The Jordan B. Peterson Podcast - 265. Meritocracy or Else | Dr. Adrian Wooldridge
Episode Date: June 27, 2022Dr. Adrian Wooldridge is a political editor at The Economist and author of the new book ‘The Aristocracy of Talent: How Meritocracy Made the Modern World.’In this episode, Dr. Wooldridge and I dis...cuss how his new book has been received, the history of meritocracy, how IQ testing shaped educational policy, group-based judgement, and the importance of defending liberal individualism. —Links—Follow Dr. Wooldridge on Twitter: https://twitter.com/adwooldridge‘The Aristocracy of Talent: How Meritocracy Made the Modern World:’ https://amazon.com/Aristocracy-Talent...More books by Dr. Wooldridge: https://amazon.com/kindle-dbs/entity/...—Chapters—[0:00] Intro[1:06] Reviews of ‘The Aristocracy of Talent’[3:47] Measuring the Mind, History of IQ Testing, & British Education[7:22] 11+ System vs. the Modern Prolonged Educational System[10:22] Workplace Selection Tests [11:58] IQ Literature & IQ Testing for the US Military[14:55] Michael Young’s ‘The Rise of the Meritocracy’[16:58] Pareto Distribution, Matthew Principle, & Creative Achievement Tests[18:22] History of Meritocracy [22:43] Conflating Moral Worth with Intellectual Ability[24:25] Conceptual Inadequacy & “Bell Curve Liberals”[29:45] Blank Slate Argument & Ethnic Differences in IQ Testing[34:59] White Working Class in England [37:45] Perception of Meritocracy in the UK vs. US[42:21] Judging People as Group Members [48:17] Distinction Between Affirmative Action & Diversity[51:36] Idea of Meritocracy as Propaganda for the Elite[54:00] Openness of Competition of Examinations[56:10] Foucault & the Complexity of Perception[59:55] Social Justice, Economic Efficiency & Growth Rates[1:05:35] Challenges to Western Dominance[1:10:59] European Ladder of Opportunity & Plutocracy [1:14:32] Ethics: Levels of Analysis
Transcript
Discussion (0)
[♪ Music playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background, playing in background born in 1959 and educated at Bollyill College, Oxford, where he took her first in modern history, and
all souls college were held a prize fellowship and was awarded a D fill. His thesis was published
as measuring the mind. He's worked for the Economist magazine since 1988, including as West Coast Bureau Chief,
Washington Bureau Chief, an author of the Lexington Column Management Editor,
an author of the Shumpeter Column, and Political Editor, an author of the Beigehawk Column.
He's the author or co-author of ten books, including The Right Nation, Conservative Power in America,
with John Mick-Mickleff-Wayt, Capitalism in America, with John McElthweight, capitalism in America,
with Ellen Greenspan, his most recent book, which I recently read, is The Aristocracy of Talent,
How Maritocracy Made the Modern World. I've rarely researched or been able to talk with someone who
has so many interests that dovetail with mine, and very much looking forward to this conversation.
So you've published this aristocracy of talent Talent and it's the continuance of an
interest that you've held for a long time.
How has the book been received?
Well, I'm glad to say that the book has been extremely well received in Britain.
It's been reviewed by all the leading periodicals on both the left and the right and has been widely discussed
on the radio and in various media outlets. In the United States, the reception has been
much more muted, I would say. It hasn't been discussed anywhere near as widely, although
there is discussion going on and it's beginning to mount a bit.
But what most Erksmys, it hasn't been reviewed by the New York
Times.
The every, all the major publications in this country,
I'm by this country, I'm in Britain,
where I'm sitting now, reviewed it.
The New York Times hasn't reviewed it.
The New York Review, Books hasn't reviewed it.
A lot of the sort of mainstream, particularly liberal publications
reviewed it here in Britain, all the liberal publications reviewed it. And I thought I expected
to be more criticised than I was by the liberal publications. It was a sense in many
liberal publications that this is an idea that we should grapple with and we shouldn't dismiss
out of hand. I was very pleased by, you know,
the reception both on the left and the right, for example, the new state's been wrote along and
and and positive review of it. So for the New York Times not to have mentioned it at all,
well, we all want to be reviewed by the New York Times because it's a it's a big and important
newspaper, but for them not to mention it at all all the new review of books not to mention it at all
The New Yorker all of these these outlets. I was disappointed by that just as I was extremely
Encouraged and pleased by the breadth of the reception in the United Kingdom
Well, it seems to me to be a reflection of exactly what you're writing about in the book
itself. I mean, you you traverse the history of the idea of meritocracy and the practice of
meritocracy, also contrasting it with forms of social organization that weren't meritocratic,
either implicitly or explicitly. And you you talk about the revolt against the idea of meritocracy,
especially on the left and the increasing potency,
let's say politically and psychologically of that,
rebellion.
You know, interestingly enough, also pointing out
that at least at certain times in the 20th century,
the meritocratic idea was fundamentally progressive,
and maybe it was in its essence.
So maybe I'd like to know from you,
you did your thesis, your doctoral thesis,
on measuring the mind, the history of that.
And this has been a concern of yours
for an extraordinary long time.
And I'd like to know what's at the bottom of that.
And sure.
I wrote, I did a D-Fill in history at Oxford University, and my D-Fill was on the history
of IQ testing, and particularly the way the history of IQ testing, the way that IQ testing
shaped educational policy, because we had something called the 11-plus examination in Britain,
which all people in the state sector had to sit, and which determined whether they went
to grammar schools or secondary
modern schools, I elites academic schools or non elite schools and which was essentially an IQ test or
a set of IQ test. It's an extraordinary example of the massive public impact of a set of ideas
about what constitutes mental ability and how you test that mental ability. So I was
interested in that partly because I was myself a product of a grammar school and I went to Oxford
having been to a grammar school. My entire educational career was determined by sitting this
examination at the age of 11 and passing this examination and passing subsequent examinations.
So it was sort of a personal thing to me,
but it also struck me as a very just thing that somebody from my background,
which is a very ordinary background, could go to a really first-rate academic school
and get an education that was comparable to people like Boris Johnson,
people who went to Eden or Winchester.
And so it all struck me that this examination, this web organizing educational
opportunity was a very intriguing thing.
It was something that was immersive of the status quo, which was embodied in my
mind by the private schools, the independent schools, and then the labor
government, which I naturally sort of gravitated towards and supported, came along and destroyed the grammar schools, abolished
them in the name of comprehensive schools and in the name of getting rid of testing and selection
streaming and things like that. And it struck me as a young person. This was an extraordinary thing
for a supposedly progressive party to be doing.
And it disillusioned me with the first thing, many other things did subsequently, but it's the
first thing that really disillusioned me with the socialist or the or the labor project. So I got
interested in the history of how this came to be, how the 11 plus came to reshape education in
Britain and how and how and how these ideas were
at first accepted and then rejected. And I discovered, I think, that most people in
the history faculty at Oxford, which was a fairly conventional conservative faculty,
thought I was completely mad to be looking at this subject. And I found myself in the
strange position of being somebody who was looking at an unconventional
subject, not political history or constitutional history, which was an unconventional subject,
which would have put me in the camp of some sort of deranged lefty, but actually from quite a
conservative direction, because I thought that dismantling the 11 plus and dismantling the
grammaticals was a terrible thing. So I would say
intellectually quite homeless, but actually being intellectually homeless, I think,
is quite appropriate to somebody who's interested in meritocracy, which ultimately, I think,
is an idea which in political terms tends to be intellectually homeless.
So you do point out in the book, you're the phrase in your book, you say cruel meritocracy,
cruelty, meritocracy, I believe, and you are referring there, despite the fact that you
were a beneficiary of the 11-plus system, that the test, like it's a really sharp fork
in the road, and perhaps it's too sharp a fork in the road in some sense to be palatable.
And then I suppose the people who have dismantled those systems would object to your support for that system by saying,
well, it allowed you through, and that was good for you, but there was all those other people who were arbitrarily denied the possibility of advancement. And I
think the weak part of that argument is the idea that it's arbitrary, right? That's the
crux of the matter. What exactly does arbitrary mean? And you might also say that cruel as these
examinations were, they were perhaps less cruel than what they prevented.
Absolutely. So I wouldn't advocate for a return to the 11 plus.
I think it was a system which was too much
a matter of dividing people into sheep and goats.
It was two ones and four all.
I think you have to have some sort of recourse
to what happens if people have a bad day.
And I would want a system in which you have a very agitated set of selective schools, lots of second chances, lots of different types
of schools. But I think there's a distinction between sort of a system which is short, sharp
and therefore obviously cruel and a system which is very prolonged
seems to be very kind and actually ends up being quite cruel. And I would say that what we've
done is replace a system whereby you have, you know, a one-off test which can benefit a large
number of poorer people with a system of very prolonged educational selection, which over a long period of time tends to be very biased
towards people who have the resources
to keep going through the system.
So under the 11 plus, you have a number of people
who would be selected at 11,
would get a very good academic education,
would get free educations at Oxford Cambridge
or whatever university they went to,
and then would go on to the fast stream of the civil service. Now, where you have a much more prolonged system, it's easier for
people who don't have a lot of resources to be weeded out or to drop out. And so, you know, it costs
a lot of money to go to university, it costs a lot of money to go to graduate school by prolonging
the process of selection. It looks kinder on the surface,
but deep down it can be a system which is much more socially biased towards richer people,
rather than people who might be deserving on the basis of their innate.
You see the same conundrum emerging to some degree with the use of statistically valid and reliable tests to do selection in the workplace.
Yes.
I mean, they have an error, so some people are going to be forbidden advancement
as a consequence of that test because of error.
But, and that's obviously unfortunate, and it's particularly unfortunate for them.
And that's obviously unfortunate, and it's particularly unfortunate for them.
But placing someone in a position
where the probability that they'll succeed over time
is extremely low and then tormenting them to death
over a one year period while they failed dreadfully.
And also burdening the company, let's say,
with the fact of dealing with someone
in a management position
for the sake of argument who actually isn't competent to do that, doesn't strike me
as a particularly just or empathic solution.
And part of the problem here is that, and this is, I think, part of the problem that we're
facing as a society in general with the use of, let's say, intelligence tests, intelligence tests
is they are the most powerful technology
that's research psychologists have ever invented
by a large margin.
And so if we equated them in some metaphoric sense
to surgery, we might say, well, you don't want,
surgery might be necessary,
but you don't wanna do it without a anesthetic.
And you also wanna be aware that the scalpel can kill.
And so I think partly what we're wrestling with is among many other things is the fact
that these tests are of incredible power in terms of their predictive ability and we're
not exactly sure what to do with that.
I mean, when I started familiarizing myself with the IQ literature, it was actually quite
disheartening in some sense because I started to understand just how broad the ability range among human beings is, and how
intractable that is in some measures in the lower, let's say, 10th. So one stat I came across at one point, and you detailed the use of IQ tests by the American military. They were picked
up very rapidly by the military and very successfully, and with many positive social consequences.
But you know, the American military decided, I believe all three branches, and I believe
this was in the 1980s, that it was illegal. It's now illegal in the US to induct someone
to the armed forces if they have an IQ of less than 82.
And that's 10% approximately, 10% of the population.
And that is a dismal statistic because the military is chronically hungry for people.
And if their conclusion after close to 100 years of IQ testing was that 10% of the population can't be trained to do anything of any utility in the
military. That has, well, that speaks for itself, if you think it through. And so it's no wonder people
are leery of these tests, and they're leery of what they reveal. And the easy thing to say is,
well, what they reveal isn't true. You know, it's the tests themselves. But I'm afraid I couldn't swallow that. I spent 10 years
looking at the IQ literature.
Well, when we talk about the military, there are two big questions. One is the First World
War, when a lot of the IQ testing was fairly crude and when they had this, a lot of literature
which came out of the First World War was quite racist.
And I think Bingham for one recanted on what he'd said in 1930, he said,
and then we were wrong.
It was a premature application of our methods.
We should have been more sensitive about cultural differences and linguistic abilities,
because you have a huge population of new immigrants.
After the Second World War, I think it was a much more
developed sign. The most important thing it revealed in both Britain, but most specifically
in America, was the huge amount of talent that was in the population that was being under
utelite. Right. And so out of that comes the GI Bill, because people are saying, gosh,
there are all these clever people.
We're a technical, scientific civilization.
We must use them.
We must promote them.
So I think there's a big difference on the impact
of the two things.
But these two questions that you raise.
One is the accuracy of the tests.
But the other is whether they're accurate or not.
But the other is, if they are accurate,
what they reveal about the human
population, and particularly the sheer range of abilities within the human population,
and so which is very wide.
And so the person who invented the term meritocracy was Michael Young, who wrote this wonderful magnificent
sort of really clever book in 1958 called The Rise of
the Maritocracy. And what he was saying in that book was that the problem with meritocracy,
the problem with IQ tests, is that they work and the meritocracy works. The general
tenor on the left at that time was these tests were inaccurate. They were missing children of
ability. They were allocating positions arbitrarily.
Michael Young says, no, no, no, no, the real problem is that they work, that they're accurate.
But the sort of society that you create by selecting people and promoting people on the basis of
ability is the opposite of socialism. He was a socialist. He was one of the authors of the
Labour manifesto of 1945. He says he didn't like the sort of society
that was being created by the use of these tests,
precisely because it promoted people by ability.
And it revealed very wide differences in people's capacity
to do things.
And he wanted to do things.
Yeah, that is a pain for the classes.
That is a painful thing.
Well, that is a pain for anyone psychologically and socially.
But, you know, the rub is always, yeah, yeah, compared to what exactly?
Oh, well, compared to my hypothetical utopia.
It's like, no, no, your hypothetical utopia is very low resolution and impractical.
And if you implemented it, it wouldn't turn out the way you think it is.
Think it would.
So we're not going to go there.
How about compared to other real things? And you do that in your
book, in your recent book, right? You walk through other forms of social organization.
You talk about diagnostic organizations. You talk about aristocratic organizations that
are based, well, that were based, let's say, mostly on the possession of land and that
tended to be hereditary. And so they were unbelievably stratified and also completely immobile.
And so you can dream up a non-stratified society, but maybe you could comment on this too.
I found out late in my life the existence of the Pareto distribution and the Matthew Principle.
It's quite common among economists.
I mean, we tended to think in psychology
that everything was normally distributed.
But there's lots of things that aren't.
When I developed a test called the Creative Achievement Test,
which is widely used psychometrically now,
and when we first administered it to hundreds of people,
and it was basically, it's a test that sums the number
of creative achievements you've
concretely made in 13 different creative realms.
Well, it was wildly perito distributed.
The median score was zero across 13 dimensions.
Right.
But the world people who had scores of 80, you know, they were way out on the tails.
And we could even utilize the test.
It was hard to utilize the test statistically
because it didn't conform to the normal distribution
assumptions that underlie, well, by Q-testing, for example.
And that's when I started to become
aware of the Pareto distribution.
And the Pareto distribution be devils every society.
And so you get stratification.
And so these people who are objecting to the meritocracy, okay, well, are they objecting
to stratification?
And I'd say yes.
And so, okay, well, what's the solution to that?
Well, then it turns into something like, well, it's capitalism's fault, which is non-believably
shallow analysis.
And that's why I liked your historical approach as well.
What I tried to do in my book was to look at the history
of meritocracy and treat as a historical problem rather than
just as a philosophical problem or a legal problem.
Because what I wanted to show is that if you look,
meritocracy is a relatively recent thing,
and it's an extremely radical thing.
And if you look at the history of previous societies,
most previous societies have been based on principles other than merit.
Because there is an argument that says,
of course, we all believe in meritocracy,
it's a natural way of doing things.
And what's the point of it,
what's the point of discussing it, everybody believes it.
In fact, for most of human history,
societies have not been organised according to the principle of meritocracy.
They've been organized according to the principle
of the inheritance of positions from father to son.
So, so dinnest is, they've been organized
according to the principle of ascription,
whereby the position that you have in society
is one that you inherit and one that in some how is regarded
as natural, the world is naturally organized into hierarchies.
Shakespeare talks about a great deal about how people should
reconcile to themselves, their position in society.
Because if they try and change it,
it will cause some terrible problem,
almost a psychic problem or a natural order of thinking,
I'm chewing that string and what you know, what discord follows is,
you see in Trojanism and Crescita.
And also, so you have a notion that a static society
is a good society, a hierarchical society is a good society
that power and position and property should flow
through families and, you know,
and dynasties that should root well. And also, you get the question
of how in such a society do you allocate positions? Well, there are actually very significant
answers to that. One is that you give them away as patronage. Another is that you buy
them and sell them. So there was a huge market in jobs in these pre-marriage
ocratic societies that you know you would buy a job in the civil service or
you would buy a job as a tax collector. France was a particularly extreme
example of this but most pre-modern societies you know had a market in jobs.
Jobs were regarded as property and one of the most the things that didn't exist
in that world was a notion
that there is a precise relationship between having a job and your ability to perform that job.
So I quote the example in the book of a woman called Margaret Scott who was the wet nurse
to the Prince of Wales. In 1783 she was given a pension of £200 a year. And £200
a year in those days was a great deal of money, but it was also a great deal of money when
you consider the fact that the Prince of Wales was 23 years old at the time and so probably
not in need of a wetness. But you know, there just isn't a notion that a job is something you do that you need to be qualified for
That is a set of commitments to your employer
So let's let's take it
Let's take that apart for a minute because
Partly what you're pointing to is that the idea of meritocracy is so deeply rooted in our culture that we assume that its existence is something
akin to a natural fact.
It's not a natural fact, and it's a fragile fact.
It's something that we can lose very easily if we do the wrong things.
So that's why I spend so much time talking about history, because what I want to prove
in this book is that something that was created historically and could be destroyed historically.
We could move towards a non-meritocratic society, which is what worries me.
So we assume now, I think, that if I have a job, my job, it doesn't really matter what
the job is, is to produce something productive that other people value in as efficient a manner
as possible at a cost that's less than what I'm paid.
Right, and all of those assumptions are questionable.
Absolutely.
They're not natural kinds, which is partly what you're pointing out.
And then, okay, so we'll accept that.
Let's go to the other side of this for a minute. So part of the problem, I think, is terminology.
It's part of what makes people resistant to this.
Because we also tend to sort of casually talk about elite institutions, which implies
a kind of moral valuing.
We talk about meritocracy, which implies that the people at the top are of greater merit,
right?
And that means, to the degree that that meritocracy
is established on the basis of, let's say, fluid intelligence,
that we're conflating moral worth
with abstract intellectual ability.
And that's really a catastrophe.
And that's part of the pride of intellect.
And you talked about the best and the brightest.
And one of the criticisms that that book leveled
against the meritocracy was precisely one
of intellectual pretension and arrogance.
It's just because your smart doesn't mean you're good.
It doesn't mean you're wise.
It doesn't mean you're meritorious.
It doesn't even necessarily mean
that the decisions you make are going to be better
than decisions that other people would make using other means.
Now, it's complicated because as you point out in the book, it's quite likely if you're
in the top, let's say, 10th of the IQ distribution and you start poor, that you won't end up poor.
Right.
Right.
And so I believe I read a paper at one point that suggested that you were much better off
in the United States.
If you were born in the top quartile of IQ, then if you were born in the top quartile of
wealth, if you had to pick at birth.
Yes.
I think that's the answer.
Yes.
I think this is...
So British evidence of the same thing, the same thing.
Yeah.
And I do have some sympathy.
I mean, one of the things I've been trying to
sort out in my own mind is the conceptual inadequacy of both the left and the right when it comes to
profound individual differences in ability. So I had a client at one point who had an IQ of under 80
and he couldn't read well. He collected a lot of books because he was a bit obsessive,
but he couldn't read. And I spent about 30 hours training him to fold a piece of paper, a letter
into three equal segments so that it could be put effectively into an envelope with enough accuracy,
though a multitude of such envelopes would actually pass through an envelope sorting machine. And it was something I could do without thinking. And he couldn't really do it
after 30 hours of training. And so I struggled for about a year and a half to find him a volunteer
job. And it turns out, you know, volunteer jobs are actually harder to get in many ways than
paying jobs now because there's so many police checks and that sort of thing you have to
go through and they're very technically challenging.
And I sent him to a government agency that was hypothetically designed to help people
like him find a job.
And they said, you know, type up your resume and send it out.
It's like, well, he can't type and he doesn't have a resume and he can't use a computer.
And that's not helpful
Thank you very much. You have no idea what you're dealing with here. And so
This 10% of the population let's say the liberals think you can train anyone to do anything
Which is rubbish and the conservatives think if you work hard enough, there's no obstacles to your success and that's also
rubbish in some situations because hard work alone isn't
going to do it. And so we have a real conundrum. Now what we're doing right now, I think, is
shooting the messenger. It's like, we don't want to hear this. So we'll get rid of tests
that are valid and reliable. So, you know, the heart of my de-filthesis, and also to some
extent of the heart of this new book, The Aristocracy of Talent,
is this group of psychologists who emerge in the late 19th century and become very dominant in
the 20th century up to the 1960s, who are psychometricians who are concerned with the psychology of individual
differences, measuring individual differences. And what I would say that those people are essentially is bell curve liberals.
They believe in the bell curve, they believe in the normal distribution, they believe that the
range of individual differences is very wide, but they say that those natural facts about the world
lead one to liberal conclusions. They need, to be leaving in a more active state,
a more child-centered set of educational policies,
and a more redistributive tax system as well.
So in Britain, where I think
Belfast liberalism is particularly dominant,
they would all be members of the Labour Party,
or at the very least of the Liberal Party, they would have all voted in 1945 for the Labour Party,
they believe that the very fact that people have wide ranges of individual ability means that you
have to have an active and generous welfare state, because it's not their fault that they're not
very bright, it's not their fault that they're not very bright,
it's not their fault that the bottom society
that they can't look after themselves.
So they need to be, as it were,
looked after through a pension system,
through a system of redistributive taxation, as I say,
through supplements to that.
Well, you're making a case-thirity,
that's an interesting case, because you're actually making the case that it is the observation
of genuine and profound differences in people's ability that are fundamental and maybe not
even easily changed by social policy that actually justifies the redistributive welfare state
at a moral level.
Right.
And so that's something for people who oppose the idea of meritocracy to really think about for a while.
Well, I mean, John Rawls, actually, you know, it's central to the history of justice that you should have redistributed.
I mean, he general is very interesting, as a, as a leftist, as also a sort of genetic determinist.
He says that people don't own their talents, they inherit their talents.
And so if they're born very bright, it's not because they're morally superior,
it's because they have to be lucky.
If they're born not so bright, it's because they have to be unlucky.
And therefore society has an obligation to redistribute resources from the lucky to the unlucky.
I think that's a weak philosophical argument in some sense,
because I think you could just as easily say,
if that is the case, those a priori presumptions
about the distribution of talent,
it is in everyone's best interests,
regardless of the causes of the differences in ability
to radically incentivize those who can,
so they will produce as much as they can
for the rest of us who can't.
And so what is interesting about it is that there
is a liberal case for redistribution based
on the idea of inheritance of people's inherited IQ.
And I think that was the dominant position on the left.
So we've got a whole bunch.
Let's say JBS Hall Day Day in who is a sort of
Marxist, who is the sort of editor of the daily worker, which was the Communist Party magazine.
He was also a biologist. He wrote this book, I haven't had it on my shelves here,
in 1932 called The Inequality of Man. And it's all about, you know, if we have,
if we know that people are unequal, what do we do about
this? And he thought that what you do about it is have a bigger, more active, more enlightened
enlightened state. And something happened in the 1960s, roughly in the 1960s, whereby this notion
became forbidden on the left. The left became not only more egalitarian rather than meritocratic,
but it also became committed to a blank slate theory of the world. And that anything that became not only more egalitarian rather than meritocratic,
but it also became committed to a blank slate theory
of the world.
And that anything that questioned a blank slate theory
of the world was associating with the right.
Okay, so let me ask you some questions about that.
I see the malevolent side of the insistence politically
on blank slate as justifying the utopian
pretensions of those who would like to remake man in the image of their political ideology.
And if the blank slate argument is true, then we could be anything that those who would
like to change this could make us into.
And why not?
And so that bothers me.
I also think it's unbelievably by naive both biologically
and psychologically.
It's clearly not the case.
There isn't a deep psychological,
biologically minded psychological thinker
who adheres to anything like a blank slate theory.
Even the behaviors have completely abandoned that notion.
And they probably did the most rigorous job
of attempting to test its validity. And then with regards to the rejection on the left, let's say, part
of that was a consequence of persistent ethnic differences in IQ testing. And that's proved
something, well, that's a no one knows what to do with that.
Now I read some recent work showing that the ethnic differences and racial differences
that pop up in the IQ literature are much less evident at the age of five and increase
over time.
That's quite interesting because it does indicate that perhaps there's an educational
deviation that's occurring that's at least
at least in part at the basis of this, but it's proved a very thorny and intractable problem
with endless social consequences, particularly in the US.
And we don't know what to do with that, I would say.
And the easy answer is to say, well, the tests themselves are biased, but then you're stuck
with, well, what are you going to use instead and And what do you mean biased and compared to what exactly?
Yeah, on the ethnic differences, the group differences.
I mean, of course, these are differences between group averages.
And that, you know, there is an incredibly wide range of talents and abilities within groups,
differences within groups are much bigger than average differences between groups evidently.
But it is a very American set of data.
And I think that what we're seeing in Britain
at the moment, which is very interesting, I think,
is that we've had a series of schools
which are called academies,
which are a bit like American magnet schools,
but they're schools that can select people at the age of 16,
once they've done their O levels when they're going to A levels.
There's a lot of them in the East End of London,
in poorer parts of other cities.
And we found that these schools, which have been very academically rigorous,
very focused on achievement, have been designed to say that
if you've got a poor population,
what you need to do to it is to give it opportunity and give it rigor rather than sort of dumb down
education. And these schools have been extremely good at getting members of ethnic minorities into
high quality universities. So there's one called Brampton Manor Academy in the East End of London,
which has an ethnic minority dominant population, which has the majority of its students have
free school meals, which is a measure of poverty, and they now get as many or more children
every year into Oxbridge than Eaton does.
So, and again, you have, you know, in the United States. 5% or total number.
In total number.
So, in fact, by percent, I think that would have been,
would be better because Eaton's a very big school.
So, these schools have been doing amazingly well
and they've surprised everybody
by how successful they've been.
So, there is a lot of drive in poor ethnic minority population.
And what we're finding in Britain is that the people who are doing worse,
white working class children, particularly white working class boys,
and they're being surpassed in education by African-Americans, West Indians,
and obviously oriental Chinese, I think,
minorities, which have traditionally done very well.
So it's a different, it's a bit of a different picture
from the United States.
So okay, so what do you think is going on
with the white working class in England?
The white working class in England is,
it's partly that they're living in areas
where opportunities don't abound.
They're living in the north of England,
they're living in areas.
These were people who were part of the industrial working class
and we had a massive deindustrialization,
particularly from the 1980s onwards.
So they're in left behind areas which you've seen
their industries destroyed. So that is a depressing thing and I think that's limited their ambitions.
It's certainly limited their access to good schools and ambitious teachers. And I think
also you have a culture which tells them that they're bad people or that we have a culture that celebrates
almost every group in society, apart from the white working classes.
Yes, particularly, well, I've seen the conflation of ambition and achievement with power and domination
in that sort of messaging, right? And those things shouldn't be conflated.
It's very disheartening, I think
particularly for boys and girls, even if they're poor, still have the message that's sent
pretty strong by our culture that, well, whatever a girl wants to accomplish and achieve, that's
to be celebrated, there's no fear of patriarchal power lurking underneath that, let's say.
And so, yeah, I think it's dangerous to underestimate
the demoralizing effect that that kind of language
and messaging that's constantly applied actually has.
Yeah, so we, you know, we, and like the United States,
about 60% of people in universities now,
are women.
And the people at the very,
people who've got the least opportunities, I would
say, are probably the children, the male children of white working class people living in areas
like Stoke or Newcastle who've seen industrial jobs disappearing, but still have this conception
that men must be people who
sort of make things or do things and it shouldn't be sitting behind desks or being involved
in the caring professions or something like that.
And those are the people I think who really are stuck with that, they don't have role models
and they don't have a general sense of where they fit into the post-industrial hierarchy.
Yeah, well, the attitude that men are people
who do things with their hands
is a perfectly useful attitude in industrial society
when you're in the lower strut of the population
because that's exactly what the case is.
And there's plenty of honor in that as well.
And so it's not easy for that to be replaced
when that was the basis of productive effort itself
and of success.
So why do you think that your book has been positively
received all things considered in the UK?
Is the assault on the meritocracy, let's say,
or the conflation of the idea of intellectual prowess
with merit maybe, is that not as contentious
an issue in general in the UK?
Now, we have a lot of the currents that you have
in the United States, but in a sort of week away
as a sort of echo chamber in the United States.
But we still have a memory, I think,
of the meritocracy as being something that was progressive
and something that was a cultural memory
of the meritocracy as being something that's progressive
and something that displaced the old aristocratic elite. And I think both the the new
Tories and the old Labour people can agree that you know the old aristocratic elite there's
something wrong with them. So we have we have a better memory of the failures of a pre-meritocratic society than you do in the United States, I think.
I think the situation in the United States is strange,
because one of the things that we're better at
at the moment in Britain is I think promoting social mobility
or doing something about social mobility. That, As I say, we've got the academy schools which are providing real opportunities for an excellent
education in the inner cities.
Oxford and Cambridge are doing something to reach out to a much broader strata of the population.
They're creating extra years where they take people from poor backgrounds and give them
an extra years where they take people from poor backgrounds and give them an extra years
education. So they're basically broadening the selection.
Without abandoning the principle of merit, I think exactly without abandoning the principle of
merits, they may be softening it to bits in some areas. But in the United States, you still have,
I mean, you're not in the United States,
I believe you're in Canada.
But in the past enough for now,
they still have legacies,
which exist, they still have athletic scholarships,
which they still have incredible advantages
for the children of faculty members.
And if you look at the social composition
of Harvard, it's an exceptionally elite institution, Plutocratic institution. Now people come from very, very rich backgrounds at Harvard. So I think America at the top of society
is doing less to revive the meritocratic spirit than we in Britain are doing.
And what it's doing instead, because it sort of feels some sort of vague guilt about the
fact that, you know, Harvard is a privilege.
Of course.
1920, Rich University, is they leap into workism as a sort of almost, as a sort of defense mechanism
to their guilt.
I happen to believe that a lot of this work is a sort of way in which the old, privileged,
white ruling class holds on to its position by preserving a certain, you know,
it's us plus certain selected members of the excluded classes. But yeah, well, I saw that often in my students,
who were of the radical left persuasion at elite institutions,
like Harvard, where I was there for seven years as a professor,
and then less so at the University of Toronto,
but it's a less elite and plutocratic institution
by large margin.
But it always grated on me to some degree because I thought, well, here you are at this institution,
so you are by definition already a member of the class of oppressors that you hypothetically
despise.
And the fact that you are here and accepted this and going through this means that you've
accepted it, and now you want to be on the side of the oppressed, and you want to have all the advantages of
the hypothetical oppressor simultaneously, seems a bit much to ask for, right, to be a victim
and an oppressor at the same time. Yeah. Well, I think we should all start with the question of
what are you personally willing to give up, But still, I mean, so what,
I think one of my worries about abandoning
the meritocratic principle,
I think that as I said,
the meritocratic principle is something that's fragile.
It's something that was created
relatively recently in history.
It's something that can be destroyed.
And once you start making exceptions,
so we'll make an exception for the children
of faculty members, we'll make an exception for alumni,
we'll make an exception for people who give us a lot of money,
we'll make an exception for people who were born
into certain groups of the population,
we'll accept the marriage of credit principle. Ultimately, you end up completely destroying the marriage of credit principal, but you also
end up reintroducing the idea that people should be judged as members of groups.
And the fundamental thing about the marriage of credit principal is you judge people as
individuals, not as members of groups.
And as soon as you begin to reintroduce this collective principle
judging people by members of groups, then you have a different principle on the basis.
Okay, so, and so, so, are there advantages, do you think, to classifying people by group?
If we played devil's advocate? Because that's, I see that exactly the same thing happening.
There's this insistence that immutable group identity
should trump individual merit.
And then there's a deeper criticism, which is,
and the deepest criticism, in some sense,
is your understanding of merit, your conception of merit.
And I'm speaking of you personally,
as an advocate of this position,
is nothing but a reflection of your unreflected demand, say, to justify your position as a
beneficiary of the 11th system, and also to justify the privilege you have as a member of your
particular ethnicity and background. That's Foucault's criticism, right? Of virtually everything.
Well, let me answer the two questions.
And I think you probably weren't to agree with my first answer.
But I think that there are certain groups of people who by
didn't of their history do deserve to be treated as groups who've
been collectively wronged. And this is a, you know, I've been a long-term opponent
of the affirmative action.
I've now come around to seeing its merits
because I think the African American population
in the United States, because of the legacy of slavery,
because of the legacy of Jim Crow,
and because redlining and segregation by residents
lasted for such a long time in the United States,
there is a case for affirmative action, for reaching out positively to look for talent,
to look for potential and making an incredibly hard effort to do that as a way of making up for historical wrongs, but historical wrongs which continue to limit opportunities. But I would say
what I do not accept as a conclusion from that is that you can just do it by numbers,
hitting number targets. You can't just take them into the universities and just you know,
hit your quotas and then not doing anything about it. It should be part of a very broad
policy of affirmative education, not just affirmative action, but affirmative education.
As I say, what they're doing in Oxford now is giving people who've come from historically
under privileged backgrounds and giving them a foundation year, spending a whole year
making sure that they get up to standard so that they can compete with people who've come privileged backgrounds and giving them a foundation year, spending a whole year making
sure that they get up to standards so that they can compete with people who've come from
from from from being through a more rigorous educational system. And I think one of the
many problems with affirmative action in America is that they've tended to accept people
and then just let them do what they do. And quite often that means, you know, either dropping
out or moving to courses that are that are that that's a that's a that's a that's a that's a less than or or
Jerry mandering the standards themselves.
So I'm going to press you on that a little bit.
You did point out just before we had this last bit of conversation that the danger in the elite institutions in the US in particular are the exceptions to
the meritocratic principle, right?
And so how do you reconcile the desire that you just expressed to in certain cases to
redress historical wrongs with the problem of exception to the fundamental merit, merit individualistic meritocratic rule.
Because you know, it's, that's a typical conservative
objection in some sense.
It's like, yeah, yeah, that's your exception, you know,
but then so there's gonna be 10 other people that have
slightly different case to make for exceptions
and then we're back to the same problem.
So we should just stick to the damn harsh 11
that's an actual cutoff, right?
Despite the fact that it causes a certain amount of trouble,
because there isn't a better solution.
Sure. Absolutely.
As I said, I came to this position reluctantly because, you know,
it's, it's an inconsistent position, but I also think it's a pragmatic position.
I think that the, the injustice involved with slavery was of such a different order
that we need to make
recompense for it. The society in general has to make
recompense for it, and it continues to shape the opportunities
of Black Americans, but I would not extend that principle,
let's say, to recent immigrants who, by the very fact that they've
immigrated to the United States, have massively improved their life chances. I'd like to keep it limited to essentially the descendants
of slaves. And also, I would like to say that it's something that should be time limited.
It's something that we want to get beyond. We want to get beyond beyond it and to a world
in which we can begin to judge people purely
on the basis as individuals. What that time frame would be, I'm not sure, but it seems
needs to be something that's ended. And that's why I think there's a really important distinction
between affirmative action and the talk now of diversity. This diversity is based on very different philosophy
from affirmative action.
The philosophy of affirmative action
is we did something bad and we've got to make up for it.
The philosophy of diversity.
Within the confines of a myritor-cratic system.
Yes, within the confines of a myritor-cratic system,
we were actively searching for talents
and we have to actively search for talents
in certain populations much
more than we do in other populations because of their history.
Now the logic of diversity is very different from that because the argument of diversity
from the back case was that diversity is a good in itself and you have to judge people
as members of groups because it's by mixing those members of groups because different groups
have different characteristics that you produce better educational outcomes.
Now, that's, there's no evidence for that.
That's wrong, technically wrong.
Well, it's partly wrong because, look, we could talk about one of the arguments you lay
out in your book that certain psychologists, and they tend to be educational psychologists, have levied against strict meritocratic tests like those that are fundamentally IQ tests.
So that would be the SAT, the GRE, all everything that's used for entrance into undergraduate
universities where that's used in graduate school, professional schools.
That's all IQ testing, essentially, and people will say it's not, but that's because they
don't know what they're talking about.
Okay, so then you might say,
well, IQ is pretty singular.
And it's pretty good predictor of long term success
in a cognitively complex society.
But there are other sources of variance, possibly.
So you get thinkers like Robert Sternberg,
for example, who talked about practical intelligence
and the multiple intelligence theorist,
Howard Gardner, and both of whose scientific work I think is shoddy beyond comprehension
and a terrible answer to a problem that's been answered actually quite nicely, psychometrically.
We know there are other sources of variability.
There's variability in temperament, five dimensions.
That's a lot, five dimensions. And I don't think that's a biased finding,
and it was agnostic theoretically.
It emerged out of pure brute force statistics.
That's where the diversity lies,
and there is not a lot of racial difference in temperament.
So the idea that group membership
produces diversity of a sort that would actually broaden the human scope of any discussion, any corporation, et cetera, et cetera, is just wrong.
There's no evidence for it whatsoever, and it's even worse than that because it makes the presumption that the essential source of diversity is, in fact, ethnicity and race, and that can go wrong very badly.
But the diversity argument is a much more profound threat to a marriage to credit society
than the affirmative action argument, because the diversity has no possible time limit,
and it's fundamentally opposed to individualism.
It's fundamentally illiberal because it says that group membership is fundamental to our
identities.
And you must judge people, at least partly, if not primarily, on the basis of group identity.
But I wanted to go back to your point about Foucault, which I think is a very interesting
point.
And I think one which is absolutely refuted by history, because
one of the arguments that the critics of meritocracy make is that meritocracy is basically propaganda
for plutocrats or it's propaganda for the ruling elite. The ruling elite chooses people
according to its own criteria. It invents those criteria. Essentially the criteria of the capitalist
class or the ruling class and only people who fit those criteria will be're essentially the criteria of the capitalist class or the ruling class,
and only people who fit those criteria will be selected. So it's purely socially constructed.
Yeah, on the basis of the drive to power, of the drive to power, but I would say that
actually something very different is going on, and that's why the history really matters
here, is that merit meritocracy is a prometionan concept or it's a it's a it's a
mutable concept that actually has its own internal logic. So if you look at
Britain as an example of this in the middle of the 19th century a group of
educated bourgeois men the intellectual aristocracy decided that they wanted
to take power from the land of the elite and they said that they wanted that they would do people like them, Thomas McCauley,
people with names like like like like like Huxley and and and hold there in and all and
canes and these people wanted to and Stephen wanted to have power and so they said what
they needed to do was to have open competition for jobs in the civil
service, Oxbridge fellowships and the rest, and open competition that was determined by your
ability to perform in examinations. So that, you could say, well, these are a bunch of people who
are advancing their power. They've vent these ideas to advance their power. But look at what
happens historically. First of all, you get women coming along and saying,
well, if my brother can get a fellowship of Trinity College
cramish by doing this exam, why can't I?
And indeed, if open competition means anything,
you can't just exclude women.
If examinations test objective ability,
you can't just say we'll only have them for half
of humanity.
So the very logic is self perpetuating.
So you do indeed get a bunch of very clever women who come along and knock on the door
of these institutions.
So I tell this story in my book of a woman called Philip Of Orset,
who in 1892 sits for the Cambridge Mathematics
Tripos, which is the hardest examination in the world.
And she comes top, she gets the best results,
she beats everybody.
But of course at that point,
women were actually officially allowed
to sit these examinations.
So she is classified as above the senior Wrangler. The senior Wrangler is number one, but she's
classified as above the senior Wrangler because she has taken on this system and beat it.
So there's then, then there's the working classes. You've got a whole bunch of people
who come from poor backgrounds, but a born very bright, who are born with a great
desire for knowledge. They come along and they knock on the door of the civil service
and they knock on the door of Oxford and Cambridge and say, judge us by these standards and we'll
get into these universities and the same happens. You get something like W.E.B. Dubois in the
United States, you know, a black person who becomes the first, I think,
tenured professor at Harvard, registered magnificent book on the Philadelphia Negro,
writes this great stuff on the talented 10th, on the talented 10th of the population who
are going to drive progress in all populations. So what you're doing is not creating a system
whereby the ruling class can regulate who comes up and who doesn't, whereby
the ruling class defines what merit is, you have a system which, by its own logic of open
competition, of examinations, changes the nature of the ruling class. And I don't think any
of the people who set up the system in the first place imagined universities in which 60%
of the people going to them would be women,
imagined a system in which you'd have massive numbers of ethnic minority people
or of working class people going to go into universities.
So merit is not a conspiracy of the plutocratic elites.
Indeed, it's something which constantly reconfigures society
from the outside group coming in and getting ahead
as a result of the openness of competition.
Okay, so I want to hit hard at that argument because I've been trying to parse out in my
own mind exactly what it was that Foucault was doing.
And so one of the problems that has emerged since the 1960s is the problem of the realization of the complexity of perception.
So up until about the 1960s, it was more or less assumed that the world was just made out of objects in some simple way and that we saw those objects and then we thought about them and evaluated them and acted.
And that's just wrong. That isn't how it works at all. It's almost impossible to perceive a visual landscape.
We almost have, we have almost no idea how we do it.
It looks like you need an intelligence that's embodied in some sense and that can act in order to perceive.
So perception is extraordinarily tightly tied to action.
And there's almost an infinite number of interpretations of any given visual landscape.
And the same problem, be devils all other forms of perception.
That emerged in AI, and has be deviled robotics engineers ever since, which is why we don't
have robots zipping around doing everything that we could do.
And then it also emerged in literary criticism.
It's like, well, how many ways can a text be interpreted?
Well, innumerable ways.
Well, how do you know which of those ways is canonical?
Oh, we don't know how we know that.
Well, how do you know the whole canon is canonical then?
Because it's just a meta-text.
Well, we don't know that.
Well, how is it you understand a text given its innumerable interpretations?
We don't know that.
We don't know how we do that.
Well, maybe you just do it as part of your drive to power.
Yeah. Okay.
Premature answer to a very difficult question.
That's Foucault.
He essentially assumes that the will to power
is at the basis of categorization itself
and even at the basis of the process of categorization,
which isn't even a deeper criticism, right?
It's nothing but your drive to elevate yourself
in power hierarchies that governs
the process by which you categorize.
And even your justifications for that categorization.
Okay, I think that is the most cynical thing you can think.
And I don't say that lightly.
But it's not that easy to detail out what the alternative is. Now, you're pointing at it to some degree
with this issue of merit that transcends the power drive
of any particular group of people,
even those who might be pushing the idea of merit.
Well, there's something deep down in there.
Is what is it that's being facilitated,
that isn't the drive to power?
And we haven't got that conceptualized well.
The university, especially the humanities departments,
wouldn't have been so easily taken over
by the postmodernist types who insist upon
this kind of interpretation.
If the counter argument was well articulated.
Well, one of the problems with,
one of the problems with FUNCO, the many problems with FUNCO
is I'm not sure how it wouldn't go about disproving his claims because they're so all-encompassing and so,
so sort of mutually self-reinforcing. I don't know how one would say your interpretation
of text is not right.
Well, you did it with a historical example.
Right. Your claim is, I hope to do that, but I I would say that Fukuoka has a huge influence on the revolts against the meritocracy in the 1960s and 70s,
because he's basically saying that categories that we use to make distinctions between people, as you say, the products not of sense or organizational
necessity or convenience or efficiency, but of power. I happen to believe that the arguments
in favour of meritocracy can be made in terms both of social justice and in terms of economic efficiency. I think we can demonstrate
that meritocratic institutions and meritocratic countries and systems are more economically productive
that they have a higher, you know, a higher efficiency level of efficiency that productivity rates
are higher in such societies than in other societies. So just just dismiss it all as a mishmash of power plays, I think, you know, it can be subject to...
Well, I... Okay, so let's take that.
Let's take that as a starting point then, because at least in principle,
one of the things that the people who claim that those in power are doing
by imposing their category system is
Subjecting those who are deprived to a level of absolute deprivation that's so terrible that it's unjust and immoral
But if the counter claim is no you wait a minute when we make arguments on the basis of
individualistic Maritocracy and the net consequence of that is that although there's still a fair degree of income disparity, that
the bottom gets lifted up far enough so that absolute privation, let's say of the sort
that defines starvation, just to take an example, no longer exists, that you interfere with
that at your peril, even if you're on the left, and you actually care for the poor and dispossessed.
Absolutely. I believe that I can demonstrate quite clearly that meritocratic societies
have high levels of productivity. If you take a family company, or you take family
companies in general as a category, and compare them with public companies that will appoint
people primarily on merit, you will see that public companies are more productive, that they grow
faster, that they're better at turning inputs into outputs than family companies. Family
companies have a much bigger variance of performance, but the average performance of public
companies. If you take countries that are pretty meritocratic, they will have a higher growth
rates than countries that aren't meritocratic. So let's take Singapore, which is in many ways the most meritocratic country in the world, it's growth rate, which has
been extraordinary, has been powered by its use of human capital, by its meritocracy compare.
Singapore was Sri Lanka, which in 96 to their on comparable income levels, I think Sri Lanka
was a bit richer. Singapore, by focusing
relentlessly on meritocracy, has pulled ahead or take to it. And you think the data linking meritocracy
per se and the stringent meritocracy in Singapore to that economic advancement. I think you can collect
data on this. So another example would be if you take Sweden,
or any of the North European countries
and compare them with Greece and Italy,
Greece and Italy being nepotistic
or familial in their organization
and much more dominated by family companies
and much more dominated by informal, familial arrangements,
they have got lower growth than
Sweden, and also the rate of growth in Italy has been slowing down recently as they've moved towards
you know, as the effect of high technology has begun to kick in. So the growth rate in Italy,
which was quite far staffed at the Second World War,
as economists are becoming more advanced, is beginning to slow down because of familial
nepotistic organisation, just is proving to be incompatible with an IT-based society.
And there's plenty of economists, Luigi Stingal, is at the University of Chicago, primarily, who've done work showing that meritocracy,
using big data sets on how companies select people
on how open the educational system is on how much corruption
there is, that meritocratically organized societies
have higher growth rates.
Well, there's a very, very well-developed
psychometric literature in management psychology,
the actual science of management psychology.
There is a bit of that,
although most of management psychology is rubbish
and the same for most of leadership psychology,
but there's good data looking at difference
in individual productivity rates
across a multi-year period after hiring
depending on the method of selection and the best method is one that's
G-loaded, the second best method is one that assess conscientiousness, big five
conscientiousness, the best test combination is a combination of those two, a
weighted combination of those two, and it predicts individual productivity at
about 0.6, which is staggeringly high for bi-cycometrics standards,
by the standards of such things.
And that doubt is very, very well developed
by I think the best psychometricians and statisticians
that are working in psychology.
And, you know, if you're a social scientist and you say,
well, those things aren't believable, I would say,
I defy you to find anything social scientists have ever demonstrated
using any methods other than those methods
that show results more than one-third is great.
So if you throw out all that, you throw out everything.
It's the same methods.
But so if we accept that economic growth is a good thing
and improvements in productivity are good things
because they make the life of the average person better
as well as the life of successful entrepreneurs better.
I think the consequences of this,
which I was just saying, which can be demonstrated
are extremely big.
And this is what leads me to the biggest worry in my book.
And that is that we live in
a world that doesn't just consist of the West, we live in a world in which you're getting
the biggest and most serious challenge to Western dominance that we've seen ever, which
is coming from China. And that if we are seeing at the moment meritocracy being abandoned
in various ways in the United States, at a
time when I believe that China is becoming more like Singapore and taking meritocracy much
more seriously, both in terms of its educational system, which is very, very competitive in
terms of its university system, which is both highly selective and growing all the time.
And the way that the Communist Party operates, and I think it does set itself,
the form and standards and even promotes people
on the basis of examinations.
If we have America becoming less meritocratic
or less enthusiastic about meritocracy
and China becoming more meritocratic
or at least more enthusiastic about meritocracy,
that presents the possibility of a future
in which China really pulls ahead
of the United States.
You know, I think, except there are lots of objections to this.
China has massive levels of corruption, it has the red princes, it has enormous inefficiencies
and internally inequality and the rest of it.
But imagine if I'm right, imagine if China really is slowly slouching towards being a Singapore,
but with 1.4 billion people.
Yeah, not so slowly.
You know, not so slowly.
Yeah, I mean, that has massive implications for the future.
And what is America doing at the moment?
You've got gifted programs being abandoned.
You've got SATs being abandoned for University entrance. Boston
Latin, which has used to select people on the basis of examinations, is ceasing to
do so and is now accepting more people on the basis of Lotteries, the same with
Lowell High School in San Francisco. You've got these books like Michael Sandel and
Mark Vitzis book attacking the principle of meritocracy.
At the same time that you've got this sort of rather plutocratic iv league system.
So you're getting the ladder and then you've got the attacks on the elite schools in New
York.
So you've got the ladder being distrapled down on the one hand and you've got a sort of woke, blue-to-cratic elites on the one hand
enjoying the fruits of all this educational,
this vast dare is that the educational system has,
but on the other hand,
not really being willing to reach out,
which is what meritocracy should be about
to the most talented groups in the whole of society.
I think that means ultimately
that the American loses in China
wins, which is not something I want to say.
Well, I spent a lot of time in Silicon Valley and it's a very interesting place to be.
What you see there is an unbelievable concentration of unbelievably smart people. That's a merit-based
establishment and look what it's produced. It mean, it's absolutely stunning. It's absolutely remarkable.
It's singular in some sense.
And that's all a consequence of the,
because, I mean, you get merit-ocratic selection,
and that's one thing.
But then you get this multiplier effect
when you get people who have passed through that system
and they all get together.
And you've seen also the tremendous consequences
of exactly that for India, for example, because
the Indian Institute of Technology is incredibly selective and it's producing graduates who
are certainly the equal of MIT graduates, which is really saying something.
And so many of them, many of their best and brightest, went to Silicon Valley.
And what's happened is they dumped immense amounts of capital back into India and facilitated the development of a robust technological society there.
And so it's been to everyone's stunning benefit, assuming, as you said,
that economic growth and material prosperity are valuable.
And you know, you could critique that idea.
You could say, well, we should be more aesthetic.
We should, there are other values we should pursue
than material prosperity.
But I do not see that coming from the left.
What I see happening is an insistence
that the corrupt aspect of our current society
is the lack of material prosperity at the bottom
and simultaneous interference with the only process
we know of that has historically demonstrated
its ability to redress that. So what's going on? Like, why is that happened on the left?
Well, I just pick up on your point about MIT. MIT is now going through a big process of producing
a mission statement or a... Oh, God. Well, you know, do you know that 75 to the word merit from it?
They've excluded the word merit. That's MIT of all places. Yeah, of all places 75% of applicants to the UC system in the research science
streams are
rejected without consideration of their research
History on the basis of their diversity statements,
which is something introduced now to in Canada to get a grant at many of the federal agencies,
you now have to produce a diversity statement or some equivalent of that along with your
research proposal.
Yeah.
No, I think something very, if you go back against the late 19th century in the United States,
you had a ruling class that became
very worried about itself. It was very worried about the level of inequality, very worried
about plutocracy, very worried it was becoming European and no longer sort of American.
And what they did as a result of that was to construct a ladder of opportunity and throw that ladder down as deeply as possible.
You know, from Harvard down to the local village school, there's a sort of sense that we
must, we must draw all the talents from right across this great country.
Now, we have the similar phenomenon, which is the creation of a Pew-to-Critical
Leads, which is very divorced from the whole of society.
But instead of saying, well, we must create a ladder, we must make sure that the ladder
really works, we must get talent from everywhere we possibly can.
They're saying, well, what does talent mean?
Does it really exist?
Can you measure it?
Is it really a good thing or is it an instrument of ruling class power?
It's sort of a class bead games being played and very little that's being done
that will really increase the supply of real talents and some sources of talent
such as the Asian population deliberately being ignored.
And it's difficult not to conclude from that that you actually have
an old plutocratic elite that is in these very convoluted ways using won't language basically engage
in opportunity hoarding. They don't want to be displaced from these positions. So and
that's the net consequence of these sorts of actions.
Well, at least in the short term, we'll see what happens as those ideas propagate, because
they're deeply, especially the Foucault insistence, it's the thing that I think disturbs
me the most, the idea that at the basis of the active categorization itself is nothing
more than a totalitarian will to power.
That's a positively satanic vision of mankind
It truly is and what really frightens me about that is what it means for how you treat your enemies
Look, it's like you're just out for your power. That's it and me too
There's no place we can meet as civilized people between our power hierarchies that place doesn't even exist
And so what am I supposed to do with you if you oppose me?
If we can't come to an accord? Well, you don't have to think very long before you come up with a solution for that.
Well, that's why the meritocracy, the history of meritocracy is so fascinating,
because it moves in directions which we never designed.
It was never designed to do in the first place.
You know, once you set up the principle of open competition,
the groups that succeed,
that are coming up from submerged positions
in society are succeeding without any sort of plan.
And quite often against the will of the traditional
ruling elites, I guess I did the land
of the ruling elites completely displaced by this process.
So, and it comes because the system
of testing, examination,
open competition has its own internal logic,
which is totally different from what Foucault would say,
because all categories and all ideas
must be instruments of the powerful.
Yeah, all categories.
No matter what they are.
It's an unbelievably deep criticism.
And I think it was a reflection
of Foucault's character
itself, frankly speaking.
He's not someone I admire at all on the ethical front.
No.
No, I didn't think I think that's right.
But here we have Subleton groups.
W-E-B Dubois is a particularly interesting example
when he talks about the talented 10.
These are Subleton groups who are saying, well, this system provides opportunities which we must
seize and which we can use to transform society peacefully and by rising up intellectually.
And again, that's true of the woman's movement.
It's true of the working classes, the Aristotle, the same labor.
It has something to do as well with our struggle and movement as a society towards the integration
of something like ethics across multiple levels of analysis.
So we say, well, we want our workforce to do something productive that elevates our material
well-being and stop suffering
And so we want to make the micro movements that we make and the selections that we
engender
Systemically serve that end. So the whole thing is the whole thing is integrated and that that that desire for that integration
For the greater common good in some sense
especially to elevate to what to alleviate the grossest elements of suffering
at the most extreme end.
That's an ethic and a desire that isn't captured properly at all.
It's antithetical to the spirit of totalitarian oppression that Foucault insists, in fact,
every act of categorization.
But meritocracy is also essentially a form of liberal individualism.
It says that individuals should be judged on the basis of their own efforts and abilities.
And it's also an idea that presents agency. It has agency at the very heart. It says that
people can shape their own futures. They can shape their characters. They can work hard.
They can get ahead on the basis of work and ability.
That was always something, you know, that they're properly rewarded for that.
And that they need incentives.
But to do.
And that's something that the, you know, the, you know, Foucault is obviously against,
but a great bulk of modern sociology has been against that.
It's removed the agency and a sense of agency.
But I think that it exists. I think that, you know, that agency and a sense of agency. But I think that exists.
I think that there is a sense of agency.
We do shape our decencies.
We can work hard or we can sleep all day.
And we can exercise our talents
or we can choose not to exercise our talents or...
Yes, and we have virtues.
We have virtues.
And we can exercise those
and we're not fundamentally totalitarian
demons driven by nothing but the will to power.
Exactly.
So I think that the philosophy embodied in liberal individualism is something that really
needs to be defended, and again, it doesn't have enough defenders at the moment.
As you see, the large chunks of academia, and particularly have gone to post-modernism,
which is ultimately dehumanizing, or it takes the agency out of being human, which is what
being human, I think, is about. So I think meritocracy is right at the very center of a liberal view
of the world. Well, let's say amen to that and close this discussion. Thank you very much.
Thank you very much. Thank you very much.
I am very much appreciated and enjoyed talking to you.
And great.
It went very quickly.
Okay.
Well, I hope we'll talk again sometime in the future.
I hope so too. you