default to the simplest level that moves you to the next step.
So for example, and generally that is what you should do if you're having an argument
with someone that you have a long-term relationship with.
You can start by arguing about what the little argument is about, or you can immediately cascade
into whether or not you should have a relationship with this person at all, or even into whether
or not you should even bother with relationships.
Which is, you know, every time there's an argument, that question is a reasonable question
to have emerge, or at least it's in the realm of potential reasonable questions, but it doesn't
seem useful to jump to the most catastrophic possible explanation.
Every time some minor thing goes wrong, that's what happens to people who have an anxiety disorder.
And that's what happens to people who are depressed, right? They can't bind the
anomaly. And so what happens is it tends to propagate up the entire system until it takes out their highest order
conceptualizations. You know, so if you're seriously depressed, maybe you'll watch a news article about something stupid and you'll think,
Jesus, why should I even be alive?
You know, and I'm dead serious about that.
If you score like 60 on the Beck Depression inventory, which puts you way to hell up in
the depressed range, anything that happens to you that's negative will trigger suicidal
thoughts, roughly speaking.
And sometimes even positive things will do it because there are very few positive things
that happen that don't carry with them
some threat of change or transformation.
So one mystery, it's a big mystery, is why don't you fall into a catastrophic depression
every time something little goes wrong?
Because it's not that level of analysis is not self-evident. And you see this with people who are high in neuroticism too, you know?
They're trivial...
Welcome to season 3, episode 20 of The Jordan B. Peterson Podcast.
I'm Michaela Peterson, Jordan's daughter.
I hope you enjoy this episode of Maps of Meaning Part 4.
Sorry I haven't been around for the intro, and wonderful ads from our sponsors for the
last couple of episodes.
And I'm so random back if you were glad I was gone.
My family and my dad and I are still in Serbia, although I think we're planning to come
home in the next month.
We're seriously missing Canada.
Not looking forward to the 14 day quarantine though.
Seems a little unnecessary given the fact we've all had COVID and have now been recovered
fully for over a month.
If you guys didn't know about the COVID, now you know, he's okay. It really wasn't that bad.
I don't have much else to tell you really. Life isn't easy. We're still waiting for Dad to recover
more. It's been very difficult and it's still difficult. It won't be hard forever, but it is right
now. If you're interested in staying up to date with what's going on, obviously I'll be updating
you here as well periodically.
I have my own podcast.
I interviewed Representative Dan Crenshaw, and that episode is coming out Tuesday, which
is exciting.
We talk about mental toughness.
Something I would argue isn't being taught well enough these days.
I got taught mine from dad.
He taught me to never feel sorry for myself, and that was one of the most important lessons
I've ever learned.
Probably the most important lessons I've ever learned. Probably the most important actually.
It's been hard this year to stand by watching him recover, obviously most of my feelings
are empathy for him, but I think that's the only reason I've been able to help really.
Anyway, enjoy the episode, stay sane out there.
Sleep is really important for your health.
You know how awful you can feel with jet lag?
A lot of that is just sleep disruption.
Hopefully you've tried to improve your sleep, if not you should.
There are a few key things you can do.
Blackout curtains are a sleep mask, not using blue light a few hours before bed, sleeping
in a cold room and a quality mattress.
We spend half our lives on a mattress, so it should be tailored to your needs.
The most comfortable mattress I've tried is from Helix Sleep.
If you go to helixleap.com slash Jordan and take their 2 minute sleep quiz, they'll
match you to a customized mattress.
A feature that's cool too is for couples.
Helix can split the mattress down the middle, providing individual support needs and feel
preferences for each side.
They have a 10 year warranty and you get to try it out for 100 nights
risk-free. They'll even pick it up for you if you don't love it, but I'm sure you will. Right now
Helix is offering up to $125 off all mattress orders. Get up to
$125 off at helixleap.com slash Jordan. That's helixleap.com slash Jordan for up to
$125 off your mattress order. Helixleap.com slash Jordan for up to $125 off your mattress order.
helixleap.com slash Jordan.
Season 3, episode 20, maps of meaning part 4, a Jordan B. Peterson lecture.
Now that you've had an opportunity to walk through a narrative, then hopefully some of the things that I'm going to say that
are more technical will make more sense.
And so what we're going to do today, at least in part, is to deal with, to start to deal
with conceptualizing a solution to the fact that the world is too complex to properly perceive.
So what the problem fundamentally is,
is that there's a lot more of everything else
than there is of you, especially if you include in that
everything else, all the parts of you
that you also don't understand.
And so I want to walk you through how I think we solve that,
at least in part,
and we do that essentially by simplifying the world,
but I think mostly that we simplify it as a place in which to act rather than a place in which to perceive objects.
And I really believe that there's a critical distinction between those two things.
And I think that part of the reason that there's been a
continual tension, say, between the claims of science,
and let's say the claims of religion, is because the idea
that the world has a place of objects and as a place to act
have to be considered separately isn't properly understood.
I don't know.
So I'm going to try to straighten that up to the degree
that that's possible.
So I'm going to talk to you about stories and meta stories.
And the story is this, I would say,
it's the simplest unit of useful information
with regards to action and perception
that you can be offered.
And then a meta story is a story about how a story like that transforms.
And I would say we'll concentrate on the structure of the story,
and then we'll get into the structure of the meta-story,
and that'll constitute today's class.
So the first thing I want to show you, I know many of you have seen this, but I'm going to show it anyways.
For the longest time, it was presumed that
the longest time, say at least in the 20th century, it was presumed that
we make a pretty complete model of the world. And then we act
in the world and we compare what happens to that model. And as long as our model and the world
are matching, then roughly speaking, we believe that everything is okay and our emotions
speaking, we believe that everything is okay and our emotions stay under control. But if that model mismatches, then we know that something's up. Now, a lot of this work was done by Russians,
especially in the early 60s, by two Russian scientists, Vinogodov and Sokolov, who were students of Alexander Luria,
who was arguably the greatest neuropsychologist
of the 20th century.
Luria spent a lot of time studying soldiers from World War II
that had received head injuries and various sorts.
And because of that, he could draw inferences
about how the brain worked and some of what we're going to talk
about over the upcoming weeks with regards to brain function.
Much of it is predicated on Luria's work,
and Sokolov and Vinigredova were his students,
and they were interested in this phenomena.
They were interested in psychophysiological measurement, right?
So as a way of inferring brain function,
and so psychophysiological measurement is measurement
of those physiological parameters, say like pupil width or skin conductance or EEG, that
are in some ways directly reflective of how the brain works. Now if you measure
skin resistance, skin resistance changes with the amount that you sweat and
that can change very, very rapidly.
And it changes in response to physiological demands placed
on your body.
So for example, if your body assumes that you're going to leap
into action for some purpose, then it's going to open up
your pores to prepare you to keep yourself cool.
And you can measure those transformations quite accurately
by measuring the electrical resistance of the skin.
And so what you see, if you put someone in a lab chair,
and you expose themselves to different stimuli, you find that, for example,
if you expose them to something that's threatening, say like a picture of a snake,
then their skin conductance will decrease because their...
Sorry, their skin conductance will increase because their skin conductance will increase because
they sweat a little bit more and it's quite a rapid response.
It can be a very rapid response.
Now one of the things that Sokolov or...
Yeah, that's right.
Noted was that if he...
If I sat you down, for example, and I put some headphones on you and I played a tone to you that repeated,
just exactly the same tone that repeated at predictable intervals, that the first time you heard the tone you'd produce quite a spike in skin conductance,
and the next time a slightly smaller spike, and then the next time a slightly smaller spike until after maybe you'd heard it three or four times, you would not respond to it at all.
And that was often regarded as habituation. Habituation is the same thing that you can see in snails, for example.
And I'm using snails as an example because they have very, very simple nervous systems.
So if you take a snail and you poke it, then like it comes out of a shell and you poke it, it'll go back into a shell, and then it'll come out.
And then if you poke it again, it'll go back into a shell, and it'll come out.
But if you keep doing that, sooner or later, the snail will just stop going in.
And you might think of that.
It has been conceptualized as the simplest form of learning habituation.
And the behavior is tended to presume that if a human being manifested a response that
could be modeled by a simple organism, then the human being was using a response that
was analogous to that of the simple organism.
And sometimes that's true.
And sometimes it's not.
So for example, you have simple reflexes that, you know, if you put your hand on a hot
stove, you'll jerk back.
And that's quite a simple circuit.
You move your hand back before the message gets to your brain because this spinal cord
is smart enough to mediate reflex like that all by itself.
So your brain is actually quite distributed throughout your body.
It's not just in your head, like people tend to think.
And so we have conserved fast acting reflexes at various levels of our nervous system.
They aren't capable of sophisticated response.
It's pretty much stimulus response, thinking about it from the behavioral perspective,
but they have as an advantage, incredible speed, because there just aren't that many neural connections
between the stimulus and the response. And so we have layers of response at different time frames
that help us match with the demands of the external environment.
So Charles Darwin, for example, used to go into the,
I think it was museum in England.
I don't remember the name of it.
They had a snake in there.
I believe it was a cobra.
And he'd stick his face up at the glass
and the cobra would strike at him and he'd jerk back.
And he tried many, many times to master that reflexive response to the snake, but there
was no way.
Every time that thing struck at him, he'd jump backwards.
Well, you can imagine the survival utility in a reflex like that, but in reflexes in
general.
Okay, so back to Sokolov.
Now, what he decided thought, if you took that tone
and you did anything to it, that was perceptible,
because there are certain gradations of tone
that you're not capable of perceiving.
But let's assume you took the tone and you adjusted it enough
so that it was perceptibly louder,
or it was perceptibly a different frequency
or something like that.
Or even that the spaces between the tones,
because I said they were predictably spaced,
even if the spaces between the tones were changed,
then when the change occurred,
the orienting reflex would be reinstated.
You'd respond to it again.
And Sokolov tried to vary the tone on many, many parameters.
But no matter what parameter he varied it on, as long as
you could detect it perceptibly, you'd produce an orienting reflex. So Sokolov's idea
was that you must be producing a complex internal model of the world that's in concordance
with the world across pretty much every perceptible dimension. Because if you weren't doing that,
how in the world would you know that the tone had changed from what you had already learned about it?
And so for the longest time, and this was also true for people who were investigating artificial
intelligence, we had this idea that what people did was make a complex model of the world
and hold it in their mind, so to speak, and then they'd act in the world, and they'd compare
what they expected to happen in the world with the model.
And as long as there was a match, then there was no orienting reflex.
Now, the orienting reflex turns out to be quite a complex reflex.
It's not merely an alteration in skin conductance, what it is in essence is
the manner in which you start to unfold your response to the unknown and the initial stages of that are very, very
quick, but it's hard to tell when the orienting reflex stops and when more complex learning
begins, they sort of shade into one another.
So the initial stages of the orienting reflex are quite reflexive, but the later stages
can be extraordinarily complex.
So for example, well, I always think the example of betrayal is the best one because it's so complex.
So imagine that you come home and you find evidence lipstick or something like that.
Evidence that the person that you're with is betraying you.
The first thing that's going to happen is that you're going to orient.
There's going to be a real shock and that's reflexive.
It's very much akin to the response that you're going to, that you would manifest if be a real shock, and that's a reflexive. It's very much akin to the response
that you're going to, that you would manifest
if you saw a predator or snake or something like that.
And so that's very instantaneous, you know?
And then that'll prepare you for action.
You'll get, you'll get ready to do whatever it is
that you need to do next.
That's a very unpleasant thing.
But then it might take you even years
to fully manifest the
learning that would be necessary in a situation like that because there's
so many things that you have to reconsider. First of all, the person might now
appear to you as a threat. That's pretty immediate. So there's a biological
physiological response first, your body reacts first, then you respond
emotionally. That's going to take a while and that emotional response
might extend over days or weeks or months or even years.
And then as you're doing that as well,
you're going to try to start to resort out
your interpretive schema so that it can adjust
to the transformation that this error on your part say,
or this catastrophe or this betrayal, it has to adjust to whatever
information that event contains.
And so the orienting reflex can manifest itself over an extraordinarily long period of time.
It's best to think about it as the initial part of what can be a very complex learning process.
Now that was a standard idea in
psychology for the longest period of time that we created a detailed internal
model of the world. We watched how the world was unfolding. We compared the two.
And the physiology, the neurophysiology of this was even understood to some
degree, even by the Russians in the early 1960s, because they basically localized,
you could use complex EEG, electro and cephalogram technology, to localize where the orienting
reflex was occurring in the brain, and basically it appeared to occur roughly speaking in the hippocampus,
and the theory arose that your brain, your cortex, let's say, produced a very complex model of the world,
an internal model, and your senses were producing
a model of the external world.
And the hippocampus was watching those two things
to see if they matched.
And if they didn't match, there was a mismatch signal,
and that would be the orienting reflex.
And then your body would start to prepare,
would prepare itself for whatever that mismatch meant,
and then you would engage in exploratory behavior
to try to update your model.
Well, that was the standard theory,
and it was very well accepted theory.
It has elements of cybernetic theory in it,
but it was well accepted enough so that when people
first started to experiment with artificial intelligence,
that's how they tried to make artificially intelligent systems.
They tried to make ones that would model the world and then act and then compare the changes in the world to that model.
But that didn't go anywhere as it turned out because it turned out that it's so difficult to see and model the world that people had no idea how complex that was.
It was impossibly complex as it turned out. And so that's part of the reason
we don't have robots wondering around doing apparently simple things like walking, walking in an
environment like this. Now when we look at the environment we think, well it's not that much,
it's not that hard to look at, it's full of objects and they're just self-evident, there they are,
and we can just wander through it. And we don't even do that consciously to any great degree because so much of that perception
is presented to our consciousness without effort in some sense.
But the AI guys learned pretty quick that perceiving the world was way more difficult than
anybody had guessed.
And then this experiment really, in some sense, put the phenomenological, put a phenomenological
punch behind that observation.
Because one of the presuppositions of the orienting reflex theory that I just laid out
was that you were very good at detecting changes that your nervous system would automatically
detect change, anomaly, right?
Any mismatch between your model and what you expected.
And then, well, the
AI guys, I think, figured out, first of all, that that was a big problem, that the problem
of perception was much more complicated than that. You know, it's actually, it's out of
that same set of observations, in some sense, that postmodernism emerged in literature, because
in literary criticism, because, well, it turns out to be hard enough
to see a normal object like a chair. And part of that is, if you just do that to the chair,
it's really different than it was before. You can imagine how different it would be if
you tried to paint the chair under both those conditions. And if you were really good at
looking at it, you'd find that even though, if I asked you what color this is,
you'd say white, if you were actually painting it,
you'd find out that the colors of the chair,
when it's in that location, and the colors in the chair,
when it's in that location, just because of the difference in lighting,
are substantially different.
I think it was Monet, I think,
who painted a very large series of haystacks in the French countryside,
right, under in different seasons
and under different conditions of illumination,
just because he was exploring how radically different
the same object could be as it moved through contexts.
And so it isn't even obvious why we think this is the same
object when you move it.
And the answer is something like, well, you can sit on it
in both positions, which is not a description of an object, by the way.
Right?
That's a description of something that's useful, something that's a tool, something that
exists in relationship to your body.
It's not an object.
And so, if you think that just looking at something like a chair is almost impossibly difficult
and subject to interpretation, then imagine how difficult it is to perceive something like a text, like a novel, because
a novel obviously is subject to multiple interpretations.
And the interpretations are going to depend on, well, at least in principle, on the intent,
conscious, and unconscious of the author, of the time, of the place, of the culture, of
the language, then that's
just on the side of the production itself, but then there's the reader.
It's like, I've read books when I was 16 and then reread them, say when I was 40, and
the book was almost completely different as far as I was concerned, partly because I knew
what was in it the second time, and I didn't know what was in it the first time. And so the meaning that manifests itself out of a book is a consequence of all the complexity
of the book, plus all the complexity of the reader.
And so, you know, if you're reading Russian literature, for example, and you've already
read 50 Russian novels, you're going to be in a much more different, you're going to be in a different
interpretive space than you are if, say, the Russian novel is the first novel you've ever read.
And so, and the postmodernists were grappling with this as well as with many other ideas that
I think contaminated their thinking, and their conclusion was, well, you can't extract out a canonical meaning from a text.
It's so dependent on the situation
that to say the text has a interpretable meaning
is actually an error.
Now, just because it's difficult to do something
doesn't mean it's impossible.
And there's massive holes in the postmodernist view
as far as I think it's an unbelievably pathological
view personally.
But the thing is, is that there are reasons why it emerged and the reasons were analogous
to the reasons that the AI project initially failed and analogous to the reasons that this
experiment turned out the way it did.
So I'm going to show you this.
Many of you have seen this already, but as I said, it doesn't matter. So the job, your job here is to count the time, see there's
a team of three people here dressed in white, and there's a team of three people here dressed
in black. And your job is to count the number of times the white team throws the basketball
back and forth to the white team members, okay? So we'll just run that. Okay, well, so obviously,
or perhaps not so obviously,
the number of times I believe that they threw it back,
they threw it back and forth with 16,
if I remember this correctly,
but of course that's not really the issue
because what happens in the middle of the scene is that
guy wearing a gorilla suit comes out into the middle of the screen is that guy wearing a gorilla suit comes out
into the middle of the screen and pounds his chest
three or four times.
And he comes out quite slowly as you saw.
How many of you, is there anybody here
who didn't see the gorilla?
No, well, you, and I presume all of you knew
about this video anyways.
So Dan Simon, who produced this video,
has got a couple of other ones where he shows that,
you know, even if you're smart enough to see the gorilla because you've seen the video before you've
heard about it, if you make other changes in the background, you'll count properly and
you'll catch the gorilla, but you'll miss the other changes in the background.
And they're not trivial either.
And it's really quite remarkable.
He's produced other short videos, for example, where you'll be looking at a field and a road will grow in it,
occupying about a third of the photograph space, and you'd think, well, yeah, you're going to see
that. It's like, you don't. You don't. So, okay, so this through a big spanner into the works,
this sort of experiment, along with the AI failures, and we could even say the postmodern dilemmas. Like, well, hmm, everyone virtually, every psychologist would have predicted
before this series of experiments that there's no damn way you'd miss that gorilla.
Because your nervous system was actually attuned to change in the environment
and like, that's a big change and it's also a gorilla.
It's something you would really think that you couldn't miss.
You couldn't possibly miss, especially when it's occupying
the center of the visual field.
And so, well, this is part of a phenomena called
change blindness, and it helped psychologists
who had been studying the visual system for a very long time
figure out, well, mostly figure out exactly how blind
human beings are, because we're way blinder than we think.
And so we actually focus on much less of the world
than we think.
And we do that partly.
It's not exactly obvious how we do it.
It's kind of like we hold a still picture in our imagination
and then fill in the details by using our central foveal
vision, which is always dancing around like a pinpoint
or a laser beam moving back and forth.
And we're assembling those little snapshots
from the fovea into a relatively coherent picture.
Maybe what happens is that I look at you and then I look at you
and I've still got the information from looking at you.
So my brain can sort of infer that that's remain stable. But like if I look at you and I've still got the information from looking at you so my brain can sort of infer that that's remain stable.
But like if I look at you and I pay it, I've tried to learn how to do this because you
could look at something and then pay attention to the periphery.
It's annoying.
But so if I'm looking at you, I really can't make out your eyes.
I can more or less make out the fact that you have a head.
I can see that
you're and I especially if you move it and so that's what your periphery sort of like
frog vision or dinosaur vision. It's much better at picking up movement than it is at picking
up something that's staying still and that makes sense because well if it's staying still
then and it hasn't already hurt you then it's probably not going to hurt you but if it's
moving then you know that's a good thing that you might pay attention to.
And so, if your periphery catches movement, then you'll focus your fovee on it.
It's like you go from really low resolution to really high resolution.
And so, the center of your vision is incredibly high resolution, but then it fades into low
resolution as you move towards the periphery until it's out here, which would say be about 170 degrees, I really, if I concentrate on this hand, I can
tell it's a hand mostly when it's moving. I have no idea what color it is. This
one I can't see at all. And then I can probably see my fingers now. And then I
can clearly see them if I look at them with my fovea. And so your vision
is a very, very, very strange thing, and it's focusing on something very specific, and
so you're pointing your eyes at something, very specific, and that's what you seem to
see. And so then that opens up a whole new universe of questions. It's like, how do you
decide what to point your eyes at?
That turns out to be insanely complicated problem. John Verveiki talks about
that all the time as the problem of relevance. But and the issue is, well,
there's many many things in the world. There's an infinite number of things,
let's say, and you're not going to be able to see them. That's for sure, even if
they happen to be changing as it turns out.
And so out of this mess, first of all, how do you pick what to look at?
And second, even if you do pick it, how do you see it?
Because it's so crazily complicated.
So that's the problem that we're going to try to unpack.
Now, roughly speaking, what seems to have happened with the Gorilla video is
you have to take that first theory that you make a complete model of the world and then a complete model of the world, which is
the objects in the world and how they're interacting.
And you compare that to the objects in the actual world and how they're interacting.
You have to modify that model.
You say, well, no, you're certainly not making a complete model.
And people should have known better anyways, even subjects to the limits of your perceptions.
Because there's all sorts of things in the world that you can't directly perceive. But what you're doing instead is
it's something like you're making a partial model of the world, but you're only making a partial model of the world that you're currently operating on that,
on, on, with some goal in mind, and you're also comparing that to a model of the world as it's currently unfolding.
Because the other thing that was implicit, this is really tricky, this is where you have to watch your implicit assumptions.
The other thing that was implicit in the original cybernetic theory was that you have a model of the world that's complete and then what you're watching is the actual world as
it unfolds and that's not a model. That's just your perception of the objects but that also turns
out to be wrong because your perception of the world as it unfolds is also a model and so what's
happening is you look at the world, the world you see is a model and a very partial model at that and then you compare it to the model that you expect or desire more accurately
Desire, although the initial models were expectation
Because if you're in the lab listening to tones, it's not like you desire anything
But mostly when you're acting in the world you have desires and so the experimental
constraints the experimental constraints skewed the data in some sense by making people assume that
what people were doing when they walked through the world was expecting instead of desiring.
Anyways, you have a model of the world that's generated as you look at it, you have another
model of the world that's something like the world that you desire, then you compare
both of them and they can mismatch and they can mismatch in a way that upsets your current
pursuit.
That's the critical issue. You don't see the anomaly unless it upsets your current pursuit.
And you kind of know that too because when you're like, well, I'm lecturing to you guys,
you know, mostly you're sitting still, but people are moving their arms and they're they're moving their glasses and they're shifting their feet. And generally, I don't see any of that because what difference does it make?
You know, it's not relevant to the ongoing what?
On going contract, the ongoing series of interactions, it's something like that.
So as long as you keep your movements bounded within a range that doesn't interfere with whatever it is that we're
doing, then it's going to be as invisible to me as the gorilla was when you were counting
the balls. And the cool thing is about the gorilla experiment or one of them is that the
reason you were blind to the gorilla was because you were counting the balls. And so that's
so fascinating because what it shows to a huge degree, an unfathomal degree
to an unfathomal degree, is that the value structure that you inhabit determines what you perceive.
It doesn't just determine what you expect or want.
It bloody well determines what you see.
And that makes the world a completely different place.
No one really expected that.
And so if you watch the basketballs,
you see the basketball, you see the basketball.
If you stop watching the basketball,
well then you see the gorilla.
And so the first question that arises
from an experiment like that is,
well, just exactly what is it that you don't see in the world?
And the answer is, all of it.
You see so little, it's unbelievable.
You see that tiny amount that's necessary for you to undertake
the next sequence in your plotted movements, something like that.
But then that becomes very complicated too, because it isn't obvious how you can conceptualize
or how you can determine what your next movement is,
because it's not like you just add up movements and make up your life. It's not that simple,
and it's related to the novel problem, the problem of meaning in a literary work. So you
imagine, you're trying to specify the meaning of a literary work. Well, there's meaning
in the word, but the word is dependent, the meaning of the literary work. Well, there's meaning in the word, and then, but the
word is dependent, the meaning of the word is dependent on the phrase within which it's embedded.
And then the meaning of the phrase is dependent on the sentence that it's embedded in, and the
sentence in the paragraph, and the paragraph in the chapter, and the chapter in the book, and the
book in the corpus of books of that sort, and then within the culture, and then within
whatever your peculiar personal experience is, all of those things nested are operative
to some degree when you're extracting out the meaning at any level of analysis.
They're all operating simultaneously, so you might say, well, what are you doing in this
classroom?
Well the answer is sitting in a chair, but that's obviously that's a very short-term
and context independent answer. But you're also attending to what I'm saying hypothetically,
and you're attending to some of it and not to other parts of it, and you're thinking about
some parts of it and not other parts. And you're also attending a class and the
class is a sequence of lectures and that's embedded within your desire to
finish up the semester and then to finish up the year and then to get your
degree and then you nest that inside whatever it is, whatever the reason is that
you're getting your degree. And then maybe that's nested inside your career
goals and that's nested inside your life goals and that's nested inside your ultimate values which you that's nested inside your life goals, and that's nested inside your ultimate values,
which you may or may not even be aware of.
And so I could say, well, you're sitting here
because it serves your ultimate values.
Well, that's true.
It seems a bit abstract to be useful, right?
It gets so vague out at the out at the outermost levels
that it doesn't really have much specificity, right? So gets so vague out at the out at the outermost levels that it doesn't
really have much specificity, right? So it seems to lack information, but by the same
token, if I said what you're doing is sitting there, it has the same problem of two restricted
meaning because of over specificity. And so there's some level in there that you would
interpret as meaningful, God only knows why, And that's the level, there's a natural level of perception
for that sort of thing.
So for example, when children learn to name an animal,
for example, they'll name cat.
They don't name the species of cat
or the subspecies of cat.
And they don't confuse cats with dogs,
even though they're both in the category
of four-legged furry mammal.
So why not call a cat and a dog a furry mammal?
Well, children don't do that.
They go to cat and dog,
and people who've studied the acquisition of language
have found that there are basic level categories that children pick up first,
and they're often represented with short words.
And the words are short because they've been around a long time
because they seem to reflect the natural level
at which people perceive the world.
But none of that's obvious.
It's by, I mean, you could just lump all that animals together
for that matter and just call them animals, which we do sometimes.
So anyway, so it's very difficult to specify the meaning level
and it's not very easy at all to figure out how we do it.
And so that's partly what I'm trying to unpack.
So here's part of the issue.
So let's say that you have a computer, yeah,
well, I have a story for this.
So one time when I was in Montreal,
I was using my computer as in my apartment.
And I was typing out an essay and it crashed.
And so what happens when your computer crashes?
Well, usually you utter some sort of curse.
And it's interesting that you do that because the circuit
that you use to curse with is the same circuit that monkeys
use to detect eagles or leopards or snakes.
And so when there's a bunch of monkeys together,
they're not all preyed on by eagles and leopards and snakes.
But there's usually a predator in that category
for every single monkey population,
and so when the monkeys are watching, they have an emotional utterance that the most nervous monkey
might utter first that basically says, you know, hide from the eagle, get out on a thin branch,
so the cougar can't eat you, and look the hell out for the snake. But there's a circuit that's linked
to emotions that produces an instinctive utterance that represents that category.
And that's the same circuit that you use when you curse.
And it's not the same circuit that you use for normal language.
And we know that because that circuit is activated in people who have Tourette syndrome,
because they preferentially swear.
You think, well, why in the world would you have a neurological condition that makes you preferentially curse?
Well, that's the reason. You don't just have one linguistic circuit. You have one for, oh my God, there's a predator.
And that's the one that will get activated when something happens like your computer crashing.
Because, you know, you're an evolved creature, and so those old circuits that were there say 30 million years ago to deal with exceptions are the same circuits
you're using now to deal with your computer.
Why else would you want to hit it?
Because that's what you want to give at a whack.
It's like it doesn't behave whack, aggression right away.
Well, that's some clue as to the category system
that you're automatically using to encapsulate the event.
OK, so fine.
What do you do when your computer crashes?
Well, first you curse, and then you
do the stupid things that idiot primates do
when they're trying to deal with something that's way too complex.
And maybe you turn it on and off, right?
And that doesn't work.
It didn't work.
And so then I thought, well, maybe the power bar went.
So I checked the power bar. I turned it on and off, and nothing happened. So I brought a light behind
the computer, the light wouldn't go on. And so I thought, aha, I must have blown a fuse.
So I went to the fuse box and took a look, but the fuses were fine. And so I thought, oh,
the power's gone out. So then I went outside, and the power was out. None of the street lights
were working. The power was out everywhere.
And it was seriously out because this was the time that
almost the entire Northeast power grid in Quebec collapsed.
And the reason it collapsed is because there was a solar flare
that happens reasonably often.
And the solar flare produced a huge electromagnetic pulse
because it's basically like a million hydrogen bombs
going off at the same time, 93 million miles away, produces this tremendous electromagnetic
pulse, passes through the earth's atmosphere, produces a spike in current in the main power
lines and blows the whole system.
And so just so you know, an event like that happens about every 150 years,
and if we had one now it would take out all of our electronics, like one of the big ones. There's
a big one back in the late 1800s. Everything. Satellites, computers, cars, everything. Go on.
And so that's a big problem, and no one knows what to do about it. One missed us by about nine
minutes, I think, two years ago. So that's something else to worry about if you're inclined to worry about
those sorts of things. Okay, so what did I conclude from that? Well, the function of my
computer was dependent on the stability of the sun. It's not the first thing you check
out when your computer crashes, right? You don't run out and go, hey, well, yeah, the sun's still there. No problem. I can cross that
off the list. But to me, it's an extraordinarily interesting example of the invisible interdependence
of things, you know, and our tendency to fragment the... What we seem to do is to look at things
at the simplest level of analysis that actually functions.
So, for example, when you're interacting with your computer, you're not interacting with your computer at all, really.
You're interacting with the keyboard, sort of one key at a time, and you're interacting with the symbols on the screen.
But as long as the computer is working, you don't care about it at all.
You don't give about it at all.
You don't give it a second thought.
And you certainly don't care about the fact that it's dependent on,
well, the electrical power, for example,
and the electrical power is dependent on, you know,
I don't know, how many men are out there right now
or were out there last night when it was freezing rain,
fixing power lines and freezing to death
while they're doing it so that your stupid computer doesn't malfunction while you're
watching cat videos.
I mean, there's this incredibly dynamic living system that's social and economic and political
that has to remain dead stable in order for us to have access to functional and like
pure non-fluxuating
electricity, 100% of the time.
Because you also don't think, well, the stability of your
computer is dependent on the stability of the political
system, but of course it is.
Because if the political system mucks up and the
economic system goes, then people don't go out and work to
fix things and things are breaking all the time, that's
their normal state is broken, not working.
And so, and that's all in some sense, folded up, not only inside your computer, but actually
inside your conceptions of the, your tiny conceptions of the computer while you're using
it. And you only get a glimpse of what the computer is really like when it doesn't work.
Then it's when it becomes a complex object, right?
As long as it's working, then your stupid perceptions are perfectly fine to get the job
done.
And that's another indication that what you're using your perceptions for is to get the
job done.
And how you specify exactly the level of resolution
that you should be operating at, I haven't sorted that out,
but it's something like you default to the simplest level
that moves you to the next step.
So for example, and generally that is what you should do,
if you're having an argument with someone
that you have a long-term relationship with,
you can start by arguing about what the little argument is
about, or you can immediately cascade into whether or not you should have a relationship with this
person at all, or even into whether or not you should even bother with relationships.
Which is, you know, every time there's an argument, that question is a reasonable question
to have emerge, or at least it's in the realm of potential reasonable questions, but it doesn't seem useful to jump to the most catastrophic possible explanation
every time some minor thing goes wrong.
That's what happens to people who have an anxiety disorder.
And that's what happens to people who are depressed, right?
They can't bind the anomaly.
And so what happens is it tends to propagate up the entire system until it takes out their
highest order conceptualizations.
So if you're seriously depressed, maybe you'll watch a news article about something stupid and you'll think,
Jesus, why should I even be alive?
And I'm dead serious about that.
If you score like 60 on the Beck Depression inventory, which puts you way the hell up in the depressed rage,
anything that happens to you that's negative will trigger suicidal
thoughts, roughly speaking, and sometimes even positive things will do it, because there
are very few positive things that happen that don't carry with them some threat of change
or transformation.
So you know, one mystery, it's a big mystery, is why don't you fall into a catastrophic
depression every time something little goes
wrong? Because it's not that level of analysis is not self-evident. And you see this with
people who are high in neuroticism too, you know. Their trivial fluctuations at their
workplace or in their relationships or in their health will produce a disproportionate
negative emotional response, but it's part of the range of normal emotional responses. Some people are very, very high in neuroticism, so everything upsets them. Some people are very low.
And the reason that whole range exists is because sometimes you should get upset when some little
thing happens to you, because it's an indication that the whole damn environment has got dangerous on you. And sometimes you should just brush it off,
because its net consequence is low.
But how do you calculate that?
Very, very difficult question.
So when your computer goes wrong, well,
you have to pick the proper level of analysis to fix it.
And you could say, well, there's something wrong with the circuit board, and maybe there's a crack
in one of the somewhere that it's soldered.
Or sometimes now when people are building microchips,
they've run into a crazy problem.
Microchips keep getting smaller and smaller and smaller, right?
And so the little wires now are down to atomic width,
or you know, the width of maybe 20 atoms or something like that,
but really, really, they're really getting thin.
And so that produces another problem, which no one would have ever,
no, no, you wouldn't expect.
And that is, you know, that at the quantum level there's uncertainty
about where electrons might be.
Normally that doesn't matter.
The degree of uncertainty about where your electrons are is small enough at your size
so that it's basically irrelevant.
But down at the subatomic level where these microchips are starting to be produced, sometimes
the electrons will be outside the wires and that means that they're getting so damn small that they'll short-circuit by themselves, because the electrons
aren't stable enough to be where they're supposed to be in the wires.
So, well, the reason I'm pointing that out is because a problem that exists in a system
can exist at any of the multiple levels of that system, and it isn't obvious where to
start, and a lot of political arguments are like that.
It's like, well, maybe a company goes bankrupt
and its shareholders get maybe a bank fails
and so people can't withdraw their money
and one response is, well, that just shows you
how rotten the capitalist system is.
It's like, well, maybe that is what it shows.
But it seems like that might not be the most
appropriate level to start.
And so again, it's like Occam's razor in the scientific world, right?
You want to use the simplest explanation that it's not that fits the facts because you
don't organize your perceptions by facts.
It's kind of like you want to use the simplest tool. You can possibly manage to fix the problem.
So you don't, when your car has a flat tire,
you don't buy a new car.
You fix the flat tire if you can figure out how to do it.
And so you go for the thing that will put the tool back
together with the minimum involvement of time and effort.
It's something like that.
And you care about that because you have limited time
and you have limited resources.
And so it makes sense for you to conserve them.
And I'm telling you that partly for practical reasons, too,
because this is a very useful thing to know
if you're arguing with someone.
You want to argue about the smallest possible thing
that you could argue about that might fix the problem. You want to really specify it. It's like what's going
on at a micro level and what's the minimum that I would require to be satisfied with the
outcome. And if you're, this is especially true in intimate relationships, it's like
if someone's bugging you and you want them to change, you think, well, how can I be minimally bothered by this?
And what's the tiniest amount of change I could request that might satisfy me?
Because otherwise, the argument will come unglued, and every time you guys try to discuss
a problem, you'll start talking about whether you should even be together, and then you're
done, because you'll never solve a problem.
And then you won't be together, because you'll never solve a problem and then you won't be together because you never solve a problem. So, okay. So, here's a way to think about
perception. So, let's say that this is the thing you're trying to look at. I called
that the thing in itself. Now, that's a schematic of a thing in itself. So, the
thing in itself, that's an old philosophical concept.
And I think it came from Kant, but I'm not sure about that.
It might be older than that.
And the thing in itself is what you could see if you could see everything about something,
but you can't.
So it's a hypothetical entity.
And maybe who knows if I was looking at you like the thing in itself, maybe I could see every level of your being
from the subatomic up to this level of perception.
And then beyond, I could see your family relationships.
I could see how they were nested
in your societal relationships, economic relationships,
political relationships, the ecosystem as a whole.
Like I would see all these levels at the same time.
Of course, I don't, because I can't.
What I see instead is, first of all,
you're radically simplified by my senses,
because they're just not acute enough
to say, see you at a microscopic level.
And they're not comprehensive enough
to see your connections across time.
So my sense is filter a bunch of you from me right away.
And then I'm also filtered from you by my, by your willingness
to act like I want well-worked together, because you could be doing all sorts of strange things at
the moment, but you're not. And so you're helping me simplify my perceptions of you by agreeing to
play the same game that I'm playing while we occupy the same space. And that's basically politeness.
That's the mark of someone who's well-socialized.
You walk in somewhere, you get the game, you play the game, and you don't scare the hell
out of everybody.
And that's partly how we keep our emotions stabilized, because if you're like a Freudian,
you think, well, as long as your ego is well constituted,
you can keep your emotions under control.
It's like, yes and no, mostly no.
I like the Piagetian idea better, which is,
if you're well socialized, you're awake enough
to identify the game that's going on wherever you go.
And then you play that game immediately,
and so do all the other socialized primates. And so
then you can just understand the game. You don't have to understand them. Thank God. You can just
understand the game. And as long as the game continues, you don't have to be nervous because you know
you at least know what's going to happen. And maybe you even know how to get what you want in that
game. And so, so that again, that's really worth thinking about
because we talked about this before
about why people want to maintain their culture.
It isn't just because their culture is a belief system
that helps them orient themselves in the world.
It's because a belief system is a game
that everyone who shares that belief system is playing
and the fact that everybody's playing means nobody needs to get upset. So it isn't like that belief system is playing and the fact that everybody's playing
means nobody needs to get upset.
So it isn't like the belief system
is directly inhibiting the emotions.
That isn't how it works.
So, and it's not like the culture is just a belief system.
It's only secondarily a belief system, man.
Mostly it's a game that people are actively engaging in.
That's way more important than the beliefs
that go along with it.
You don't even need the damn beliefs.
That's why wolves can live with each other.
They don't know what the,
they don't have a belief system exactly.
Mostly they have a set of,
they have a game.
It's the wolf game, roughly speaking,
and all the wolves know how to play it.
And so that's that. That's how they keep themselves organized in their packs. A lot of it's externalized.
And so, okay, so anyways, so the thing in itself, that's a very complicated thing. It's got multiple
dimensions, multiple levels. And then it's worse than that because it doesn't only have multiple levels,
but all of those levels move across time,
and every one of those levels shifts as it moves across time.
And so I like to think of the thing in itself like a symphony.
I think that's a good moral.
I think that's why we like music, in fact,
because music shows you a multi-level reality
that unfolds and shifts across time
within some parameters, right?
Because it's not just chaos.
The music has an element of predictability and an element of unpredictability, and it
has these multiple levels, and that's sort of what everything in the world is like.
It's what the world is like.
So this is a, even that is just a conceptual model of the thing in itself.
First of all, that's only got two dimensions instead of three,
because it could be a cube.
And then it has, even a cube has three dimensions
instead of four, because if that was a cube
adding the third dimension,
then it would also be a cube that would transform and shift
as it moved across time.
And that's what the thing in itself is.
But that's too damn complicated.
So then the question is, when you look at it,
what you see and the answer is, to some degree,
it depends on what you want to use it for.
And so I would say, well, here, look at the different ways
you can look at this.
You might say, what is this?
And somebody could say, well, it's a rectangle.
And would you say, that's correct?
It's like, well, it's a rectangle. And would you say, that's correct? It's like, well, it's not correct, because there's not
a one-to-one correspondence.
But it might be a useful conceptualization.
If you think about that as a box, it could contain that.
And if you were carrying the box, you'd only
have to be concerned about the box.
And so that would be fine.
That's a good functional simplification.
That one's a little higher resolution because it says, well, yeah, it's actually four rectangles
and that one says, well, wait, think about that as an orchard that someone's looking at
from the top.
You want to figure out how to walk from south to north.
Well, you got a little map there because you can think of those as bars instead of collections
of dots.
PGA showed that children will automatically do this.
So for example, if you take six dots and put them in a row
and you take the same six dots and you stretch them out
so the rows this much longer.
And then you ask the child where there are more dots,
the child will say that there are more dots
where it's longer.
Because they're flipping in some sense between the perception of the individual dots and
the perception of the shape that the array of dots makes.
And so the shape is longer, because you can see it as a rectangle.
And so they think, well, longer is bigger, bigger is more.
There's got to be more dots.
So, well, and then there's this one, which is sort of an amalgam of this one and this one,
and then that one, there's that one, and that's the highest resolution model of that that's still
a simplification. And, you know, what I like about this diagram is that, you know, people say,
well, the facts are the facts, and what we're disagreeing about is our opinion about the facts.
It's like, no, yes, you have an opinion about the facts,
but the world is so horribly complex that you can actually
disagree about the facts themselves.
And I think an ideology does that to people very, very
commonly. So I saw this movie once that Naomi Klein made.
If I tell you the same story, tell me, okay, because I don't want to tell you the same story, but I might.
So, she went down to Argentina after a bunch of money had
got out of Argentina because of her financial collapse,
and she went to a factory that had been padlocked,
and it was a heavy machinery factory.
And the workers that decided they were going to undo the
padlocks and go build machines, you know,
tell with the owner who shut it down. And so she went down and made this movie and
followed these workers around and you know showed how catastrophic their lives had been because they'd lost their livelihood in this big financial crash.
And so that was really interesting, but then she went and interviewed the guy who owned the factory and she treated him like he was
like a cipher in some sense. Instead of asking him how he got the factory, what he wanted
to do with it, how it fit in with his life plans, why he why he shut it down
instead of continuing it, you know, he she didn't get the backstory on him.
She just left him in the evil capitalist box and went on with the film and it
was like it wasn't like what she did, wasn't true.
But it was only half true, and it was half true,
because she could perceive the complexity of the workers,
having sympathy for them.
But as far as she was concerned, the enemy,
the owner had no complexity.
He was just bad capitalist.
And that's how it was left in the movie.
I found it profoundly unsatisfying
because I wanted to know, okay, it's like you know that these workers are suffering. It's
not self-evident that you want your damn factory closed. You'd think you'd want it open so
you could be building things. It's like, who are you? What are you doing? Why is this just
ifiable? Have a question about it. Well, you can take this infinite set of facts and then you subject it to your filters
and you let some of the facts through and their facts. But what about all the facts that you don't
let through? That's the thing and that's what the Gorilla video shows too. It's like yeah, yeah,
you got the basketball count right, but you missed the big primate and you might say, well, your
priorities were a bit skewed in that circumstance because you were rearranging the deck chairs as the the basketball count right, but you missed the big primate. And you might say, well your priorities
were a bit skewed in that circumstance because you were rearranging the deck chairs as the Titanic
sank, you know, as the old Joe goes. And so it's very much useful to think always, well you're,
it isn't just your damn opinion that's biased, although it is. It's your perceptions that are biased.
although it is, it's your perceptions that are biased. So, well, and with your words, it's even more, so you say, well, you can't see the thing in itself,
because it's too complex, so you perceive it simpler than it is.
And some of that perceptual simplification is dependent on your aims.
So that's a vicious one because it pulls the the value
structure that you're in sconce within into your perceptions it pulls it into
the realm of facts itself. And then you do another I think about this as a
compression. You know you can compress a photograph by getting rid of redundant
information. That's sort of what you're doing here.
It's your, like, one of these squares, little black squares here,
black rectangles, compresses all of those.
It's like we're going to treat those as if they're grayish black.
Same thing happens here.
So we're blurring across them.
So we have a much less high resolution image here.
So you take the thing in itself, So we have a much less high resolution image here.
So you take the thing in itself,
you perceive it as a low resolution representation.
And then you take that low resolution representation,
and you replace that with a word.
And so the word is a twofold compression.
And then when someone tosses you the word,
you unpack it into the low resolution perception, and then
maybe into the world itself if you can do that, but probably not.
So that's what we're doing.
We're taking the complex world.
We fold it into a simple perception.
We fold that into a word.
We throw the word to someone else and they unpack it.
And the only way you can unpack it, of course, is if you've had enough similar experience
so that you have the reference for the word already in your experience. So, which is why you have to use simplified language with children, right?
Because there's no point tossing a child a concept that he or she can't unpack. So, we
compress a very complex reality through a very, very small keyhole. That's basically our cognitive processing.
OK, so then here's the next kind of argument.
This goes along with the science-religion argument
that I was making earlier, which I want to unpack a little bit
more.
I think that fundamentalists and atheistic scientists have the same problem.
The fundamentalists, so we could say the Christian fundamentalists in the U.S., make the proposition
that biblical stories, we'll call them mythological stories, are literal representations of the
truth. But that might be true depending on what you mean by literal.
But what they mean by literal or what they attempt to make literal mean is that they're in the same category as scientific facts.
Because they don't have the idea that there are different ways of approaching truth
and that truth can serve different purposes.
They don't have a sense that your definition of truth is actually something like a tool,
rather than an ontological statement about the reality of the world.
And so the fundamentalists basically make the proposition that the idea that God created
the world in six days, 5,000 years ago, is literally true.
And they get the 5,000 year estimate, by the way,
by going through the genealogies and the Old Testament
and adding up the hypothetical ages
and figuring out how long before Moses, Adam lived.
And some bishop did that back.
And I think it was in the mid-1800s.
I might be wrong about that, but it was somewhere back
about that time.
And more or less, that's been accepted as canonical fact ever since.
And then the scientists say, well, yeah, those are empirical truths.
They're just wrong.
See, and that's the only difference there is between the fundamentalists and the atheist
scientists.
The fundamentalists say, those are fundamental scientific truths, and they're right.
And the scientists say, well, they're scientific truths.
They just happen to be wrong.
Well, I think
that's a stupid argument, personally. I mean, for a bunch of reasons, one is that the
people who wrote the ancient stories that we have access to were in no way, shape, or
form scientists. You know, modern people tend to think that you think like a scientist,
and people have always thought that way. First of all, you do not think like a scientist.
Even scientists hardly even think like scientists, but if you're not scientifically trained,
you don't think like a scientist at all.
So one of the things, for example, that characterizes your thinking is confirmation bias.
And so if you have a theory, what you do is wander around in the world looking for reasons
why it's true.
And a scientist does exactly the opposite of that,
in the little tiny narrow domain where he or she is actually capable of being a scientist.
And what they have is a theory and look for a way to prove it wrong,
but believe me, you don't run around doing that.
I mean, you can train yourself, so now and then you can do that.
You know, you can learn to listen to people, for example,
on the off chance that you might be wrong. But that is by no means a natural way of thinking. And of course,
the fundamental philosophical axioms of the scientific method weren't developed until
Descartes and Bacon and who else Descartes made. And there's one more. Anyway, the name escapes me at the moment.
But you can argue about when science emerged.
But it's certainly emerged in its articulated form
within the last 1,000 years.
I think you could say even more specifically
that it emerged in the last 500 years.
Now, you might argue with that and say, well,
what about the Greeks and other people
who were fairly technologically sophisticated or who invented geometry or that kind of thing, but yeah, yeah,
bear precursors to the idea of empirical observation. Aristotle, for example, when he was writing down his knowledge of the world, it never occurred to him to actually go out in the world and look at it to see if what he assumed about it was true. And it certainly never occurred to Aristotle to get 20 people
to go look at the same thing independently,
write down exactly how they went about doing it,
compare the records, and then extract out what was common.
And that seems self-evident to us to some degree,
but it was by no means self-evident to anyone 500 years ago, and people still don't do it.
So it's not even, it's not plausible if you know anything about the history of ideas. It's not
plausible to posit that stories about the nature of reality that existed before 500 years ago.
We're scientific in any but the most cursory of ways.
So why we have that argument continually is somewhat beyond me.
Part of the reason is though that everyone, fundamentalists, included, really believe
in scientific facts, even though they hate it.
They'll use computers, they'll fly.
Computers won't work, wouldn't work, unless quantum mechanics were correct.
The fact that you use a high-tech device indicates through your action that you actually accept
the theories upon which it's predicated, the same as flying, the same as anything you do
in a complex technological society.
You're stuck with it, you're reading by the lights.
Do they work?
Yeah, they work.
Well, so it's really hard
for people who are trying to hold on to a way of looking at the world that appears to contradict
the scientific claims when everything they do is predicated on their acceptance of the validity
of the scientific claims. It's really problematic for people and it's problematic in a real way, I think,
because one of the problems with the scientific
viewpoint is it doesn't tell you anything about what you should do with your life.
It doesn't solve the problem of value at all.
In fact, it might make it more difficult, because one of the fundamental scientific claims,
roughly speaking, is that every fact is of equal utility, at least from a scientific
perspective.
There's no hierarchy of facts.
It's not exactly true because you can think of one theory
as more true than another.
But that boils down to saying that it's more useful than another.
So I don't think that that's a really good exception.
OK, so fine.
You got the scientific atheists on one end
and you got the religious fundamentalists on the other,
and what they both agree on, whether they like it or not,
is that there's so much power in the scientific method
that it's difficult to dispute the validity of scientific facts.
And they seem to exist in contradiction
to the older archaic stories if you also accept them
as fast fact-based accounts.
So what do we do about that? Well, if you're on the scientific atheist end of things,
you say, well, those old stories are just superstitious science, second-rate,
barbaric, archaic, forms of science, you just dispense with them, they're nothing but trouble.
And if you're on the fundamentalist side, you say, well, we'll try to shoehorn science
into this framework, and really that doesn't. And really, that doesn't work very well.
It doesn't work very well with the claims of evolution.
For example, in fact, it works very badly.
And that's a problem because evolutionary theory
is like, it's a killer theory.
And it's really, it's really, really hard.
And like, it's not a complete theory.
And there's lots of things we don't know about evolution.
But you know, trying to hand wave that away,
that's not going to work without dispensing
with most of biology.
So that's a big problem.
So here's another way of thinking about it.
You don't just need one way of looking at the world.
Maybe you need two ways of looking at the world, and I'm not exactly sure how they should be related to one another,
like which should take precedence under which circumstance.
But one problem is, what's the world made of?
You know, what's the world conceptualized as an objective place made of?
And the other is, how should you conduct yourself while you're alive?
And there's no reason to assume that those questions can be answered using the same approach.
I mean, physics has its methods and chemistry has its methods and biology has its methods.
So, a method for obtaining the truth
can be bound to a domain.
So why would we necessarily assume
that you could use the same set of tools
to represent the world as a place of objects
and to represent it as a place
in which a biological creature would act?
I mean, anyways, I'm suggesting that we
that we don't view it that way.
That we have two different viewpoints.
Maybe they can be brought together, although it's not obvious how,
but that it's not a tenable solution to get rid of one in favor of the other.
And I think the reason for that is that you need to know how to conduct yourself in the world.
You have to have a value system.
You can't even look at the damn world without a value system.
It's not possible.
Your emotional health is dependent on a value system.
The way you interact with other people is dependent on a value system.
There's no get away from it.
And you say, well, there's no justification for any value system from a scientific perspective.
You're going to draw that conclusion that no value system is valid, where the hell does that leave you?
There's no down, there's no up, there's no rationale for moving in any direction,
there's not even really any rationale for living.
And so people say things like that, well, why the hell should I care what happens in a million years,
who's going to know the difference? It's like, yeah, yeah.
True, stupid, but true.
And the reason I think it's stupid is because it's just a game.
I can take anything of any sort and find a context in which it's irrelevant.
It's just a rational game.
It's like, who cares if a hundred children freeze to death in a blizzard?
Who, what difference is going to make a billion years?
Well, what do you say to someone who says that?
You say, well, seems like the wrong frame of reference,
buckle, that's what it looks like to me, you know?
Because at some point, you question the damn frame
of reference, not what you derive from it.
And it certainly seems to me that situations like that
don't allow you to use that kind of frame of reference.
There's something inhumane about it and that trumps the logic or at least it
should. And if it doesn't then all hell breaks loose and that doesn't seem to be a
good thing. Okay so I have this quote from Shakespeare here. He says all the
world's a stage and all the men and women merely players. They have their exits
and their entrances and one man in his time plays many parts.
Well, it's the sort of thing that you'd expect a dramatist to pant, but that's how he looked at the world.
And we still watch Shakespeare's plays some hundreds of years later, because there seems to be something essential captured in them.
Something about how people do act, but more importantly, I think, how people should and shouldn't act. Because
what fun is it going to a play that doesn't outline how someone should and how someone
shouldn't act? You want a good guy or a couple of them? Maybe they can be complex intermingling
of good and bad. You know, that makes it more sophisticated. And you want a bad guy
or a bad, you know, you always want to see that contrasted,
either within a character or between characters.
And it's because you want to know how to live properly.
That's how to be a good person.
And you want to know how to live improperly.
How to be a bad person.
So you can watch out for people like that
or so you can figure out what that means for yourself.
It's compelling.
And that's another thing that's worth thinking about.
Why is it compelling?
And it's compelling to everyone.
That's the thing that's so cool is that there aren't that many phenomena that you can point to that are compelling to everyone.
Music is close.
It's a very rare person who doesn't like at least some genre of music, no matter how narrow.
But the other one is stories. very rare person who doesn't like at least some genre of music, no matter how narrow.
But the other one is stories.
You're hard pressed to find someone, especially if they're younger, who doesn't like stories.
Why?
Is it waste of time?
Or is there something going on?
Well, I think it's not only not a waste of time, it's actually the most fundamentally
important thing you can possibly do, because there's no difference between understanding stories
and figuring out how to get along in the world.
So, and there's a tight relationship between the story that you inhabit that structures
your behavior and the games that Piaget talked about that organize people's behavior, you
know, to some degree the reason that we can all sit in this room together,
like this, is because a huge chunk of the value system that guides our behavior is shared.
So I am lecturing and you're sitting in the classroom and that distinguishes us to some degree,
but you know that that's partly merely a consequence of the difference in our age.
It's the same trajectory.
We just happen to occupy different positions in a value hierarchy that we both accept.
And so, as long as you feel that that's fair and just, then you're not going to object to it.
But I'm here in the classroom for many of the same reasons that you're here in the classroom.
If you look at the higher order parts of the value structure, and maybe right out at the end of that, because I've tried to figure out, if you push why you're doing
what you're doing right now, to its ultimate limit, so you can't get a story that's super
ordained to that, it's something like, well, you believe that the investigation of the
world to acquire knowledge is worthwhile, otherwise what the hell are you here for? And even if 80% of your motivation is to get a good stable job,
fair enough, there's still something outside of that.
Because the whole culture says, well, you're more likely
to be able to function properly in a good stable job
if you're this sort of person who knows how to go out
in the world and forage for information usefully.
And I think that's very much analogous to the hero's story.
It's like you go out and you search the unknown to find something of value.
And so fundamentally, that's what we're doing in the classroom.
And the reason we can all organize our behaviors is because we accept that framework consciously
would be, we know how to articulate it.
Unconsciously, it's, well, it doesn't matter.
We know how to act out the patterns. Whether we know that, can, it's, well, it doesn't matter. We know how to act out the patterns.
Whether we know that, can say the rules or not,
it doesn't matter.
Same as a wolf back.
We know the dam.
We know the procedures.
And you could describe them with an articulated value
structure.
Let's take a break.
Okay, so let's go back to the complexity problem.
See, I actually think it's the, in some sense, it's the fundamental problem.
When you read about the terror management theorist types,
and they think that death is the fundamental problem.
And that's a good argument because it's definitely a fundamental problem,
but I think it's a subset of the complexity problem.
And the reason I think that is because sometimes people's lives become so complex that they'd rather be dead.
So, and the reason they seek death through suicide is to make the complexity go away,
because complexity causes suffering if it's uncontrolled. You know, things just get beyond your control.
complexity causes suffering if it's uncontrolled. Things just get beyond your control.
And that can happen.
If you're hit by three or four catastrophes at the same time,
maybe you have, oh, the political system collapses.
There's hyperinflation.
You lose your job, and you have someone
that you love or two people die.
And maybe you get cancer, something like that.
Those things happen to people, and they just think, well, there's no getting out of this.
Like, it's just too much.
And you know, one of the things that's very interesting
about being a psychologist is that what you learn
if you're gonna be a psychologist is that people come
to you with mental illnesses and that's almost never true.
People come to you because their lives are so damn complicated,
they cannot stay on top of them.
In any way, it doesn't make it look like they're just going to get more complicated.
And so then that causes symptoms.
It's like, is this old idea sort of a metaphor for genetic susceptibility?
Take a balloon and blow it up until it's beyond its tolerance.
It's going to blow out at the weakest point.
Well, that's sort of what a genetic susceptibility is.
If I just keep adding complexity on top of you, at some point you'll blow out at your
weakest point. You know, maybe you'll get physiologically ill, maybe you'll start drinking,
maybe you'll develop an anxiety disorder, maybe you'll get OCD, maybe you'll get depressed,
whatever. There'll be something about you that's the weakest point. And if I just push,
that's where you'll blow out. So that's a mental illness, but those things almost never just happen.
Sometimes, but not very often.
Usually people have just been hammered like two or three different ways.
And then they collapse in the direction of their biological weakness.
And then maybe you put them back together.
But it's almost always a complexity related phenomena rather than a mental illness related phenomena.
Not always, but almost always. So, okay, so now, you got this complexity problem and you think, well,
you deal with it conceptually. And that's sort of akin to the idea that it's belief systems
that protect you from death anxiety. The ideas are roughly comparable, but again, that's
wrong. It's the sort of thing only a psychologist idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of the idea of old cities, this is a medieval city in France, beautiful old city.
Old cities were walled, and the reason for that was because they were places of wealth
and if you didn't put walls around them,
then other people would come in and steal everything
and kill you, so like having some walls was a good idea.
Like the same as having walls in your house is a good idea.
Walls between your rooms are a good idea,
or borders between categories are a good idea.
And so part of the way you simplify the world
is by building walls or walls around your space
because then a whole bunch of things can't come in.
And so you don't even have to think about them.
It's not conceptual, it's practical.
And so, and you know, one of the things I think I figured out recently is the fundamental
political difference between people. And it looks to me like the fundamental political
differences. How many walls should there be around your stuff? And the ultimate liberal answer
is zero. And the ultimate conservative answer is, well, bring on those walls, man. And what's
interesting about both those perspectives,
first of all, is that there's temperamental contributions
to them in second that they're both valid.
So one of the mysteries, I believe, that permeates
psychometric psychology right now, is why
the temperamental factors that influence politics
are those particular temperamental factors?
So there's five, let's say, right?
This classic big five, extraversion, or autism, agreeableness, conscientiousness, and openness.
Well, the biggest predictors of political allegiance, forget about the politically correct types for a minute,
but on the liberal to conservative axis is that the liberals are low in conscientiousness and high in openness,
and the conservatives are high in conscientiousness and high in openness and the conservatives
are high in conscientiousness and low in openness.
And so then you think, well, why those two traits,
that's first question.
And the second question is, why those two traits together,
given that they're not very highly correlated, right?
They're really quite independent.
So why do they co-very along the political axis?
And I think this is the reason, I think it's exactly that,
is that open people
like to live on the periphery of boundaries
and they like to break boundaries between things because interesting things happen
when you
when you think a different way when you think outside of the box so to speak
that's what open people do they always think outside of the box no matter what box you put them in
you know and sometimes you meet people that are so open that
they're completely disorganized.
Their thought process is almost completely
associational, like a dreamer.
They just jump from one thing to another.
And they're very interesting to talk to.
It's very hard for those people to get their lives together
because they're interested in absolutely everything
and their attention just flits all over the place.
And so they're open, and that actually does go along
with higher intelligence, generally speaking. So, and then if they're low in conscientiousness, they don't see any utility in
order and order like orderly people, because that's part of conscientiousness and the biggest
determiner of political belief in the conscientious domain, the orderly people like to have everything in
its separate place and properly structured. And so, you know, their world is box inside a box,
inside a shelf of boxes, and then that shelf of boxes
is inside another box, and all those boxes are nice
and neat and tight, nothing inside them is touching,
and everything in every box is the same thing.
And, you know, you can see that that,
you can see the utility in that.
And that, as far as we've been able to tell,
is also associated with disgust sensitivity, and disgust we've been able to tell, is also associated with discussed sensitivity
and discussed, people are disgusted, generally speaking, when things that shouldn't be touching are touching,
like something horrible stuck to you, for example.
And that produces a very visceral sense of disgust.
And it's a boundary violation, because that's what disgust is.
It's indexes of boundary violation. And you
can, you, how separate people should be from one another as individuals or in groups
is an entirely debatable issue, because there's huge advantages when people mingle and mix,
and there's huge dangers when people mingle and mix. And so at some point you say, well,
the dangers are overwhelming the positives, and at some point you say, well, the dangers are overwhelming the positives
and at another point you say, well, the positives are overwhelming the dangers. And you have
a continual argument about that with yourself, but more importantly, with people who have
different temperament than you. You know, and the terrible temptation is to assume that
only those people who have your temperament are correct. And that's just those other temperaments
wouldn't exist if that was true. I mean if you look at it from just say if you look at
it from a strictly biological perspective. So anyways one of the things we do to simplify
the world is to frame it physically. And so you look at this you've got wall number
one and then you have wall number two. But then inside the walls you have walls around
everything. All these houses are walls and inside the houses,
there are walls as well.
And so everything is, and what you do
when you put walls around things is you make
part of the world simpler, right?
Constantly, if the reason you have a house is so that
everybody and his dog isn't in your house,
you just want those few people that you can barely
tolerate in your house, and not all those few people that you can barely tolerate in your house
and not all those other strangers
and God only knows what they're gonna do.
You'll still invite people in now and then
because maybe you're sick and tired and bored
of the people that are in your house
and so you want a little bit of new information
but you want those barriers to be there
so that you can voluntarily modulate the information flow.
Okay, so that's the first thing you do
and then you set up rules with everybody else, it says, well, I'm gonna have some walls voluntarily modulate the information flow. Okay, so that's the first thing you do.
And then you set up rules with everybody else, it says,
well, I'm going to have some walls so you can't come in,
but what I'm going to do is pay you for that privilege by letting you have
some walls where people can't come in.
And so I think that's analogous.
I was thinking about the issue of discrimination in relationship to sex,
because I've been thinking a lot
about discrimination lately, because everybody thinks discrimination is a bad idea, which
is a very stupid proposition, because you're discriminating all the time.
And the most fundamental form of discrimination is choice of sexual partner.
And so you might say, well, why should that even be allowed?
Because it is the most fundamental form of discrimination.
So for example, almost everyone is racially prejudiced
when it comes to sexual partners.
So you think, well, is that a, what about,
are you, do you use age as an exclusionary criteria?
Probably, do you use physical attractiveness only in so far as you're able?
Right? You use it completely if you could get away with it, roughly speaking.
But you can't because the most attractive people aren't going to be anywhere near you.
So you can't do it, but you'd like to. Health, yes, strength, yes, wealth, yes, education, definitely.
So it's unbelievably discriminatory. And so you might say, well, why is that justifiable? And it seems to me that it's something like, well,
you get to say no to me if I get to say no to you.
It's something like that.
We've agreed that everybody gets to discriminate
on that basis.
And because everybody can do it, then it's fair.
It's something like that.
It's very much worth thinking about.
I don't know if you know this, but in Huxley's book Brave New World,
where the family had been completely demolished, right?
And children were conceived in bottles
and produced in factories.
So the whole idea of the relationship between sex
and procreation had become a taboo.
One of the mantras, the slogans of the society, was everyone belongs to everyone else.
And so it was actually a social faux pas to refuse to sleep with someone just as it was
a social faux pas to have any exclusionary relationship.
Because another thing that you might notice is that there's nothing more discriminatory
than falling in love with someone.
It's like, you're special and all the rest of you?
No.
So it's the ultimate exclusionary act, right?
And yet we presume that that's unacceptable, not only acceptable.
We demand that as a right.
And well, that's we're thinking about a lot.
Anyways, okay, so what you're doing is by agreeing to this segregation and boxing, what you're
doing is carving off little bits of the world that are simple enough so that someone like
you can live for some amount of time there without too much danger.
And everyone agrees to do that, roughly speaking, because everybody needs to engage in that
process of simplification and safety provision.
And so we have towns and the towns are nothing but boxes, but inside boxes.
So there's a good schematic of a little house, and you can see that even inside the same place,
we segregate off rooms for different purposes.
And then what's interesting too is that we set up those rooms as little dramatic spaces,
right?
So you furnish them and you furnish them with things that tell you how to behave in that
room.
So, table and chairs tells you that's where you're going to eat and that's where people
are going to sit and they're roughly going to sit facing each other.
That has certain implications because the chairs don't face the walls, they face each
other.
And you have a living room where it's comfortable and there's a fire and you know you're setting
up little stages basically so that just like kids do when they pretend, you know they
all assign each other roles and then they lay out a little drama and that's what you do
when you invite someone over.
Well let's sit in a living room.
Well you probably get a drink if you sit in a living room and hypothetically you're going
to have some conversation.
And so it's a bounded place, there are rules that apply, and then you get to have a little exploration inside that set of bounded rules.
And if you're open, you're going to discuss all sorts of things, and if you're conservative and closed, then you're going to discuss a very, very small subset of things.
And so hopefully everyone will agree on that. So that's one form of binding.
Then another is, well, we put boxes around each other when it comes to groups. And so this
is a picture from the Democratic Convention when Obama was elected, if I remember correctly.
But anyways, what happens is that people
segregate themselves into little microgroups
like Democrats and Republicans.
They basically do that on temperamental grounds,
fundamentally.
And then they produce these games that everyone knows how
to play.
And that's another form of simplification.
So when you bring all these people together
at a political convention, it's not
like they all have the same ideas.
They don't.
And it could degenerate into chaos.
And sometimes that happens.
You get big demonstrations at these places.
And sometimes people throw tear gas and all of that.
But mostly speaking, it's pretty peaceful.
And the reason for that is that there's
a set of procedures in place that have some historical
justification that are embedded within a shared cultural and belief system, and everybody
goes there and agrees to play by the rules, roughly speaking.
And so then they can elect a candidate, they can kind of flip it down to a binary choice
for the election, right?
Yes or no, something like that.
And nobody gets killed usually.
So hooray for that.
That's a hell of a thing to pull off,
to be able to generate out of 300 million people,
two people to run for the highest office,
then let everyone play a game to determine
who they're going to be,
and then to have the bloody thing function
stably through power transitions.
Like, that never happens, right?
That's a complete bloody miracle,
and hardly any societies have ever pulled it off.
The power transition being the really important thing.
Because a tyrant can be stable for a while,
but usually what happens is he dies and all hell breaks loose.
So, I think George Washington, I think it was George Washington
that said, or had said about him, the reason that he was a great leader wasn't because he was president, but because he stopped being
president. And that's really worth thinking about.
So then the next thing that sort of simplifies your world is actually your physiological structure,
right? And we talked about that a little bit. Well, you can only see things there in front
of you, not things that are to decide or behind you. You know, you can only see things there in front of you, not things that are to the side or behind you. You can only see a very narrow chunk of the electromagnetic spectrum,
roughly that chunk that enables you to see by sunlight and to detect ripe fruit and that sort of thing. So it's very evolutionarily determined.
And you see things have a certain size quite easily
because they're handy, right?
So objects manifest themselves to you as things
because they have some relationship to your capacity
to use them as tools.
And that's dependent on your size.
You have a certain strength, and not a different strength.
You have a certain degree of articulation.
There's some things you can represent in language.
So you have limitations that screen out from your consideration, all sorts of things.
And that's bad, because, for example, before people discovered germs, there was a lot of them
zipping about killing people,
and the fact that we couldn't see them
wasn't such a good thing, but by the same token,
we're also not as overwhelmed with complexity
as we might be if we could detect everything,
and one of the problems with being connected so much
is that it's easy to drown in information.
And that's rough for information foragers.
You can't stay off your damn computer
because it opens up your senses far beyond their normal
limitations.
And so where should you stop?
Well, you don't.
You're on the damn thing like a pensioner on a slot machine
and for many of the same reasons.
So your body also filters out the world for you and provides you with
access to some information and not access to others. And then the same thing is the case
with your nervous system. And I do read, I put the first picture there of the, this is
the central nervous system, the control of voluntary movement, for example. I put it
there because people like to think that their brain is in their head,
but it's a stupid way of thinking about it as far as I'm concerned, because you have an awful lot of
neurological tissue distributed through your body, and like your autonomic nervous system,
if I remember correctly, which is mostly distributed through your body, has more neurons in it than your central nervous system.
And so, you aren't a brain in a body. You know, your brain is really, really
distributed through your whole body. And I think the idea that you have a brain in a body
is kind of a holdover from the idea that you have a soul in a body, and not that I'm necessarily
criticizing that idea, but I think they kind of got grafted onto one another. And so, but the problem with that is that,
and this is that, so it's the soul, body,
brain body, mind body, dichotomy,
which I think is the same dichotomy.
And the problem with that is that it's easy to think
of thought as something that's abstracted away from the body.
And I think that was an enlightenment idea, you know,
that just like the soul shouldn't
be contaminated by the demands of the body, if you were going to be pure spiritually,
so your thought shouldn't be contaminated by your subjectivity and your emotions and
your motivations and all of that, your abstractions should be independent of your subjectivity and rationality and
emotion are construed in that manner as enemies.
The purpose of rationality is to dispense with the irrationality of emotion and motivation.
Freud's idea of the properly functioning ego with something like that too, because the
id is this place of compulsion and drive, and the ego has to basically suppress that in
the service of the super ego.
There's no idea of integration really in Freud.
Now I don't want to be rough on Freud, and I think part of the reason that he thought
that way is because the patience
he had were precisely those who weren't very well integrated because of their pathological
past, and so they didn't know how to get those subsystems up into the overarching game,
and so their only alternative was something like suppression or repression. Because if you don't know how to be aggressive
in a sophisticated way,
you're still gonna be aggressive,
but you're gonna have to inhibit it,
control yourself,
because you can't just be aggressive around people,
it just won't go well for you.
So even if you can't do in a sophisticated way,
you're gonna repress it,
or you're gonna get in trouble, those are the options. So, okay, but if you can't do it in a sophisticated way, you're going to repress it, or you're going to get in trouble. Those are the options.
So OK, but if you start thinking about the brain,
the nervous system has part of the body as an inseparable part,
well, then the function of thinking
starts to become something different.
It's not so much the objective abstract representation
of the world, which is kind of what you're pursuing
if you're a scientist. It's more like it's more like conceptualization of and practice the practice of the proper way of
being in the world. And I think that's what you're more interested in anyway. So I don't see how you can't be since you're a living thing and you're overwhelmingly
motivated to successfully manifest those actions that a living thing has to manifest in
order to continue.
And it's complicated.
Like, you can boil it down to survival and reproduction.
It's a good overarching simplification.
But there's nothing simple about survival and reproduction.
I mean, all sorts of complex monsters emerge out of that,
even simple conceptualization.
But it's not unreasonable to assume that one of the things
that people generally want to do is to continue living in as pain-free manner as possible.
It's something like that.
Although that's a simplification.
So now the reason I'm making that case is because the fact that you have a body and
the fact that you have a nervous system is another set of limitations on how it is that
you're going to interact with the world. Okay, so now we've got a nervous system is another set of limitations on how it is that you're going to interact with the world.
Okay, so now we've got the nervous system.
We can go to higher resolution.
We say, well, you have a brain.
And the brain, see if I can, so that's the prefrontal cortex there.
And that's the temporal cortex there, and that's the parietal cortex there, and that's
the sensory cortex there.
And these were, if I remember properly, these were divisions that I think were first,
well they were first thought through in the late 19th and early 20th century.
They're slightly specialized, so this cortex back here is, does a lot of the elaboration of vision
and that one there helps you with your sense of embodiment
and your knowledge about where your body actually happens
to be localized, and then that one helps for example,
in some elements of language output,
and then the frontal cortex,
especially the prefrontal part, which is up here,
is concerned with the organization and implement
the organization of motor action.
And that's a good way of thinking about it.
You've got part of your brain that deals
with the sensory world and the integration of the sensory world
which seems to happen about there, or these places meet.
And the prefrontal cortex, it grew out of the motor cortex.
The motor cortex helps you plan and plan out voluntary actions.
The prefrontal cortex grew out of that in the course of evolution.
So you might think, well, there's reflex actions,
and they happen when something happens to you, you respond.
And then that elaborates up into the motor system,
and that enables you to act voluntarily in the world.
And then that elaborates up into the prefrontal motor
system, which helps you plan how you might act in the world.
So it's the prefrontal cortex that's the home of,
let's call it, its complex, sophisticated,
voluntary thought, which you could think about as a way
of representing the world, but which
is more accurately a way of generating avatars of yourself in hypothetical worlds to figure
out how they would survive if you did implement them into action.
And so I think that's why, so one of the weird things that you discover psychometrically
is that there's no correlation between conscientiousness and intelligence. And that's a weird one, you know, because people think about
intelligence as planning and forward thinking and all of that, but that's also
how they think about conscientiousness as planful behavior and and the
consideration of future possibilities, but intelligence and conscientiousness have
zero correlation.
And so you think, well, why is that? Well, I guess it has to be that way because
you couldn't think abstractly if you were prone to act out what you thought.
You just go and act it out. And that, like when I mentioned this to you before, when you dream,
you're paralyzed. And you can take that little part of the brain that
produces that perilous, perilous out of a cat or out of a person, but we haven't done it with people, out of a cat.
And then when the cat falls asleep and hits REM sleep, it'll run around until it runs
into something and then it'll wake up.
Also, the dream thinking is so tightly allied with action that there's no separation between
them.
So there's no real abstraction there.
If you couldn't abstract, you wouldn't be able to think.
And the fact that you can abstract
means that you can separate your thinking from your action.
So that's why, as far as I can tell,
there's very little correlation between conscientiousness
and intelligence.
It's like it has to be that way.
Because you have to be able to think about things
that you wouldn't do if you're going to think.
So, and in generally, we think of people who act as soon as they think as impulsive.
So, okay, well, so, there's a huge part of the brain that's devoted to sensory processing,
and there's a huge part of the brain that's devoted to planning, And the whole prefrontal part of the brain is devoted to planning.
And that's, and again, so what that indicates is that in large part,
as far as your evolved body is concerned,
the reason is that you think is so that you can act better.
And of course that makes sense.
And you can think about memory from that perspective too,
because if you think scientifically,
you think that your memory of the world
is something like an objective record of events,
of objective events, but it's really not very much like that at all.
And besides who cares?
You don't need an accurate representation
of all the facts about this room.
In fact, all it would do is weigh you down.
Who cares what color the walls are,
what color the ceiling is, or what color the paint is, all of that's not worth remembering,
partly because it has no relationship whatsoever to what you need to do in order to continue to act.
And so what you're doing when you remember, as far as I can tell, is that you're mining your
experience for information that you can bring forward into the future. It's purely pragmatic. And so, you know, I teach treat people who have
post-traumatic disorder or symptoms of post-traumatic disorder. And so let's say they got post-traumatic
stress disorder because, again, because a relationship collapsed on them suddenly. It's
quite common. You know, they get betrayed or someone leaves them suddenly and
then they don't know what to do because especially if they're conscientious because
then they just tear themselves into pieces trying to figure out what they did wrong
to bring about that event. And the reason they're doing that is because
they want to retool their perceptions and their actions so that the
probability that they'll have the same experience again is minimized.
And their mind won't leave them alone until they do it.
And no wonder, right?
Because if you fall into a big pit and you get really hurt, the first thing you should
figure out is how to not fall into big pits anymore.
And your mind is set up exactly for that.
And so what you do with someone who's
having problems like that, so maybe they're waking up at the middle of the night, obsessing
about what went wrong, is you walk them through it. You do a situational analysis first,
because one of the over simplifications that people make, and this is especially true
for conscientious people, is if something bad happened to me, I must have done something to deserve it.
Now, that's actually a pretty functional idea because it suggests that there are things
about your behavior that you could change that would make the future better.
But the problem is, is that, say, if it's the collapse of a relationship and you've been
with that person for eight years or longer, well, you
did so many things with them that the idea that you did something wrong pretty much extends
to every single thing you ever did with them.
And that's how are you going to fix that?
And so that's part of the trauma actually.
The trauma is 80 million snakes all at the same time.
It's like, well, forget it.
You don't have time to go through all that material.
And so partly what you do is with people,
and this is what you should do with yourself too,
is you do a situational analysis.
It's like don't be assuming necessarily
that the thing that happened to you only happened to you
because of what you did or didn't do.
There's all sorts of factors at play.
So one of the things that sometimes I do with clients
is if they were in a relationship,
and I can get some reasonable personality information
about both of them, I can point out
where they were temperamentally incompatible.
You know, like if you're a highly conscientious person
and your partner is very, very low in conscientiousness,
it's like, well, good luck to you too.
How the hell are you ever going to work that out?
Because you want everything to be exactly where it's supposed
to be, and you're working all the time,
and your partner could care less whether things were where
they're supposed to be, and they're not going to work.
And you can butt heads about that forever,
the probability that you're going to shift it,
except to some minor degree is very, very low.
And so sometimes you end up with someone
with whom you get along very well
on one temperamental dimension
and your absolute catastrophe on the other four.
And the probability that you're going to be able to mediate
a huge temperamental difference is extremely low.
You wouldn't expect yourself to mediate
a huge intellectual difference, right?
You're going to make the other person smarter,
or maybe you smarter depending on who you're with.
It's like, no, probably not, bit maybe.
So, you do a situational analysis.
And so, what you're trying to do is to extract out information
from your past and your present that will enable you to conduct
yourself properly into the future.
And so, that's another example of the pragmatic element of thought.
Well then, within the brain itself, apart from the major subdivisions which we just described,
there are minor subdivisions and here's a bunch of them listed that caught eight nucleus,
the cerebral cortex, the huge newest part of the brain that's about a square meter if you unfold it.
It's all folded up.
And most of the processing occurs right on the surface.
That's the idea, anyways.
The thalamus, that's a place where a lot of the information in the brain
appears to be integrated.
The cerebellum helps you with balance and the sequencing of complex motor activities.
The hippocampus, that's the one we talked about before.
One of the things that the hippocampus does
seems to do is compare your model of the world
as it's unfolding with the model that you desire to be occurring
and then keeps track of mismatches.
And if it detects a mismatch, then it
disinhibits other emotional and motivational centers.
And that's the beginning of your response to the unknown.
So one of them is the hypothalamus.
I'm going to concentrate on it for a bit.
It's a little tiny part of the brain that's
pretty much at the top of the spinal cord.
See, it's really small compared to the rest of the brain.
Now, it turns out that if, imagine this
is a cat brain for a minute.
And you take off the whole cat brain except for the hypothalamus, which people do, you take off the whole cortex,
for example.
And then the cat's still alive if you do it carefully, but it doesn't have much of a
brain, and so you might think, well, that cat would just do nothing, but the cat's actually
pretty functional if it's reduced just to its hypothalamus.
And that's because the hypothalamus is an incredibly important part of the brain, and it
provides what I would say, constitute the major frames, the major psychological frames.
And so, I like a de-cortic cat can still eat and drink and regulate its body temperature
and engage in defensive aggression,
and if it's female, it can still mate at male cat,
because male mating behavior is more complicated.
And as long as you keep it in a bounded environment,
it can function reasonably well.
It's hyper-curious, though,
which is very weird, because you wouldn't expect a cat
with no brain to be curious about anything,
but a cat with no brain is curious about everything.
And that seems to be because part of the reason that you aren't curious about something anymore is because you've investigated it,
and you've built a representation of it that's functional,
and that functional representation then stands for the thing itself,
and then you can ignore it. And so you learn to ignore things.
They're interesting to begin with, and then you learn ignore it. And so you learn to ignore things. They're interesting to begin with and then you learn to ignore them.
And so one of the things that I think artists do,
if they're great artists, is remind you
that there's more to things that you see now
that you've learned to ignore them.
So you get a kind of a hallucinogenic painting
of flowers like Van Gogh might produce,
like his famous irises, which I think sold
for like $220 million or something outrageous. It's like what Van Gogh is produce like his famous irises which I think sold for like 220 million dollars or something outrageous
It's like what Van Gogh is trying to show you is what those flowers looked like before you thought you could see them
Because now you flower and you walk by you know
You don't see it at all because you're off to get a peanut butter sandwich or something
You don't have time to glory in the wonder of the world, you know, you've got something practical to do
So All right, so we're gonna zoom in on the hypothalamus here to glory in the wonder of the world. You know, you've got something practical to do. So,
all right, so we're going to zoom in on the hypothalamus here.
And what you see, of course, when you zoom in on the hypothalamus is that it's not a thing, it's a whole bunch of things. And then it's one of those horrible
whole bunches of things that are made out of even more bunches of things, and they're made out
of more bunches of things. And what out of even more bunches of things and they're made out of more bunches of things.
What's really interesting about going down the body from an analytic perspective is it
doesn't seem to get less complex as you go farther down.
Some of the, I should actually show you that.
I haven't showed you that little video of DNA fixing itself.
I better show you that. It's so cool, it's
ridiculously cool, so you definitely need to see it. Until I encountered the
artworks of David Goodsell, who is a molecular biologist at the Scripps Institute,
and his pictures are all, everything's accurate, it's all to scale, and his work
illuminated for me what the molecular world inside this is like.
So this is a transaction through blood.
In the top left-hand corner you've got this yellow green area.
The yellow green area is the fluids of blood, which is mostly water,
but it's also antibody, sugars, hormones, that kind of thing.
And the red region is a slice into red blood cell.
And those red molecules are hemoglobin.
They are actually red. That's what gives blood.
It's color. And hemoglobin acts as a molecular sponge
to soak up the oxygen in your lungs
and then carry it to other parts of the body.
I was very much inspired by this image many years ago,
and I wondered whether we could use computer graphics
to represent the molecular world.
What would it look like?
And that's how I really began.
So let's begin.
This is DNA, and it's classic double helix form,
and it's from X-ray crystallography, so it's an accurate model of DNA.
If we unwind the double helix and unzip the two strands, you see these things that look
like teeth.
Those are the letters of genetic code, the 25,000 genes you've got written in your DNA.
This is what they typically talk about, the genetic code.
This is what they're talking about.
But I want to talk about a different aspect of DNA science and that is the physical
nature of DNA science, and that is that the physical nature of DNA, and it's these two strands that run in opposite directions for reasons
I can't go into right now, but they physically run in opposite directions, which creates
a number of complications for your living cells as you're about to see, most particularly
when DNA is being copied.
And so what I'm about to show you is an accurate representation of the actual DNA replication
machine that's occurring right now inside your body, at least 2002, biology.
So DNA is entering the production line from the left hand side and it hits this collection,
this miniature biochemical machines that are pulling apart the DNA strand and making
an exact copy.
So DNA comes in and hits this blue donut shape structure and it's ripped apart into its two strands
One strand can be copied directly and it's can see be seen spooling off down to the bottom there
But things aren't so simple to the other strand because it must be copied backwards
So it's thrown out repeatedly in these loops and copied one section at a time
creating two new DNA molecules now you have
Billions of this machine right now, wearing it right
way inside you, copying your DNA with exquisite fidelity. It's an accurate representation,
and it's pretty much at the correct speed for what it's occurring inside you, but I've
left out error correction and a bunch of other things. This was worked from a number of
years ago. Thank you. This was worked from a number of years ago, but I want to show you next is updated science.
It's updated technology.
So again, we begin with DNA, and it's jiggly and wiggling there because of the surrounding
super molecules which are stripped away so you can see something.
DNA is about two nanometers across, which is really quite tiny.
But in each one of your cells, each strand of DNA is about 30 to 40 million nanometers
long.
So to keep the DNA organized, to regulate access
to the genetic code, it's wrapped around these purple
proteins, our labeled and purple here.
It's packaged up in bundled web.
All of this field of view is a single strand of DNA.
This huge package of DNA is called a chromosome.
And we'll come back to chromosomes in a minute.
We're pulling out, we're zooming
out, out through a nuclear pore, which is sort of the gateway to this compartment that holds
all the DNA called the nucleus. All of this field of view is about a semester's worth
of biology, and I've got seven minutes, so we're not going to be able to do that today.
No, I'm being told no. This is the way a living cell looks down a light microscope
and it's been filmed under time latches, why you can see it moving. The nuclear envelope
breaks down, the sausage-shaped things are the chromosomes, we'll focus on them. They
go through this very striking motion that is focused on these little red spots. When
the cell feels it's ready to go, it rips apart the chromosome. One set of DNA goes to one side, the other side gets the other set of DNA, identical copies
of DNA, and then the cell splits down the middle.
And again, you have billions of cells undergoing this process right now inside of you.
Now we're going to rewind and just focus on the chromosomes and look at its structure
and describe it.
So again, here we are at that equator moment.
The chromosomes line up, and if we isolate just one chromosome,
we're gonna pull it out and have a look at its structure.
So this is one of the biggest molecular structures
that you have in Lisa as far as we've discovered so far
inside of us.
So this is a single chromosome,
and you have two strands of DNA in each chromosome.
One is bundled up into one sausage, the other strand is bundled up into the other sausage.
These things that look like whiskers that are sticking out from either side are the dynamic
scaffolding of the cell.
They're called microtubules, but it's not so important.
But we're going to focus on this red region.
I've labeled it red here.
And it's the interface between the dynamic scaffolding and the chromosomes.
It is obviously central to the movement of the chromosomes.
We have no idea, really, as to how it's achieving that movement.
We've been studying this thing, the called the Connecticut,
for over 100 years with intense study,
and we're still just beginning to discover what it's all about.
It is made up of about 200 different types of proteins,
thousands of proteins in total.
It is a signal broadcasting system.
It broadcasts through chemical signals telling the rest of the cell when it's ready, when
it feels that everything is aligned and ready to go for the separation of the chromosomes.
It is able to couple onto the growing and shrinking microtubules.
It's transiently, it's involved with the growing of the microtubules and it's able to
transiently couple onto them. It's also a the growing of the microtubules, and it's able to transcend a couple on to them.
It's also a tension sensing system.
It's able to feel when the cell is ready,
when the chromosome is in a correctly positioned.
It's turning green here because it feels
that everything is just right.
And you'll see there's this one little last bit
that's still remaining red.
And it's walked away down the microtubules.
That is the signal broadcasting system.
It's any other stop signal, and it's walked away. It's that mechanical.
It's molecular clockwork. This is how you work at the molecular scale.
So with a little bit of molecular eye candy, we've got kinesens, which are the orange ones.
They're a little molecular, the courier molecule is walking one way, and here are the dining.
They're carrying that broadcasting system, and they've got their long legs so they can step around obstacles and so on.
So again, this is all derived accurately from the science.
The problem is we can't show it to you any other way.
Exploring at the frontier of science,
at the frontier of human understanding is mind-blowing.
Discovering the stuff is certainly a pleasurable incentive to work in science.
But most medical researchers, this is just discovering this stuff, is simply steps along the path to the big goals,
which are to eradicate disease, to eliminate the suffering and the misery that disease causes, and to lift people out of poverty.
Thank you.
So that's just so ridiculously mind-blowing that it's almost unbearable. I mean to think
about that as clockwork even is a pretty strange idea because while those little things walk
over obstacles it's like how the hell does that happen? They're just molecules. So it's
so cool because when you go down you'd think simple but you know. And you know he said at the beginning when they were taking that,
when the little machines were taking that DNA apart that he didn't show the error correcting.
You know there are other little machines that go along and see if everything's okay and
if it isn't they cut it out and put it right piece in. It's like yeah things we don't understand.
There's no shortage of them, that's for sure.
OK, so what I'm doing in some sense
is walking you through a psychophysiological
or representation of PHA's developmental process, I would say.
So I wanted to zero in on the hypothalamus,
because it seems to me the thing that
sets the most basic frames.
And so we'll go ahead with that.
So you see that it's made up of all these little parts.
And so it's called the hypothalamus more for convenience than because it's a homogenous
set of structures because it's not a homogenous set of structures.
This is something to consider very carefully
when you're thinking about the terminology
that psychologists use or that you might use
to describe your own behavior.
Because you know, you can roughly,
there is a psychology of motivation
and there's a psychology of emotion.
And you might think, well, emotion and motivation
are categorically different entities.
But they're not.
In fact, there's no such thing as a uniform set of motivations, and there's no such thing as a uniform set of emotions,
and the distinction between a motivation and an emotion is unclear, to say the least.
And that's partly because the physiological substructures that subsume what we call motivations, and what we call emotions,
and it's not like there's a motivation center that's
homogenous.
The closest is the hypothalamus, but it's made of structures
that are qualitatively different.
And then the emotions, because I have to use that descriptive
terminology, because we have to communicate it about it
somehow, there's all sorts of different structures in the brain
that contribute to emotional expression.
And they're not even in the same place, much less composed of identical structure or function.
So, you know, we have the shorthands that we use
to divide up the world, but they're awkward and untenable
as the level of resolution increases.
But anyways, I'm still going to go with motivation
and emotion, because it's a useful simplification,
but you can see with the hypothalamus that there's all these complicated little subsystems
in there.
And I showed you that video to show you just how complicated the subsystems are all the
way down to the molecular level.
How those little machines manage what they do is completely beyond me to call it clockwork
when those little things that walk and walk over obstacles.
It's like clockwork does one thing, you know, only.
Click, click, click, click, that's all it does.
No exceptions.
This thing walks over obstacles to get where it's going.
It's like, who knows what's going on down there.
But it works well enough, so here we are, weirdly enough.
So, motivation seems to me to be the initial framing process.
And you come into the world with the motivational systems
roughly ready to go, you know, babies are hungry,
babies get cold, babies want something to drink, you know, so
the world already comes in some sense, they come into the world with
pre-packaged categories
for existence, and those are the categories
that are going to aid their survival.
And they're not simple either.
It's not so simple.
It's, well, hunger, thirst, pleasure, pain, anxiety,
the classics and the classic emotions, sadness, joy,
and so forth.
Those systems are already there,
but babies have more complicated
systems, too, like the system for exploration is already in place and the system for play,
which is really complicated. It's already in place. And so, you know, you come into the
world with a human nature, and the nature seems to be distributed across the subsystems.
That's one way of thinking about it. And it's also useful to think about the operation of those
subsystems as something like, you could think about them as
games with an aim.
You could think about them as stories.
You could think about them as frames of reference.
You can think about them as action patterns.
And you can think about them as some personalities, which I
actually think is maybe the best way to think about them.
Because if you're hungry, it's not a deterministic drive.
It's a some personality that has a goal,
and then it has a bunch of action patterns
that are going to work in reference to that goal.
It has a bunch of perceptions that suit that goal,
and it organizes your emotional responses around that goal.
And so to think about it as a personality,
it's a much more intelligent way to look at it.
One of the thing about Skinner's rats,
Skinner could get rats to do almost everything,
and he would reward them with food.
And so he had a simple rat model.
But his rats were starved down to 75%
of their normal body weight.
So not only were they not social gregarious rats,
like rats are, because they were isolated.
They were genetically altered from wild rats, but they also weren't as complex as a real
rat because they were starving.
But a starving rat is a pretty good model of a rat, and a rat is a pretty good model
of a person.
But a lot of our models of simple behavior learning were based on starving isolated rats.
So anyways, how to think about
motivation? We'll think about it from the hypothalamic perspective. So we could say one thing
that motivation does is set goals. We could say that emotions track progress towards goals.
And I'm going to use that schema, even though it's not exactly right. So you say, well, motivation
determines where you're going to aim. So if you're hungry, you're going to aim at something to eat.
And then that will organize your perceptions so that you zero out everything that isn't relevant to that task,
which is almost everything.
You concentrate on those few things that are going to facilitate your movement forward.
When you encounter those things, that produces positive emotion.
As you move through the world towards your goal,
and you see that things are laying themselves out that facilitate your movement forward. Those things cause positive
emotion. And if you encounter anything that gets in the way, then that produces
negative emotion. And it can be like threat because you're not supposed to
encounter something that gets in the way. It can be anger so that you move it away.
It can be frustration, disappointment, grief. Those would, if you had a
response, that serious to an obstacle.
It would probably punish the little motivated frame
right out of existence.
So you walk downstairs and I don't know,
the contracting company instead of wrecking
ball through your kitchen.
It's like that's going to be disappointing.
You're not going to keep eating the peanut butter sandwich
in the rubble.
That little frame is going to get punished out of existence. And some new goal is going to pop up and it's dead.
And you know, one of the things we're going to try to sort out is how do you decide when
you've encountered an obstacle that's so big that you should just quit and go do something
else?
Because that's not obvious.
You know, and you can, you can get into counterproductive persistence pretty easily.
So we don't know how people solve that problem.
It's a really complicated one.
So anyways, we're going to work on that scenario.
Your hypothalamus pops up micro goals
that are directly relevant to biological survival.
That produces a frame of reference.
So it's not a goal, it's not a drive,
and it's not a collection of behaviors.
It's a little personality and the personality
has a viewpoint, it has thoughts that go along with it, it has perceptions, it has action
tendencies, all of that. You can see this in addiction most particularly. So one of the
things that you find often with people who are alcoholic is they lie all the time.
And that's because when they're, they've built a little alcohol dependent personality inside
of themselves, or a big one.
It might maybe it's 90% of their personality.
And one of the things that consists of is all the rationalizations that they've used
over the years to justify their addiction to themselves and to other people.
And so the addiction has a personality. And know, and so when the person is off
or maybe they're addicted to meth or something like that where we know the addiction is more
good. It's it's more short-term powerful that I would say then in the alcohol addiction. They'll say anything and
that the words are just tools used to get towards the goal. And if they happen to be deceptive, whatever it doesn't matter,
just tools used to get towards the goal. And if they happen to be deceptive, whatever,
it doesn't matter, they're just practical tools
to get towards the goal.
And then when you get towards the goal,
and you take a nice shot of math or something like that,
you reinforce all those rationales that you use
to get the drug, and then the next time you're even
a better deceiver and liar.
So OK, so we're going to say motivations.
One way of thinking about it is they set goals,
but it's not the right way of thinking about it.
They produce a whole framework of interpretation, and so we're going to think about that framework
of interpretation, and then emotions emerge inside of that.
So that's it.
The world is framed, motivation set goals, you could say the world has to be framed.
So motivation sets that frame, goes goals, emotions, perceptions, and actions, and then actions
track progress.
So positive emotion says, you're moving forward, properly towards your goal.
And if you encounter something you don't expect, you stop.
That's anxiety.
It's like, oh, we're not where we thought we were.
And so we don't know what to do.
So we should stop, because we don't know where we are or what we're doing.
Stop, frozen.
And then the more powerful negative emotions, like pain,
they might make you get out of there.
So emotions, forward, stop, reverse.
That's your emotions within that motivated frame.
So, and that's another example of how your mind is
embedded in your body.
You know, emotions are like their offshoots of action tendencies.
That's the right way
to think about it because action is everything fundamentally.
So what are some basic motivations? Most of these are regulated by the hypothalamus by the
way, and that tells you just how important a control system. It is, the other thing that's
useful to know about the hypothalamus is that it has projections going up from it that are
like tree trunks and inhibitory projections
coming down that are like grapevines.
So you can kind of control your hypothalamus as long as it's not on too much, but if it's
on in any serious way, it's like it wins.
So partly what you do to stop yourself from falling under the dominion of your hypothalamus
is to never ever be anywhere
where its action is necessary, right?
You don't wanna go into a biker bar
because you might find yourself in a situation
where panic defensive aggression is immediately necessary.
You probably don't want that.
You don't want the panic, you don't want the terror,
you don't want the frenzied fight, you don't want any of that.
You don't wanna have to run away and absolute panic. So you just don't want the frenzied fight. You don't want any of that. You don't want to have to run away in absolute panic
So you just don't go there and then a huge
Huge part of how we regulate our emotions is just by never going anywhere where we have to experience them
And so that has very little to do with internal inhibitory control and everything to do with
staying where you belong
so
Okay, so basic motivations hunger thirst pain pain is not regulated by the hypothalamus staying where you belong. So, okay.
So, basic motivations.
Hunger, thirst, pain.
Pain is not regulated by the hypothalamus.
That's a different circuit.
Anger, slash aggression.
Thermal regulation.
Panic and escape.
Affiliation and care.
Sexual desire.
Exploration, play.
And you can kind of break those in.
You can kind of break those into
the classic Darwinian categories too and say, well, there's a set of motivations
that go along with self-maintenance.
That'd be your survival, ingestive and defensive.
See, I've sort of coded them there.
So the self-maintenance, there's an ingestive set
of basic motivations that go with self-maintenance.
You say that's hunger, thirst.
There's a set of defensive motivations, pain, anger, thermal regulation, panic and escape.
And then there's motivations that are associated with reproduction, affiliation, care, and
sexual desire.
And then I put exploration and play sort of outside of that.
I would say because those two things serve both of these
approximately equally.
So what I tried to do is take the basic motivations and then
nest them inside a fundamental Darwinian framework so that
you could see how the biological process of evolution has
manifested itself and then sort of differentiated into these
fundamental biological systems.
So, okay, so this is a rat brain, flat map.
And so it's basically what you would see of a rat's brain if you flattened it out, unrolled
it, flattened it out, and then made it to dimension.
And you can see here, so this is the hypothalamus. And you can see that it's made out of these different nuclei.
That's what they're called.
And they sort of correspond to those shapes that I showed you in the human hypothalamus earlier.
And you see that there's different systems.
There's the system for eating and drinking is outlined in green.
And the reproductive system, there's two of them, and they're outlined in,
and I think it's red. Is that right?
There's two of them and they're outlined in, and I think it's red, is that right?
Yeah, reproductive is red and the defensive ones
are in magenta.
And so those are the, you can think about those
as the three fundamental value systems
of living creatures with complex nervous systems
as far as the hypothalamus is concerned.
And then given what I told you about the hypothalamus,
which is you
hardly need the rest of your brain at all as long as you have a hypothalamus
it's worth thinking that those are very fundamental to value per se. Now you
might think if you only need the damn hypothalamus why bother with the rest of
the brain at all which is that's a very useful question especially because
most creatures don't have much of a brain.
So, but it seems to be something like,
well, you've got your eating and drinking system,
your reproductive system, and your defensive system.
But the problem is, is that those things, first of all,
can conflict, you know, are you too hungry to sleep or too sleepy to eat?
That's a pretty simple kind of contradiction.
Are you more angry at your partner
or do you want sexual relations more?
So they can conflict in the present,
but then they can conflict with other people
doing the same thing and they can conflict across time.
And so partly the reason that you need the rest
of your brain is to solve the problems that emerge
from the solutions that the hypothalamus offers. And so because you don't want to just eat and drink and reproduce and
and and defend yourself, you want to eat now, later, tomorrow, next week, and next month,
while you're able to engage in reproductive activity and defend yourself in multiple contexts
with a whole bunch of people for as long as you can possibly
manage it.
And so you need the rest of your brain to calculate that.
And so what the rest of your brain has to do, roughly speaking,
is regulate these and also elaborate them up
into something that's integrated inside you, which might
roughly be your personality, and then so that that
personality is integrated
with the personality of other people.
And so you can think about it as an emergent process.
This is one of the things I really like about PSJA.
He's so damn smart because PSJA is the only thinker I know,
really, who really addressed the problem
of the evolution of value systems.
Now, he never nailed it down to the physiology
because there wasn't enough known about physiology
when he did his work, but it maps really nicely
onto the physiology.
But he said, well, but he got it right anyways.
He said, you come into the world with a handful
of pre-established reflexes.
Okay, we're gonna complicate that up a bit.
No, you come into the world with a handful
of micropersonalities that are centered around these fundamental motivational axes,
okay? And then that gets you started and that has motor output as well as
perceptions and all of that that's associated with it. And then as you
interact initially, let's say with your mother, you start to learn how to
integrate those things in some sort of social context because you form a relationship with your mother right off the bat.
And so you're starting to figure out how to produce patterned and stable interactions
between those motivational systems on a day-to-day, week-to-week, month-to-month basis.
And one of the things you do with kids, it's really important to do this with kids is you want to get them on to some sort of a routine. Because what the routine is actually
is the beginnings of the system that integrates all of these underlying biological systems into
some sort of unity. Because they have to sleep and wake up. So you want to get nail that down,
so it's predictable. You know, they have to eat, they have to stay warm,
and they need to do that in a manner that's stable.
And so it's to your great benefit, as a parent,
that you get islands of stability planted
in the life of your kid so that some of this gets simplified
so that the kid isn't constantly preoccupied
with domination by these different motivational systems.
And so it's a useful thing to know because you might think, well, you don't want to impose any structure on your baby.
It's like, no, wrong.
You don't want to be a tyrant about it, but there's no difference between that structure and the emergence of the child's adaptation to the world.
And to some degree, what you're trying to do is free them up from arbitrary domination by these underlying motivational systems.
You know, because a baby gets too tired, it's a horrible little thing.
It'll just scream at you non-stop and it's not happy about it. It's like it's not good for anyone for that to happen.
And so the faster you have to do it in relationship with the child,
you know, some will sleep right away in a schedule almost immediately,
and other kids are harder to get their circadian rhythms
regulated.
So you have to attend to the individual differences
that characterize the child.
But you're still trying to establish some stable harmony
out of this mishmash of initial systems.
harmony out of this mishmash of initial systems.
All right, so that's sort of a physiological look. This is more of a conceptual look at it.
So I said that each of these systems,
you can think about in a bunch of different ways.
You can think about about something that sets a goal.
I'm hungry and I don't want to be hungry,
point A, point B.
So the hunger and the vision of the satiation
of the hunger are all part of the same frame.
And so if you're hungry, you go into the kitchen,
you know that already, that's part of your
procedural knowledge about how the world works,
and then what you're gonna look for are only those things that are relevant to
what you're trying to do in the kitchen. Everything else is zeroed out. You won't even
really see it, and why would you?
You want to see the things that are relevant to the task at hand.
And so that, that's the thing that's so cool.
I think because what it means is that you see the things that are relevant to the
task at hand.
And so here's something to think about. Let's say that you see the things that are relevant to the task at hand. And so here's something to think about.
Let's say that you see a whole bunch of things in the world that you don't want to see,
you know, that make you constantly miserable and unhappy.
One thing you might ask yourself is,
are you sure that your goals are proper?
Because your goals determine what you see.
Now, not 100% obviously.
You can be thinking about the homework you're going to do
and step off a curb and be hit by a van.
It's like you're going to get hit by the van
regardless of how you've oriented your perceptions
likely in all likelihood.
So I'm not trying to argue for pure solipsism,
but it is very interesting to consider
that since you see in relationship to what you want,
that a very large amount of what you see is dependent on what you're aiming at.
And so one issue is, if your life is wretched and miserable, one thing to think about is whether or not what you're aiming at is the right thing to be aiming at.
And nothing is exactly the wrong answer to that. I'm aiming at nothing. So, okay, you're going to experience a tremendous amount of misery and not very much joy. So, anyways, you've got this little frame, you're somewhere,
and it's not good enough, and you're going somewhere else that's going to be better. And what better
depends upon is the state of these underlying biological systems, and then more
complexly, as those biological systems get integrated
into a personality and into the social world,
then the frame and the goal is going
to be dependent on that more complex hierarchical organization.
So you're not in here because you're hungry.
You're in here because if you get a degree,
maybe you don't ever have to be hungry.
So the hunger is properly incorporated into your, you don't want to be cold, you don't
want to freeze to death in the winter, you don't want to be on the street.
So, your higher-order goals are long-term, socially negotiated solutions to the problems
that are implicit in your being.
That might be one way of thinking about it.
So, and the micro-elements of this, so you could say, I'm hungry, that's a physiological
state and a conception.
I have a vision of how I'm going to solve that.
But then, and those are, that's an abstraction.
But what you do to transform point A into point B is not an abstraction.
You act.
You know, so if you're hungry, you actually move your body, say
down from the second floor into the kitchen, and you arrange things so that there's transformations
in the world, and that's a good way of thinking about the relationship between the mind and
the body. Your hypothetical solution to your problem, that's the mind. But the manner
in which you incarnate that solution, that's no longer abstract.
So, you know, people are always trying to solve the mind body problem.
And that's as far as I can tell, that's how you solve it.
You have abstractions, but they're not abstractions that are representations of the world.
They're abstractions that are representations of action patterns.
And the way those are implemented in the world is that you act them.
And so it's strange, because you've got this weird level of control, you know, I can move my arm,
and I seem to be able to do that voluntarily, but I really have no idea how I'm doing it.
I don't have conscious access exactly to the musculature except technically,
and I certainly have no idea what I'm doing chemically to make those muscles transform.
But my, so my abstractions ground out in this movement.
And I can observe the movement and modify it.
But I have no conscious access whatsoever to the microprocesses
that are making that possible.
I have no idea why that is. Probably because I'm not smart enough.
That would be my guess, right?
Is your only going to, evolution is only going to allow your mind to control
those elements of your being that you're smart enough to control.
And so you don't get voluntary control over your heartbeat, for example,
because you just forget. And then you'd be wandering around.
And then you'd forget to beat your heart and bang, you'd be wandering around. And then you'd forget
to beat your heart and bang, you'd be dead. So you don't get to do that. So, all right.
So all these different, I classified these again as self-propegation and self-maintenance
motivations. And so if you're too hot, well, you want to go somewhere cooler. And if you're
too cool, you want to go somewhere hotter. and same if you're thirsty and hungry, and for self-propagation, well, you get lonesome, and maybe you have some sexual desire,
and each of those different systems competes for access to this central frame, and that's something like the contents of your consciousness at any given time.
So, up pops a desire, but it's wrong way of thinking about it. Because
the desire sounds like something that's pushing you forward, but the desire is goal, framework,
emotion, perception, action, pattern, all at the same time. It's a little personality,
or it's a little story. Actually, when you describe the operation of one of these things,
that's when you're telling a story. So, I was somewhere, I needed something, I went and got it.
It's boring little story, but that's the basic unit of a story.
Because I don't care to hear what you're doing
unless you had a reason for doing it.
I just say, what's the point of the story?
And the point of the story is the point.
It's directional.
It says, I went from here to there.
That's the point.
Here's how I did it.
That's the point.
And you're interested in that, because maybe you
want to know how to do it, too.
And you won't have to struggle through it.
Like I did, you could just listen.
And so we're always throwing these little units of information
back and forth to each other.
And for good reason, I want to know what your point is.
Because better I learned it from you than make all the mistakes that you had to make when
you were learning it.
And human beings, we got that figured out, that's for sure.
So, okay, I'm going to just explain this and then we'll stop.
All right, so we're in one of those frames now and we're going from point A to point B.
And so the question is, how does the world lay itself out?
Okay, so the first thing to understand, and this is partly the reason I showed you the grill of video, is that
the first thing a frame does for you is make almost everything irrelevant.
And that's so great, because that's what you want.
You want almost everything to be irrelevant, because otherwise you're going to be so flooded with information that you, that's what hallucinogens do, at least in their initial stages, is
they take away that filter and make everything relevant.
You can read about that in Huxley's Dora's of Perception.
He does a great job of describing the initial stages of a masculine experience and what happens
is that all of the memory in some sense that
regulates his perceptions is stripped off and so he sees everything glowing and alive
and magical like he'd never encountered it before which is exactly how you would see something
if all your memory about it was gone. And so he sees things as way more complex and interesting
than he normally sees them. Well that's fine but you know if you're like that all the time then
you know you end up in a ditch starving to death
or something.
It's not commensurate with normal life.
That's what it looks like.
And so your perceptions are just shrunken, restricted
to the bare minimum necessary to keep you moving in the direction
that you're moving.
All right, so the first thing you want to do
is you want to make things irrelevant.
Now, if you're with someone in a relationship,
partly what you want them to do is to help you continue making most of their possibility
irrelevant. It's polite because one of the things you say, well, we have friendship,
let's say we have a friendship, okay? So that means you've agreed, you've agreed to act in a friendly manner towards me and to support me.
There's all sorts of other ways you could act, like a myriad of them.
And I'm going to do the same for you.
So we're simpler to each other than we would normally be.
And then you go and do something that betrays me.
It's like bang, that whole simplification is gone.
And all those parts of you that were supposed to be irrelevant,
because we were playing
the same game, they're dead relevant, and I don't know who the hell you are.
And so that's really rough, and people do not like that.
It's this emergent mismatch between their desires and the way the world is manifesting
itself.
So one of the issues of complexity is that when you hit an obstacle, everything that you have agreed with other people
to make irrelevant is irrelevant.
And that's generally a disconcerting experience.
Now, you can, you know, you might want to toy
a little bit with that in a relationship, you know,
so maybe you encourage your partner to dress differently
or you go do different things or something
because you don't want to be stuck in exactly
the same old rut.
And so what you'll agree is how you can both deviate
an interesting amount.
But that's voluntary and controlled.
It's not the same at all as having that little mess
of 80 million snakes pop up right in front of you,
which is the last thing you want to have happen.
And so it's so weird because one of the things that we're striving to do
constantly is to keep most of the worldly relevant. And our cultural systems are designed precisely for
that purpose. And part of what you do when you disrupt them is you force people to consider a far
more range of relevance than they are even vaguely comfortable or vaguely competent to manage
and it just burns them to a crisp.
Because what your body does is, if all of a sudden everything around you is irrelevant,
like I could say, you're stripped naked, I take you in a helicopter, drop you right into
the middle of a jungle at midnight.
It's like you're not bored.
Standing there frozen, paralyzed, everything is interesting.
Well, too bad for you, because too interesting is very little different from terrifying.
And so, you know, your heart rate is going to be at 160 for like two days, and then something
will eat you, and your problems will be over.
So, all right.
So, this diagram basically suggests this, is this is how you break up the world when you're
going from point A to point B.
It renders almost everything, we irrelevant, hooray.
And then what happens is the rest of the world
is broken up into obstacles that get in your way
and tools that facilitate your movement forward.
And that's actually what you see when you come into a place.
Like when you come into this room,
these are obstacles in so far as you can't walk through
them.
And those are tools in so far as you can sit on them and watch the class.
This is a tool.
And these are tools.
And this is a tool.
And I'm a tool for, although I never admit it.
But anyways, I'm a tool because you need to take this class in order to advance towards your degree.
And so basically what you see in the world are entities of functional significance and
those are not objects.
They are not the same thing.
And that's very much worth considering because we're trying to build up a case at least
in part for analyzing the nature of the structures within which you organize your perceptions.
And we tend to think that those are predicated on object perception. It's not true.
It's not true. They're predicated on relevance conception. Does it help you? Does it get in your way or is it irrelevant?
That's what you want to know. If it helps you, you're happy about it. If it gets in your way, you're negatively predisposed towards it. If it's irrelevant,
it's invisible. And so, if your little scheme is functional, your little frame is functional,
then most of the things that you encounter are mildly positive. And that's how you know that you know
what you're doing. That's how you validate the entire frame. So, okay, good.
If you found this conversation meaningful, you might consider picking up Dad's books, maps of
meaning the architecture of belief, or as newer bestseller, 12 rules for life and antidote to chaos.
Both of these works delve much deeper into the topics covered in the Jordan B Peterson podcast.
See JordanBeePeterson.com for audio, e, ebook and text links or pick up the books at your favorite bookseller. Remember to check out
Jordan B Peterson dot com slash personality for information on his personality course.
And if you want to listen to a different podcast, like I said, the Michaela Peterson podcast is on
YouTube or wherever you listen to podcasts. I hope you enjoyed this episode. If you did,
please let a friend know or leave a review. I hope you enjoyed this episode. If you did, please let a friend
know or leave a review. Talk to you next week. Follow me on my YouTube channel, Jordan B. Peterson,
on Twitter, at Jordan B. Peterson, on Facebook, at Dr. Jordan B. Peterson, and at Instagram at
Jordan.b. Peterson. Details on this show, access to my blog, information about my tour dates and other events,
and my list of recommended books can be found on my website, JordanBPeterson.com.
My online writing programs, designed to help people straighten out their pasts, understand
themselves in the present, and develop a sophisticated vision and strategy for the future, can
be found at selfauthoring.com.
That's selfauthoring.com from the Westwood One Podcast Network.