The Jordan B. Peterson Podcast - Stephen Hicks: Philosophy and Postmodernism
Episode Date: May 5, 2019Today, we’re presenting Dr. Peterson's conversation with Stephen Hicks, recorded on March 27, 2019. Stephen R. C. Hicks is Professor of Philosophy at Rockford University, Illinois, USA, Executive�...�Director of the Center for Ethics and Entrepreneurship, and Senior Scholar at The Atlas Society.
Transcript
Discussion (0)
Welcome to season 2 episode 7 of the Jordan B Peterson podcast.
I'm Michaela Peterson, Jordan's daughter and collaborator, CEO of his business, and
general all around good person.
Today we're presenting Dad's conversation with Stephen Hicks recorded on March 27th, 2019.
Today, the intro will just be done by me, and possibly next week's episodes intro as
well, who knows how long this will continue?
Maybe forever.
I do like talking so I'm okay with that.
Hopefully you guys are too.
Stephen RC Hicks is Professor of Philosophy at Rockford University, Illinois, USA.
Executive Director of the Center for Ethics and Entrepreneurship and Senior Scholar at the Atlas Society.
He received his bachelor's and master's degrees from the University of Guelph and his PhD in Philosophy from Indiana University.
He has published four books translated into 16 different languages, including explaining postmodernism, skepticism and socialism
from Rousseau to Foucault, Nietzsche and the Nazis, the art of reasoning, readings for logical
analysis, and most recently entrepreneurial living co-edited with Jennifer Hurrell.
He's published in academic journals such as Business Ethics Quarterly, Teaching Philosophy,
and Review of Metaphysics, as well as other publications such as The Ethics Quarterly, Teaching Philosophy, and Review of Metaphysics,
as well as other publications such as The Wall Street Journal, Cato Unbound, and The Baltimore
Sun. In 2010, he won his university's Excellence in Teaching Award. He's done a lot. He's an
impressive individual. Hopefully you guys enjoy the podcast, and perhaps even learn something.
When we return, Dad's conversation with Stephen Hicks.
Please welcome my father, Dr. Jordan B. Peterson.
Stephen RC Hicks is Professor of Philosophy at Rockford University, Illinois, USA, Executive
Director of the Center for Ethics and Entrepreneurship, and Senior Scholar at the Atlas Society.
He received his bachelor's in Master's degree from the University of Guelph in Canada, and his PhD in Philosophy from Indiana University, Bloomington, USA.
He's published four books, translated into 16 different languages.
translated into 16 different languages. In 2004, it expanded in 2011, he published explaining postmodernism, skepticism and socialism from Rousseau to Foucault. In 2010,
Nietzsche and the Nazis. In 1994, with a second edition in 1998, he published the
art of reasoning reasoning readings for logical
Adelisus co-edited with David Kelly, and in 2016 entrepreneurial living co-edited with
Jennifer Harrow. He's published in academic journals such as Business Ethics Quarterly
Teaching Philosophy and Review of Metaphysics, as well as other publications such as the Wall Street Journal,
Cato Unbound, and the Baltimore Sun.
In 2010, he went as university's excellence in teaching award.
Dr. Hicks has been visiting professor of business ethics at Georgetown University in Washington,
DC, a visiting fellow at the social philosophy and policy center
in Bowling Green, Ohio, senior fellow at the Objectivist Center in New York, and visiting
professor at the University of Cazmere, the Great Poland.
So welcome today, and thank you very much for agreeing to talk with me again.
Oh, thanks for having me back.
Yeah, well, it's a real pleasure.
I thought we might start by talking about explaining postmodernism again, your 2011 book,
skepticism and socialism from Rousseau to Foucault, because I know that it's been perhaps more
controversial of late than it was when you originally published it. And I'm curious
about the sales and the academic and the public reaction.
Right. Well, sales have been strong. The book was originally published in 2004 and still
sold steadily for the first decade or so, which is quite gratifying for an academic book.
And then starting about three years ago,
in part because postmodernism started to spill out
of the strictly academic intellectual world
into the broader cultural world,
sales picked up again.
And so there's been a two front set of discussions,
one at the intellectual level
and one at the more public thinking public level as well.
Gratifyingly, lots of translations.
I think there will be three more translations added this year.
Arabic, Hebrew, and Estonian are in the works.
So all together, I'm pleased with that.
The reactions are quite polarized in part because reactions to postmodernism
itself are polarized.
It's an extreme movement as a good, deep thinking should be, even if I disagree fundamentally
with postmodernism.
It is a well articulated, negative outlook on most of life's philosophical questions.
So we should expect that any movement that pushes buttons fundamentally like that should get some extreme reactions.
And the same thing holds for me, when I push back against in my book some of these strong,
to my mind, ultimately nihilistic claims that postmodernism ends up making, I also get the
negative push back.
The push back kind of comes in two forms.
I've found from the professional reviews.
There have been H to my knowledge by professional philosophers in the philosophy journals. And
they are generally strong to very strongly positive. The normal scholarly quibbles arise.
When I get pushback from or sorry reviews from academics outside of the philosophy, they tend to be more polarized,
something strongly in favor, but then particularly people in history, in sociology, in rhetoric studies,
and literature, places where there are stronger contingents of post-modern thinkers,
I tend to get strongly negative responses. And those responses are also mirrored in the general thinking public when they respond
and write back and write reviews.
Well, maybe it would be useful to bring people up to date for you to give us a brief overview
of your view of postmodernism, like a definition.
It's one of those tricky terms,
like existentialism or phenomenology
that are bandied about by people, educated people
on a fairly regular basis,
but where the definition itself is slippery
and difficult to pin down.
So maybe you could talk a little bit about
how you view postmodernism and also what argument you
made with regards to the history of its development.
Right.
Well, it makes sense that it's slippery in part because postmodernism philosophically avoids
categorizations, avoids broad sweeping statements, although they do make some.
So anytime you try to make a precise broad sweeping claim about what this postmodernism amounts to,
you will get pushed back on that. But there is a broadly unifying set of themes to postmodernism.
If you start by breaking the term down, it's postmodernism. So first you have to say, what is modernism such that postmodernism is reacting against it or saying that we need
to go beyond.
And modernism is used variously in different fields, there's modernism in art, in literature.
I'm using a philosophical and historical understanding of postmodernism and that's how it's mostly
used now.
That is to say, we look at the modern world.
So that essentially is the last four to five hundred years of history, at least in the
Western tradition.
So what's going on in the world, five hundred years ago, is a revolutionary transformation
of Western society.
We have Columbus crossing the ocean, and so we're entering into a new era of globalization.
The Renaissance is in full swing, and its impact, late 1400s, early 1500s, is now being
felt all over Europe.
There is the Protestant Reformation and the Counter-Reformation, so religious life in
the West is being dramatically transformed. You see the beginnings of science with thinkers like
Copernicus and the salius in anatomy, and so scientific method is being developed and all of the
things that we now recognize as the scientific disciplines are being founded. So that's the modern
world starting four or five hundred years ago. Philosophically, we start looking at the analyses
that are being offered by thinkers like Francis Bacon, Renee Descartes and others, and we see
that they are putting thought on a different foundation from that that had gone on earlier.
Well, it seems that what happened with the modernists, maybe if we tried to sum it up, is that
it seemed to be this emerging consensus that the world was rationally intelligible.
Yes.
And that human beings could explore both physically and mentally and also come to predict and
control the transformations of the material world.
I mean, it seems to me that that's the fundamental element of, let's say, the scientific, and therefore also the modernist perspective.
But also, I think that what went along with that was the idea that progress, genuine progress in knowledge was possible, and along with that, the benefits of progress
both conceptually and technologically.
And I mean, it seems to me to be fair to point out that movement bore substantive fruit.
I mean, it could argue about the misery that the modernist movement caused along the way,
say with regards to the advancement of military technology and so forth, but it seems indisputable to me that the average human being is far better off now than he or she was
certainly 200 years ago and absolutely 500 years ago.
Right, so this revolution and thought with the subsequent developments in science and technology, we certainly
can judge philosophies by their fruits.
And so we can then say, yeah, absolutely.
We're living longer.
We're living healthier.
We're living less pain-free life.
We're able to enjoy more art, more leisure, and so forth.
So all of the things that, again, this is a value judgment.
If you think those are all good things,
then we're doing a whole lot better
as a result of that philosophy.
Now, the other side, though, I want to emphasize here,
is that you emphasize the world is rationally intelligible,
that along with modernism came the claim
that it was rationally intelligible
to each individual rather than being an elect number of people who have special cognitive
insights into the mysteries of the universe or that there are certain authoritative institutions
that are controlled by elites and only they are the ones who have cognitive and therefore
social authority to make various pronouncements.
Part and parcel of the rise of modernism is a broadly universalizing of that that each individual
is born with irrational capacity and that with proper training, education, literacy, and so forth,
they can come to understand the world for themselves, they can be self-responsible, they can take charge of their lives. And as a result of that, we should have an extension of rights that used
to be the prerogatives only of the few, an expansion of freedom, you can do whatever you want
with your life, broadly speaking. And so what we then see is that it's not only a religious
elite or a political elite that is empowered, but rather every human being.
And then we can see systematically over the course of the next century.
It gets extended to not only males who own property, but to all males and then to women and
then to people of other ethnicities and other races.
And we're back again.
Yes, we're back again.
So we have this notion of universal rights and universal self-responsibility universal freedom that I think also was part and parcel of
the modern movement. Well the thing about science that makes it so peculiar I
think is that science is actually a technology that enables people who are
bright but not that bright let say, to genuinely produce advances in
knowledge because of the method.
Right?
I mean, if you're a careful scientist, look, when we studied what predicted academic achievement,
for example, both in graduate school and among faculty members, creativity didn't even
enter the equation.
Intelligence did and so did conscientiousness. But I think it's partly because with the scientific method,
you can actually break down your knowledge seeking into a set of implementable technological steps.
And that enables it to be implemented on an incredibly broad scale.
And even if a lot of it is error-ridden, which is obviously the case,
and to a scandalous degree to somewhat lately,
it still means that as hundreds of thousands of us,
and increasingly now millions of us,
grind away slowly at this careful technology of knowledge acquisition that overall we do
seem to be able to predict and to control the world better.
And then that started to become question.
You know, one of the things that seemed to characterize postmodernism, one definition that
I've read is skepticism of meta-narratives.
Right.
That's from Jean-F John Francois Liotard.
And he is the one credited with labeling postmodernism philosophically,
and defining it as a skepticism toward meta-narratives.
Now, what that means, there's a couple of things built into that.
One is, of course, the skepticism and philosophy for the last century and a half or so has entered an increasingly
skeptical mode.
So that pushes back against the very broad claims that the early modernists are making,
that the power of reason is great, it is highly competent, and that essentially we can figure
out all of the important truths of the world.
We can come up with a big story that explains everything
ultimately. Not necessarily that any one individual will contain all of that knowledge in his or her mind, but certainly
communally there will have a huge amount of knowledge. We will slowly, as you're putting it together, peace together, a big picture story about the way the world works.
And then in principle there's nothing about the universe
that we can't figure out.
There are just things that we haven't been able to figure out yet.
So the skepticism that Leo Tarr and the others are talking about
is a skepticism about that grand set of claims, right?
A meta narrative, a narrative that encompasses everything.
Instead, we're left with smaller narratives, and then as
the movement develops, we should be skeptical even about the truth status or the knowledge status
of those smaller narratives. So what becomes important in the post-modern tradition is a skepticism about our ability to know the world in milder form
as much as the modern thinkers thought we could and in stronger postmodern form at all.
That maybe there is no such thing as truth, no such thing as knowledge. Instead, all we have is
opinions and beliefs that are subjectively held but
don't have any objective. Well it's like the postmodernists that were
influenced by Sosur for example they seem to be convinced in some strange way of
something that disturbed me when I first really discovered dictionaries when I
was a kid you know'd look up a word
in a dictionary, and of course it would just refer to another word in the dictionary, and
that would refer to another word in the dictionary.
And there didn't seem to be, in some sense, any definition outside of the dictionary.
And the French intellectuals that were so influential in the postmodern world seemed
to think of meaning in exactly that way. They understand that
linguistic meaning is necessarily embedded in a larger linguistic context so that each word is
dependent on each phrase and each phrase is dependent on each sentence. And so there's a contextual dependency of meaning on linguistic framing, but they seem to me too.
And this is one of the major problems, I think, of postmodernism in university, is that they
seem to deny or ignore the existence of any world whatsoever outside of linguistic
construction.
And that's something that strikes me as extraordinarily curious.
That, like, it's a real denial of nature in my estimation, but also something tremendously
dangerous, because while assuming that you think that physics and biology and chemistry
actually have any sort of genuine reality, it denies the existence of a substrate of existence that
the purely linguistic relates to. I mean, I always think of words as being, they're not
so much descriptions, they're tools that you use to, like, and that's a bit constenian idea,
is that words are really tools that you use to operate on
the world with.
And the consequences of those operations are actually manifest in the world of sensation
and perception and emotion and motivation and embodiment rather than purely on a linguistic
level.
And so I also don't really understand how it could be that our intellectuals could come to the conclusion that are
And this seems like a primarily French idea that our ideas are are primarily constructed linguistically
I mean how do animals exist under those circumstances?
Yeah
Now that's strong form of linguistic skepticism that you're articulating is most pronounced
in Jacques Derry-Dah, and he does build himself as a post-structuralist, and that's a linguistic
version of post-modernism.
But the challenge here is that our view is that consciousness is a relational phenomena,
right? It's responsive to an external world.
And that should be the fundamental realist commitment
that we make.
The problem that the post-structuralists are coming up
with by the time we get to Derri Dahl,
I should say the idea that there isn't
any sort of ontological substrate matching onto,
not all of the postmodernists will buy into that
as strongly as Dairy
Dodd does. They might say, well, there's something out there, but we just can't know what
the relationship is between our concepts and our words and an external reality.
So the point though is that the words that we use are abstractions and they do come along
fairly far or high up in our cognitive development.
And if you want to argue that consciousness is a response to reality or that consciousness
is a relational phenomenon as I do to maintain that objective relational commitment there,
what you then have to do is take up all of the skeptical arguments that want to put consciousness
out of relationship,
or to say that there's no way to bridge this gap between the subject and the object.
Once you start going down that road, if you want to say, for example, that perception
is fraught with illusions or hallucinations, or that we can't tell the difference between
a veritical perception when our sensory organs are in contact with reality
and a hallucination, well then you have a gap between our conscious apparatus and reality.
If you then want to go on an argue as empiricists do that our concepts and the words that we assign
to the concepts are based on empirical observations or perceptual observations,
but you now believe that those perceptual observations are subjective and out of relation with objective reality,
then you're going to say these abstract concepts and words are also out of relation with reality.
And then what gives them their meaning if you can't establish a connection between the words and reality
Then you're into the dictionary you're saying well what gives the words their meaning is their sideways or network connections to other words and
Then a generation or two later you're into derida's university where he says that's also where the post-mortem
Reality that's also where the post-mortemists claim about the primacy of power seem to sneak in.
It's like if the words are only related to one another in terms of their verbal relationship,
well, they don't seem to have any mode of force.
And as soon as you enter a landscape of linguist to consideration that has no motive force,
then there's nothing to do. And so this seems to me to account for, like I've been criticized very
often for, let's say, conflating postmodernism and Marxism. But it seems to me that the Marxists
or that the postmodernists have had to default to what are essentially Marxist preconceptions to add any motive to their
thinking. And what they've done is to say that, well, words are related to one another and that's
how they derive their fundamental meaning. And they're not really connected to the world in any
real way, except in so far as they privilege one group or another or one person or another in terms
of power and status, which they also
will be back to your dictionary analysis. The next step then would be to say if words are in
these linguistic relationships to other words and we can find out what they are in dictionaries,
well who writes the dictionaries? And then at that point, you're not asking any
epistemological question anymore,
you're asking a social and psychological question.
So who are the authors of the dictionary?
What authorizes rather than with the power
to decide what words mean?
At that point, we stepped directly out
of neuro-epistemological arguments
into social and psychological arguments
about linguistic communities.
Okay, well, so that's a peculiarity too, though,
because well, look, if the words only have meaning
in relationship to one another,
and there's this gap between the words
and empirical reality, which by the way,
I don't think anybody disputes.
I mean, that's why we need five senses.
That's why we need to communicate with each other. That's why we need the scientific method, right?
It's because it's difficult to establish a useful one-to-one relationship between words and
reality. But if words serve power, then it seems to me that what the postmodernists have done is taken biological motivation, let's call
it the motivation for power, at least, and seeked it through the back door and reconnected
the world of linguistic abstraction to the world of reality.
But saying, well, look, the only connection is one of power.
And then they leave why it is that people want power?
Like the idea that people want power,
first of all, it's a complicated idea
because you have to define power
and you have to define want.
And those aren't trivial issues
by any stretch of the imagination.
And so you sneak it in the back door as sort of self-evident,
and then that seems to undermine the general postmodernist claim. It's like, if the words are
only embedded in a network of meaning that's related to other words, then it isn't a fair move
fair move ontologically or epistemologically to reinsert power striving, like a Nietzschean power striving, or even an adlerian power striving, as the fundamental and what would you
call it, sort of sweet generis motivation that characterizes human beings.
So I also don't understand how they get away with that,
except that it seems to me like a mask
for the continuation of a Marxist move under a new guise.
Well, I have no problem with seeing power as a positive,
right?
Coming back to just in a moment
to all of the suspicions that you're announcing
about inappropriate understandings of the relationship
of power. I do think we should be able to say our cognitive capacities are a power that
we have and they are a tool and the whole point of using that tool is to increase our power
in the world to achieve our goals. What the postmoderns are doing is
undercutting the two things that make that understanding of power legitimate.
One is to say that when I am making a cognitive claim,
I am successfully saying something about the world
so that we can use the words knowledge and truth.
So if I want to act on the basis of my beliefs,
that those beliefs do map onto world as it really is.
But if you are skeptical about any sort of a knowledge claim
or any sort of a truth claim, then you're just going to say,
no, no, your claims merely are subjective beliefs
that are peculiar to you or peculiar to your group,
and they don't have any special cognitive status whatsoever.
In that case, if you want to act on or use those beliefs to empower you, well, then you
are in an out-of-reality connection.
The other thing is that we want to say that power should be a tool that we use for good,
for advancing genuine values in the world, but another part of the postmodern skepticism
is to say that we cannot ground any values objectively.
Instead, values are merely subjective preferences, either individually or group-oriented.
So, in that case, if you have your value framework, then we're into the problem of relativism.
And I have my value framework.
Neither of us is able to induce any facts that give an objective grounding to those values
or to argue that those values should be universally embraced.
Then we're just left with, you have a certain amount of power to advance your interests.
I have a certain amount of power to advance your interest. I have a certain amount of power to advance my interests and it's a naked power struggle
in the suspicious way that you're worried about.
And that is, we would come back to this issue of how Marxist or not the postmoderns are,
but you're right that at least the great grandfather move, right, was made by the Marxist in one generation and the Nicheans
and next generation to strip power down to that amoral ontological status that you are worried about.
But what's the motivation for it? It's like if there isn't a reality that's outside the linguistic,
then why is it, well, first of all, what is power?
And I think there are two kinds of motivations. One of the things we know is that there are
people who just like power. They want to control other people. They have their agendas.
Now we can talk about the sociological and the psychological foundations of that, but
that is an ongoing fact about society.
Some people just want power, and they will then rationalize their use of power over other
people by a variety of means.
Okay, so we're willing to accept that.
We're willing to accept that as an extra linguistic reality.
That's the thing that's so surprising to me.
It's like, I'm not disputing that. That's it's obviously the case
But why that would what if you think of the way some lawyers argue in a courtroom
They will use all sorts of rhetorical power plays they will make fallacious arguments if they can get away with it
They will browbeat witnesses and make up facts and so forth
Now they are not really
browbeat witnesses and makeup facts and so forth. Now they are not really skeptical.
They believe that there's an external world and so forth.
They just believe that life is a power struggle
and any tactic is fair in order to achieve their ends.
Right, so they're not postmodernist lawyers.
They're just old fashioned power seeking lawyers and so forth.
Now that is one motivation.
It comes up in religious circles.
It comes up in political circles.
It comes up in the school yard and so on.
But the other one, and the one that I think that we are
worried about, though, is that those who get to that view
about the amoral ontological substrate being power,
are those people who are smart and who do some thinking
about philosophy, thinking about politics and so forth,
and they argue themselves into that position because they find the power of those skeptical
arguments to be convincing rationally to them. So even though this is not a paradoxical formulation,
even though they are rational individuals, they are following the logic of certain skeptical arguments
to its conclusion, and the legitimate conclusion
of those arguments is that a moral power rules the universe.
OK, so let's examine that for a moment.
I mean, this is another thing that strikes me
as specious to say the least.
I mean, first of all, I'm very skeptical of people
who try to reduce all complex phenomena
to a single explanatory mechanism.
I mean, if you look at, because I do look at things
biologically, it's obvious that human beings
have a multitude of primordial motivational systems and that we share them
and that we share them with animals.
There's pain and there's fear and there's incentive reward and there's rage and there's
play and there's hunger and there's lust and that's a handful and there's more than that
and these are very, and you know those motivations get integrated across time into
hypermotivations, let's say, that would be something akin to an integrated narrative,
one that is manifested, interpersonally, but also played out socially, and higher order values emerge
from that. You take a claim like the postmodernist make that, well, first of all, they accept the idea
that there's almost nothing but hierarchy and that people's fundamental motivations is to climb
up the hierarchy, even though they're very, my experience has been, for example, whenever I talk
about hierarchy, the postmodernist types go after me, hammer and tongs, but because I'm making the claim that hierarchy is a natural
phenomenon, not necessarily a beneficial one, but an inevitable one in some sense with
its pros and cons, but they accept that uncritically when they presume that power is the fundamental
drive. And then the other problem is, and this isn't even more serious one, as far as I'm concerned,
is that the evidence that the most effective way for human beings to occupy positions
of authority, let's say, and competence in human dominance hierarchies isn't through
the naked expression of power.
That's actually unbelievably
unstable, you know, even France to wall when he was studying chimpanzees, you know, the female
chimpanzees are more empathetic than the male chimpanzees. But of all the chimpanzees, the
alpha males are the most empathic. They're the ones that engage in the most reciprocal
most empathic. They're the ones that engage in the most reciprocal interactions with the members of the troop. And there's evidence accruing from all sorts of areas, including developmental
psychology, the developmental psychology of PSJA, for example, that suggests that something
like cooperative game playing aimed towards a particular important end is a much more stable means for establishing hierarchical relationships between people than power.
Power only rules in tyrannies. And I guess maybe that's part of the reason that the postmodernists also insist that the Western hierarchy is fundamentally an oppressive patriarchy because that justifies their claim that power
is the primary motivator and mover of the world.
But I just don't see how that's a tenable position.
Well, I think ontologically it's fair to say that most postmodern's buy into the notion that power is fundamental.
There's not anything that can be reduced to that.
But my reading of them is that that is not the entire philosophical story because power just is a tool,
a means to an end and that still leaves open the question of what ends to which one is going to use that power.
And here, I think the postmodern's are rightly diverse in their views.
There is a strong streak of them, and this is something that goes back to Marxism in
general or broadly socialism in general that we'll say, yes, we all want power, but we recognize that power is unequally distributed
in the world, and that connects to your points
about hierarchy.
But what is your value reaction to that unequal distribution
of power in the world?
Now, there are the Nietzscheans who will react to say,
well, the unequal distribution of power is fine,
and our sympathies are with those who have more power,
because we want them to advance the human species
by some evolutionary mechanism.
But that is a subjective value preference
that they are adding to previous facts.
That power is fundamental, that power is unequally distributed. Now
we're adding my sympathies are with those who have more power. The socialist or more narrowly
Marxist response to those to say power is fundamental, power is unequally distributed,
but our empathy is with those who are on the losing side of history, so to speak, or
a various sorts of social forces.
And so what that then means for them is that they will accept that power is operating
in a hierarchical context, but that they want to use whatever power they have to more
equally redistribute the power in an egalitarian fashion.
Right, so then they also talk about, it's going to be though, that third component about
what your value reaction is to what you take to be the metaphysical substrate.
Right, okay, but then there's another form of real world smuggling that goes along with that, which is both ontological and ethical,
and the ontological smuggling would be, well, there are definitely power structures and that people
compete for power, so that's claim number one, which seems to be extra linguistic, and claim
number two is that the proper moral stance of a human being is empathy. So there's a claim that something
like empathy exists, and that empathy should be reserved for people who are on the lower end of
the hierarchical distribution. That's right. Okay. And postmodernists like Foucault, make that very clear, Richard Warty, even more clearly, makes that claim.
Jacques Derri Dau is a very interesting case because most of his work is not overtly social,
ethical or political, but at various points, particularly toward the end of his life,
he says, my entire sympathies are with the, and he talks about reinvigorating a certain kind of,
or in the spirit of Marxism, something or other.
But from his perspective, he recognizes
that he has no philosophical resources
to justify that value claim.
And he doesn't want to say that it's just
a personal subjective preference that he has.
So he does appeal to a kind of Kantian-regulative idea or more old-fashioned way, whether it's
a kind of platonic form that we need to appeal to if we're going to justify it in some
way.
So it's kind of interesting that recognizing exactly the problem that you're pointing
out, where do we get that empathy claim from and justify that?
The postmoderns recognize the predicament and some of them are trying to point to extra
linguistic sources for it.
Well, that opens, that opens a big can of worms if your initial claim is that there's
no such thing as an extra linguistic source.
You know, because you let one extra linguistic source in, especially something as complicated
as the interplay between
say power, hierarchy, and empathy. I mean, those are major motivational forces.
And then if you're willing to admit to the existence of those major motivational forces, well, it's hard to exclude pain, it's hard to exclude anxiety, it's hard to exclude
something even more basic as hunger, it's hard to exclude the proclivity for cooperation
and play.
It's like all of biology, it seems to me, sneaks back into the postmodern project as
soon as those initial extra linguistic realities
are allowed.
Well, absolutely, but that's what we're finding.
A lot of our debates are right now about psychology and biology.
Is that certain number of psychologists and biologists are pushing back and saying,
oh, there is a reality here.
We're getting great resistance from the postmodern second and third generation to having to
do so.
Okay, so now you said the philosophers that have reviewed your book have been
basically positive and so why are you receiving positive feedback from what
is it about philosophy and about philosophers or about your work that's eliciting a positive response
from them.
Yeah.
Well, my book is primarily an intellectual history.
You know, to some extent, I am polemical and pushing back against postmodernism.
So people understand that I'm taking a stance as well.
But the primary purpose of the book is to do a solid intellectual history.
Where does this confusing sprawling, but nonetheless very vigorous and powerful movement come
from? And it doesn't come out of thin air but rather there's a lot of deep
thinking that's behind it. So what I'm doing is I'm tracing what I see as the
important intellectual movements of the last two centuries. So I'm starting with
Kant and Russo, but I'm talking about Hegel, Marx,
Nietzsche, Heidegger, and the others. So all of those figures are difficult, complex,
and important in their own right, and their scholarly debate about, say, how skeptical
or not Kant is, whether there is an element of liberalism or not in Nietzsche, Heidegger's
connection to the Nazis and so forth.
So there is a range of scholarly movement,
and most of these major intellectuals
have two or three major schools of
interpretation attached to them.
But what an end of, and so the pushback that I am getting,
on Kant or on Nietzsche or Heidegger or whatever will be,
from those who are in a different school of interpretation
with respect to them.
But typically among the philosopher,
it's a respectful engagement because they will recognize
that there is a very good argument
that can be made for interpreting the philosopher the other way.
And typically then what I'm doing is emphasizing
the skeptical elements or the ultimately negative
and nihilistic elements that get sifted out and woven together into ultimately the postmodern
framework, and along the way the philosophers who want to argue well, this particular
thinker is not bad or you would not buy into the whole project. Those are the ones who
will criticize beyond various things. But I typically find though outside of philosophical
circles though is and this is not a criticism of these individuals since we can't know
everything is that they will know something about Nietzsche or Heidegger or Kant, but they're
not up on the scholarly literature.
They've read one book or one article about that person that was written from a certain
perspective.
So, if I make the argument for the other perspective on that thinker, it's new to them and it seems
outrageous to them, and so they will react negatively to it.
So, something like that. So now you wrote this book back in 2004.
So you were a pretty early observer of the vital importance, I suppose, of the post-modernist
debate.
I mean, there's certainly been a rise in political correctness in the early 90s.
And that's seem to disappear by the mid 90s, but
2004 is I would say five or six or maybe even
eight years previous to the to this new
burgeoning of
political polarization and and the debate
between the politically correct types, let's say, and those who take a more biological perspective.
It's like, what clued you into the fact
that this was an issue of fundamental,
of potentially fundamental importance?
Well, yeah, thanks.
I think it does a testament to the power of philosophy,
the power of ideas, the power of logic,
that when you identify abstract
principles and their adoption, and you have a good sense of logic, you can make predictions
about how they're going to play out when they are applied in real life.
This is one of my major career beliefs that philosophy is not disembodied abstract, head in the clouds, but no matter how abstract
and speculative to various philosophical positions seem to be when they are believed and acted upon
the they they make a real life difference. So in part that's what I was doing. Now I actually
wrote the first draft of the book 20 years ago this year. In 1999, I had a sabbatical. And so I had an outline of the book written in
1999. And then by the middle part of the year 2000, I had fully written the book. But it
didn't come out till 2004, because I had some challenges with getting it published.
I had some challenges with getting it published. But I think what has happened in the last five years or so is that we're now into second
or third-generation postmodernism depending on how you count things.
What has happened is the first generation of postmodern were very successful inside academic
circles at educating large numbers of students, getting a significant number of them
through graduate school, and then to themselves becoming professors and public intellectuals,
and things reached a critical mass, I would say, starting six or seven years ago.
And so then we started to notice it significantly, starting to transform the internal dynamics of the university,
but we also now have a critical mass of activists
who are now graduated.
Maybe they didn't graduate with PhDs,
they got bachelor's degrees or master's degrees,
but they've gone into activist organizations
and they are trying to, and then successfully,
shifting the terms of the debate
outside of the academic world. And so the broader public starts to notice things. And then that's where we are right now with
the Cultural War manifesting itself on two major fronts, the academic world and the broader
cultural space. Right. Right. Well, so what are your concerns about that? Like when you look out at the world,
you're obviously concerned enough about postmodernist thinking to devote a substantial proportion of your academic career to it.
And then to put yourself on the line to some degree as well, I mean, what is it about the postmodernist view that, well, let's ask this question two ways.
What do you think the advantages, if any, are to the postmodernist view or the inevitability
of it, and what do you think the dangers and disadvantages are?
Well, that's two big questions.
First, why I'm worried about it.
And there's a question about what degree of worry
one should have.
Interestingly, in my home discipline of philosophy,
postmodernism is not that strong.
Philosophy flirted with and postmodernism for a while.
I think philosophy did generate all of the arguments, philosophy florted with and postmodernism for a while.
Philosophy did generate all of the arguments, or we saw the major arguments that postmodern's use,
but philosophy does have built into its DNA, so to speak,
a very healthy respect for argumentation
and a liking for new arguments.
So what has happened mostly in the philosophy profession
is a serious development and engagement
with all of these negative skeptical arguments
and so on, but then a realization that a lot of them
don't work in various ways,
and then people moving off in other directions.
Or once we start seeing the same arguments being recycled
and retreading a certain amount of
boredom occurs with it because smart, active-minded people live like new things. And so someone comes
along with a new positive argument or a new positive program and philosophers get excited about that.
And so postmodern journalism is a little bit passe in those disciplines. But I am worried about it because philosophy
demographic is a tiny proportion of the overall academy
and the postmodern arguments have been picked up
by the larger and more influential academic disciplines,
such as psychology, you know this one as well,
in English literature, to some extent,
in the law schools, in the field of of history, sociology is very polluted.
And then the big rise of all of the various
special studies programs, you know,
gender studies, race studies, ethnicity studies,
and so on, you find a much higher percentage
of postmodernism there.
Now, I have not seen good journalistic sociology
about higher academic, whether it's 8% or 40%
of people who are postmodern or not, but there clearly is an uptick, a statistically
significant increase in the number of people who are adopting postmodern viewpoints and
then educating the next generation of students.
Yes, well, and they're certainly dominant among the activist types.
Yeah, absolutely. Yes, that's right. So, there is a non-philosophical issue.
This is a journalistic or a demographic issue about measuring to what extent it's a rising movement,
how widespread it is, and so on. And my concern professionally is with the arguments to generate
postmodernism and refuting those. Now, why this is important is, well, I'm a professor,
so I'm always dealing with young people who are at the early stages of their careers.
In my view, the most important thing that we all need as human beings,
we're thoughtful people. We want to be passionately engaged with the world.
We want our lives to be meaningful.
As we do need a philosophy of life that's going to set us up
for the best chance of succeeding in our lives as possible.
So in my view, basically an optimist,
we do need as young people with our whole lives ahead
to have some sense that my life is going
to be meaningful.
It's going to be significant.
There are important values that I can strive for.
The romantic in me wants to say, my life can and should be this great adventure.
And having that fundamental commitment and helping students sort out what
are the genuine values that are worth pursuing in life. That has to be instilled in young people,
otherwise they will just drift through life and then they will get to their older years and
realize that their life has furthered away. Yeah, okay, so that's an interesting, you know, that's very interesting observation
because, you know, I've been trying to account,
at least in part, for, well, let's say,
the surprising and surreal popularity of my public lectures.
So I've spoken at about 150 cities now to about 300,000 people.
And, you know, I lay out a fairly straightforward case, I would say, that's very much analogous
to the case that you just described.
And that is that, well, we look for some unassailable truths.
And for me, there are two unassailable pessimistic truths. And
one is that a substantial proportion of life is going to be suffering because we're finite.
And even if things are going well for you now, your subject to illness, mental and physical,
your subject to the decimation of your dreams, you're going to lose the people that you love,
the world that you know is going to change in ways that you find
disconcerting and unfortunate. And so, suffering's built in. And then
the moment is interrupting at that point. The phrase, unassailable truth. What we should be doing,
though, in education is saying that there are no unassailable truths.
Part of a good education is any previous generation's truth should be assailed, at least intellectually
by the students.
They should challenge question and look at those truths.
What the best arguments can be amounted against them and then make their own judgments about
whether they agree that this truth is in
fact a truth or whether it needs to be rejected and moved on. So the great danger, I think, of post-modernism,
though, is its skeptical stance toward the idea of their being proof at all and then in its
activist manifestation when the professors are functioning as, I just have my subjective preferences, and I have power in the classroom,
and my view as a professor, or my practice rather as a professor, is simply to indoctrinate students
in my subjective preferences. In that case, what you are doing is not only giving students a very
cynical negative, ultimately, as an empty view of the
world, but you are not at all training them in the ability to think for themselves to
compare competing viewpoints and make their own judgment. So that's the danger.
Right, right. Well, I guess I should reconsider my use of the word on this saleable.
I was thinking more, I suppose clinically,
in some sense, in that my experience has been
that you don't have to scratch very deeply
beneath the surface of people's lives
until you find massive sorrows that they're dealing with.
And so, I don't know.
I know you're not saying this,
but from the student's perspective, it can't be that Professor
Peterson with all of his years of experience and wisdom has announced that this is a truth,
therefore it's a truth, they have to go through the process.
Yes, you went through.
Hopefully, you can accelerate that process for them, but they have to go through that
process.
Yeah, well, and I mean, I do that in the lectures by telling stories too, and illustrating the
fact that the limitations that are placed on us that produce suffering.
And I invite people, I would say, to draw their own conclusions about how they regard
that reality in their own lives. And the second proposition, let's say,
is that the suffering is often made worse by malevolence.
And that can be, well, the sort of,
what would you say, impersonal malevolence of nature
or the more personal malevolence of society
or the individual.
And so we're faced with that set of problems,
that vulnerability that's characteristic of existence. And then that vulnerability, because it constitutes a real set of problems, calls to us to generate solutions. And it's in that
attempt to generate solutions, that that adventure that you described earlier
Seems to me to manifest itself and so it seems reasonable to me to
To suggest to young people that they do have a destiny that gives their life
significant individual import and that is to
take arms up against the
Inequities of existence at whatever levels they can and to act forthrightly and courageously to minimize unnecessary suffering and to constrain malevolence.
And then it's also actually a vital importance that they do that because they're failure to do so
do that because their failure to do so is more damaging than they think. Their nihilism and cynicism that might entice them into nihilistic and destructive acts, actively, is more
destructive than they think, and their capacity to do
positive things in the world on a large scale
individually and in their family and in their community is much larger than they think and I it's very difficult for me to see
how young people cannot
can be left
uninformed of that as at least a potential reality without
falling down the rabbit hole of nihilism and cynicism and subjectivism and relativism
that seems to me to be at least one of the primary dangers of postmodernism.
Yes.
Yeah, I think 100% on the latter part of what you were saying.
I think on the, should be an open question initially.
Yes, there is suffering in the world.
Yes, there is malevolence in the world.
But we should also be open to the fact that there is pleasure, there is beauty, there is
romance, there is adventure, there is genuine love in the world, and what proportions of benevolence
versus malevolence, happiness versus suffering is possible and natural to human beings.
That should be part of the conversation early on.
That's a conversation about the potency of your tools. I'm sorry. That's a conversation about the potency of your tools.
I'm sorry.
That's a conversation about the potency of your tools.
You can admit that these fundamental limitations exist,
but you don't have to draw the conclusion that they're constraining
in any finally hopeless manner.
Well, it's not just about the tools,
it's also about the nature of reality
that we are confronting.
There are, of course, people who are polyannists
who have this view that the world is on our side.
There's a benevolent God
or the forces of the universe are lined up
such that I lead a charmed life
and everything will go well for me.
There are people at the other end of the spectrum who
Are you the opposite the the fates are against me the gods hate me no matter what I do
The forces the government universe will just grind me down
That's got nothing to do with my tool set initially so to speak that's a metaphysical claim about the nature of the universe
Now when we do turn to the tool set,
if whatever your position is along the spectrum
of benevolence to malevolence,
there is the question about how much power I have
to craft my own tools to forge myself
into the kind of being that can take on life's challenges.
And here, I think postmodernism is dangerous
in two important respects. In my view,
the most important development of education, schooling, parenting, and so on, is giving students
and young people the critical thinking, the rational power to be able to understand the world,
to be able to conceptualize it, to know how to do the
experiments, to analyze the results, to sort out good truth claims from bullshit, and so on.
And so all of that cognitive development that can only come from a commitment to the idea that
the evidence matters, that doing the experiments matters, that being extrusioning
adenably honest with respect to the power of the arguments for and against
positions that one might argue or adopt, but that's absolutely important.
The development of a student's rational logical critical capacity is
fundamentally important and postmodernism is an assault on that.
And what that means is that in practice,
students do not develop that most important life skill.
And so put them out into the world
without the tools that they need.
And I think they are then more likely to feel disempowered.
They're more likely to feel overwhelmed.
And then we get the angry, despairing,
activist type of person that we see in larger numbers now.
Okay, so if the post modernists are concerned ethically with the reestablishment of genuine
power at the bottom of the power hierarchies, why do you think it's the case, if it is the case, and many
commentators have made this case, Jonathan Haight, among them, that the doctrines that the
postmodernists tend to be teaching young people seem to be so absolutely infantilizing and
and under mining rather than strengthening and increasing resilience. Is it that they're not interested at the individual level?
I mean, because it seems so paradoxical that these things are happening simultaneously.
Yeah, a couple of things on that.
One is that in addition to developing a person's rational capacity
We do need to develop their emotional capacity
Life is a capacity for a great adventure for great positivity
But as you emphasize there is also going to be a significant amount of pain and suffering
And so what we need to do is develop our emotional capacity for
Handling all of that.
Resilience is an important part of that.
One unfortunate part of the postmodern package though is that they are focusing on a very
narrow range of emotions, typically negative emotions, and they don't see those emotions
as having any connection to rationality or any connection to a response to an actual objective reality out there.
So the emotional life of human beings is both cramped and a mystery if you take the post-modern
framework seriously. And so I think what happens then is when those post-modern
become teachers or professors or in a position of authority,
it's a large amount of emotional communication
that is going on, but it's going to be
a negative rage-focused, despair-focused, cynical,
jaded-focused kind of emotionalism.
And to the extent that students pick up on that,
they're going to be turned off,
or if they have some predisposition toward that, they just get sucked into that emotional universe.
That speaks to Jonathan Heitz point that you're raising.
Let me just say, one thing that is striking to me is I find it interesting among our public
intellectuals that three of the most prominent people in the public intellectuals sphere are
yourself Jonathan Hyatt and Stephen Kinker and all three of you are professionally psychologists.
And I don't know, I think that that is accidental because what all three of you are doing in different
ways is noticing that philosophy, of course, is
a very abstract set of arguments and principles, but all of those do need to be operationalized
in actual living, breathing human beings.
And when you see how they are actually operationalized in human beings, a large part of what you're
doing is psychology.
So I think it's not accidental that psychologists are of significant
importance in the public intellectual space right now. So to speak to Jonathan Heitz
Point, I think what he is pointing out is that we are now into a second and third generation of postmoderns, and there's a devolution in the intellectual
quality of the movement, and that makes sense because if your first generation movement
is quite skeptical and relativistic, but nonetheless very educated as Rorkee, Dharidha, Fuku, Leo Tart, especially in my view, were, but the end conclusion of their position
is that we don't need to take rationality, logic, the quest for objectivity too seriously.
What will happen in the next generation then will be a whole generation of people with
PhDs who don't take logic rationality in the quest for
objectivity very seriously, instead they will be not developing those skill sets at a very
high level. So there will be a devolution, they will be more emphasizing emotionalism,
they will be more emphasizing activism, and then in the third generation it will be a further devolution.
So where do you see that going? Is that a self-defeating? Is it something that will end
of its own corridor? I think it is self-defeating intellectually and one of the things that people
who are intellectuals who have been following the arguments for a while notice is
This is just a recycling of arguments that I heard five years ago, ten years ago, twenty years ago
And so it becomes self-defeating in the sense that it fails to attract the ongoing interest of the smart, very active-minded people.
I think also that this is something built into human nature, and this is my great
optimism with young people when they come to university, however,
underprepared and damaged, they might be by their primary and high school education.
They are nonetheless particularly, I think, in North America still,
optimistic gung-ho, they believe that they
can make something of their lives. And when they start going into two classes, where the
professors in word and action and just in their physical bearing are communicating rather
messages of defeatism and synthesis, some students who are psychologically healthy will just avoid those classes.
They will go into fields that hold some promise of positivity for them.
They will be the terror of entrepreneurial fields.
The terror is that they may avoid university altogether.
Yeah, absolutely. Sure.
Yeah, so what's the point of going to wallowing about what a victim you are, what a bad person you are because
you have white skin or you're a male or whatever for four years.
I'm going to quit university and get on with living.
I do think there also will be corrective mechanisms in place to some extent universities
are driven by dollars and who is writing the big checks if it's
a million dollar donors when some terrible manifestation of political
correctness happens at their institution they won't write the million dollar
check the next year that will get noticed and that will be
communicated in various ways. So the you know the universities have their
problems but I am ultimately optimistic that they will
be able to heal themselves.
There are market mechanisms in place to...
So what kind of time span?
That's interesting.
I mean, I waver between optimism and pessimism because I feel that the strata of postmodernists is relatively young and relatively entrenched
and protected by tenure. And of course, I think ten years a good idea. And that they're
also unbelievably good at fomenting activism. I mean, I think the political surveys indicate
that only about 4% of the general
population who have views that might be regarded as radical Marxist slash postmodern. It's
a tiny minority. It's bigger than that in universities, but they swing beyond their weight.
They hit past their weight. And it's also, I think, because,
you know, serious academics, this is my impression, is that serious academics really ignored
the second rate postmodern difference for decades, feeling that the arguments that they were
making were weak enough so that they didn't even require a
Strong rebuttal. I mean even when Stephen Paker wrote his book
The blank slate, you know, I read that book and I thought
That it was an interesting book, but I thought Jesus
Dr. Panker No one's believed that people are blank slates for like 30 years. That's so far
out of date that it seems, it has a biological psychologist. It just seemed to me to be observed
that that case had to be even made. But I mean, he was obviously right about that. And I
was obviously very wrong about that. Yeah. Predictions are hard to make. And I think it goes back to we need better journalism
about the demographics of higher education
and what's going on there.
So is it 4%, is it 12%, is it 25%,
then this issue you're raising about punching above their weight,
that does seem to be true,
but how much above their weight are they punching?
Is the major problem in the classrooms, or is it a matter of, as we know, most academics don't
like Mickey work to a significant number. So, the first rate people are doing their real academic
work and they're trying to avoid committee work, But the second and third raiders, they don't mind committee work and they see it as a vehicle to power
within the university for them. So if the postmoderns are, as we like to think,
second or third-rate, that's a little bit unfair, not all of them are, but a higher
percentage of them doing the important committee work, then they have a certain
amount of power there. An looked part of the university demographics,
from my perspective, is student life,
where the residents,
the people who look after the residents of the hall,
and the entertainment, and deciding what student clubs
are authorized or not.
There's been a significant infiltration
of postmodernism in that area.
That's not on the academic side or only in direct. But if you look at orientation programs,
and again, we need better journalism here, but you find a significant number of them are devoting the whole
orientation week when the first year students are coming into lectures on privilege and
depression and whatever the buzzwords are, that also is an important issue as well.
Right, there was an article written in the Chronicle of Higher Education
excoriating faculties of education for producing precisely the kinds of
internal university activists that are pushing
exactly that kind of agenda.
That was very interesting.
Yes, the abilities of education.
I do some work in philosophy of education.
They are all over the map, but there has been a significant post-modernism being the
reigning philosophy of education. And then of course that has impact not just in higher education because that's training
the next generation of teachers.
One of my younger colleagues, a man named Andrew Colgan, recent PhD from Western University
of Western Ontario, in his dissertation was documenting the the significant demographic shift
Among Ontario high school teachers toward basically buying into a postmodern framework
And that's going to be a very important generational shift for Ontario
So what makes you like you talked about market forces and the corrective ability and and
And we spoke before we started this podcast about speaking about optimistic and positive elements, my movements.
I mean, so, well, I have two questions for you at least before we conclude.
And one is, you seem optimistic and positive. And so what do
you see as the root out of this? And what what will replace it? And like what's the time
span? Yes. Well, I think one thing that we are noticing is an increasing number of first
rich people who are now engaging the debate within higher education.
So you can mention someone like Steven Pinker who's not just doing academic psychology now
and said he's devoting resources to defending in a public intellectual sphere the enlightenment
project. Jonathan Hade also an excellent psychologist doing clinical work as well, but nonetheless is
formative in creating that heterodox academy bringing together academics from
a wide variety of political spectrum, but the positions, but nonetheless all
agreeing that academic freedom, free speech, and so forth are important.
The work that you're doing, stepping out onto the public space stage as well.
So there is a major uptick in very good academics
taking postmodernism and its offshoots seriously
and pushing back, and I think that augurs well.
I think there also is a financial cloud.
I think young students, when they come in, they do take a postmodernism course, but they
don't go back for more.
Or they plug into the student grapevine and they learn which courses to avoid.
And in many cases, the postmodern activist type professors, they are really ghettoized
in marginal departments.
They might be outsized in their voice,
but they're not attracting a huge number of students.
And on my view, the students that they are attracting
are ones who are already predisposed to that.
They're not necessarily conferring a large number.
It seems to me that the least invasive way of dealing
with the postmodernism, if it does have the negative attributes that we've been discussing,
is actually something like a market solution, which is to inform young people as to its essential nature and to help convince them that there are viable alternatives, like viable philosophical alternatives,
viable political alternatives, courses they could be taking that would enrich their lives instead
of enhancing their sense of victimization. And it seems like the safest route rather than political
intervention or some kind of attempt to radically change the structure of the universities, which seems to me to be more dangerous than useful.
And I'm very gung ho on the internet. The internet, of course, is just a tool can be used for glitter or ill, and there's a lot of crap, as we all know, on the internet.
But it also is the case that young, open-minded, hungry students, when they are at a university
and they're not getting the education that they want, they now have access to all sorts
of viewpoints and they are actively exploring them.
I'm sure you get hundreds of contacts.
I get lots of contacts from students from all over the world who come to me through the
internet and I know that that's a worldwide phenomenon. I also do think that there's lots of very interesting entrepreneurial experimentation
going on in higher education.
Some of it's driven by the cost demographics.
People asking the reasonable question, is it really worth a quarter million dollars to
get a good higher education at a traditional bricks and border university,
or should I spend just $100,000 and maybe get only a 75% quality education at an online
institution or some other vehicle.
So there's lots of experimentation that are going on there.
And of course, the technology is just getting better and better.
Instead of the only avenue being taking the universities on head on from the inside,
that battle has to be fought.
And some of us are doing it, but there will be a significant number of people who will
just avoid the universities altogether, and there will be new institutions that are created.
And that will be a market solution.
Do you know that 70, about 75% of the cumulative student debt in the United States is held
by women?
I did not know that.
And that it disproportionate number of those women are black.
So it turns out that it's so perverse, that the statistics are so perverse. And part of the explanation for that, it's not the total
explanation, is that these women were enticed or chose to enter disciplines where the probability
of making enough money over a reasonable span of your life, especially given the high interest rates that are associated with student debt is extraordinarily low.
So that's another strange reaction.
As a perverse unintended consequence, I was not aware of that statistic.
I was aware that this matches with my experience that about 60% of our university graduates are women compared to only about 40% male. So there's a demographic
shift there. But I was not aware of the racial component of that.
Yeah, so that's a very interesting unintended consequence. It's really, well, it's brutal,
you know, because these poor women are laboring under these debt loads that it looks like they're
never going to be able to clear. Okay, so that's optimism.
It's long-term optimism, but it's optimism.
And so that's good to hear.
Can I ask you a little bit about what your private, what your life has been like, let's
say, over the last couple of years, as you've used social media more and as your work has become much more disseminated and discussed
publicly. What's being the pluses and the minuses for you and what's changed for you? Yeah,
overall pluses away the minuses definitely. The main minus says been that it's cut a lot into my writing time. In some
ways, majorly, I'm a stereotypical nerd. My ideal day is to go to the library with my
computer and read and write with a stack of books. And I envisioned my professor's life
as being dominated by that. But certainly for the last couple of years, my writing and thinking time has been lessened.
The other major negative just has been, just to crack, you have to put up with people
who are on various hobby horses who disagree with you, but who don't have social skills
or to know how to have a fruitful discussion. So they send you
ad hominem emails and just resort to insults because you disagree with them.
So there's been a certain steady stream of that but part of my learning curve has
been just to be able to ignore that or filter that out and focus on the
positive responses and the critical responses that are raising good questions.
I did wanna mention, if I can plug,
I have an open college podcast series
and I've got two podcasts in the work
where I'm taking up the the the serious
and in some cases good criticisms
that have been raised of my work.
Oh good.
I'm working on on those as well.
That's just part of the ongoing
fun, scholarly, back and forth
that should be going on.
And while I am down on postmodernism,
I should say that I do think
it's an important part of any person's
education to at least, for some time,
consider the most skeptical
and nihilistic arguments that are out there that postmodernism should have a seat at the
table in any person's education.
And so it really should be a three or four way debate that's going on there and students
need to process those arguments for themselves. The other pluses are that I do enjoy travel.
So in addition to my normal academic conferencing
and academic lectures, I've been giving some public
intellectual lectures and interacting
with the general public, more thinking public,
and that's been a lot of fun.
It's actually been very encouraging to realize
how many smart, knowledgeable people there are
out there in the world living full lives, doing very interesting things.
But they also have an interest in intellectual matters.
And you can have a very fond conversation with them about Nietzsche or Marx or the current
state of higher education.
So I found that the tourism part that comes with the travel
and just interacting with people that I never would have
interacted to be very pleasurable.
The other big plus has been, since I am a professor,
I just love young students in their first second year
of university when they realize how big the intellectual world is and how exciting
can be that when they come alive intellectually and then having a lot more students from around
the world who will email me or Facebook me with very interesting questions or they have their own
podcast and when I can I'll have a you know 45 or 50 minute conversation with them on their podcast.
So just interacting with a lot more students from other parts of the world than I otherwise
would have.
So the pluses have been great.
The thing is about the public exposure and the social media exposure that's so interesting
is that the people who come to listen to you only
come because they want to listen to you.
It's a real pure form of the university, because there's no compulsion as there is with
say mandatory classes and grades and so on in universities.
And there is this tremendous public hunger for philosophical discourse
that's really been completely in some sense undiscovered up until now and it's massive.
And that's why I think optimistically I am or ultimately I am optimistic because I think it
is built into human nature to want to be vigorous, to engage with the world, and since we're
such a smart species, to engage with the world intellectually.
So young people in their teens, when they are becoming more fully aware of themselves
as independent of their parents and that their whole life is ahead and they're preparing
for life, they do have this hunger, and it's beautiful to see it activated.
Yeah, well, obviously all the controversy that surrounded your work hasn't soured you
in the least on the intellectual enterprise.
It sounds like quite the contrary.
Well, what are you working on now?
Like, I know you're having a hard time writing, but like over the next
five years, let's say you've got ambitions. What would you like to see?
I have schedules starting the end of this academic year, mid May, a significant amount more
of writing time. And so I'm I'm I'm making progress and I'm optimistic that by the end of
this calendar year, I'll be almost done this next book. What I'm doing is focusing on the positive. The postmodernism book is negative. The Nietzsche
and the Nazis book is negative going into some dark philosophical and political territory.
But to put it positively, what are the positive philosophical issues and positions that need to be developed to reinvigorate
the enlightenment, to correct its deficiencies, to make people realize that the postmodern
arguments are powerful, but they're powerfully based on some often easy philosophical issues
or mistakes to make.
Very subtle.
So my value added is as a philosopher,
the way I'm going to, in part package,
this is to say that we do have huge debates
along any number of dimensions about politics and so on.
But in fact, most of our debates about politics
are not at all about politics.
They are about underlying philosophical issues.
So for example, we're having debates right now about the proper political status of, say,
transgender individuals.
But we're spending very little time actually talking about the politics of it instead.
We are having arguments about human nature
and to what extent things are fixed,
causally into what extent things are a matter of human volition,
what things are subjective, what things are objective,
and so on.
And so really we are having philosophical arguments,
hopefully philosophical arguments
that should be informed by biology.
But even that is itself a philosophical debate because some people want to say we should
approach this as a scientific method type of question, look at the facts, look at the
experiments, and others have a more free-floating ideological commitment that is to say they're
operating on a different epistemology.
So really what we're doing is we're having debates about epistemology and human
nature, not really debates about politics. So then politics is just a manifestation of that.
So then my hopeful professional value added is to bring clarity and some fresh perspectives on
those philosophical debates. I just just saying one more thing.
I just played philosophy as a whole number of false alternatives that have been entrenched
in the discipline for generations.
And in many cases, if you can notice two apparently opposed arguments, but realize they have a shared premise,
and in often cases that shared premise is implicit, then asking what the alternatives to that implicit
premise would be once you make it explicit can be very illuminating. So I'm working that territory
a lot. Well, it's interesting, you know, that maybe one of the consequences is that out of the,
let's call it rather murky darkness of moral relativism and postmodernism and the claim that power
is the fundamental motivation of human beings. I mean, these are very pessimistic philosophical statements taken almost to all those dudes think to their logical extreme
That maybe what'll happen is that out of that will come something like a
philosophy
That's genuinely optimistic without being naive
Yeah, exactly that's nicely put I'm
reminded of a line from the Roman poet Horus, who was reflecting on some of the skeptical and nihilistic trends of his time, where they were denying the pitch fork, ever she will return. Right. So the optimistic
return is what we're working on now. Right. Well, and there does seem to be, I would say,
a tremendous hunger for that. You know, one of the things I've been struck by, and I'm sure you
see this in your teaching, is that it, it's amazing. You know, I usually begin my lectures on a fairly pessimistic note,
detailing out the problems of human nature and society,
and to some degree the natural world,
trying to make a vicious case for the,
in some sense, the atrocity of life.
And it means that there's nothing hidden in some sense, the atrocity of life. And it means that there's nothing hidden in some sense
when the argument begins.
And then I try to make a case that despite that,
you know, we have within us the capacity to transcend that.
And then that capacity to transcend that,
the atrocity of life is actually more powerful and that you can derive an optimism
out of the pessimism, out of the pessimism that's even more optimistic because of the depth
of the pessimism. You know, like, and you can tell students, look, you guys, you've got real
problems to deal with. It's no wonder that you're suffering from the existential dilemmas that you're suffering
from.
They're real, but that doesn't mean that there isn't a set of viable solutions and maybe
a fairly large set of viable solutions that can be, that you can learn and that you can
practice and that you can engage in that make a genuine difference to your life and a
genuine difference to the life of the people around you. And that this is even more real than the reality of the relativism and the nihilism
and the pessimism. People respond, I've been aligning that especially with the idea of responsibility,
you know, that it's possible to find the sustaining meaning in your life through the adoption
of a substantive responsibility as you can manage.
And it's really quite remarkable how ready people are for that idea.
It really usually reduces the audience's to silence, to speak of that. Yeah, well that's all of that touching on the profound themes that human beings do need
to engage with. My approach is typically a different, particularly with my first-year students,
where reading of them is a lot of them are coming into a university feeling somewhat constrained. Sometimes they're
in university because they have to be in university or they have the sense that their lives are
largely predetermined or that things have been mapped out either by their parents or expectation
of certain social forces or whatever and getting them to see that the world is a lot more open to them. There are a lot
more possibilities than that they have more power to shape their own destinies than they otherwise
might have been taught. So higher education is transformative in the sense of liberating them from
of liberating them from constraints that they felt themselves to be put in. And I found that that has been useful in tapping into the hunger that we are both talking
about because that can be suppressed.
But once they get a taste of it, then in fact, they are free agents that the world is a
lot more open-ended than other people might have been telling them.
They start to drink it up.
Well, that was the great thing about university for me.
I came from a small town and went to increasingly large universities.
Every time I made a transition, the sense that the world was opening up to me continued to increase.
And it was unbelievably liberating and lightening.
And apart from that, what makes postmodernism unsettling,
because it really is a cramped intellectual vision,
but it also tends to put people into smaller and smaller categories.
You're only a member of this group and you're an exemplar of it and your identity has been
shaped by forces beyond your control and you can't engage with other cultures and other
individuals except on the basis of hostility, which just means people retrench.
So it's a very closing in kind of intellectual movement.
So the optimism and the romance and the adventure and
the sense that you can in fact take charge of your own life and make yourself and the world a
better place. That's the point that we need to emphasize. But I don't think so we do need better
intellectual tools for that. Well, I do think students too like Like, my, one of the reasons I've always loved teaching undergraduates is because even those who are who have that brittle and, let's say, thin-skinned cynicism,
sort of the prematurely intellectually hopeless have, underneath that, this dynamism of youth that wants exactly to know that
that call to adventure exists and that they will respond with unbelievable enthusiasm to
any message that, yeah, to any message that puts that idea across in a believable manner and that takes them
seriously. The other thing that struck me too, that it's really saddening.
I've talked to hundreds of people after my lectures now and it's almost
inconceivable the degree to which people are starving for encouragement.
How little they get and how little it takes to make a massive difference in their life.
Just to say to them, look, you are a sovereign individual of divine value, the cornerstone
of the community, and that's the fundamental presupposition of our society.
It happens to be true in that you can put your life together with truth and courage and things
will work out better and even more importantly than that, whether it works out or not, even
more importantly than that, that is the adventure and destiny of your life and it actually matters.
And people are so dying, they're dying for that idea.
Yep, that's beautifully put. So thanks for saying that.
Well, look, I'd like to know when you put up those podcasts that respond to the criticisms of your
book. So if you would be kind enough to let me know that I'm happy to do so.
Well, I would love to publicize them. It might be an opportunity, again, for us to have another
conversation about the, because I'm very interested in the criticisms, you know, because I relied on
your book a fair bit in my discussion of postmodernism. It's not an area of expertise of mine.
You know, I was one of those academics who tended to ignore it, not entirely, but while I was
pursuing my own studies, but your book was extremely useful, and you know, it's not necessarily the case
that because I'm not as philosophically versed as I might be that I can evaluate all the criticisms.
And so I would definitely like to know more about that and to know more about your response.
So please do let me know. I will let you know when this airs on YouTube and as a podcast,
I don't know when that will be because my scheduling isn't set for the release of such things,
but this isn't a discussion that has a time bound in any particular matter.
So that shouldn't matter too much.
And look, I really appreciate you taking the time to talk to me again.
I always find our conversations extremely illuminating.
Great.
I appreciate the invitation and spending time with you as
well. It's good fun. Great. Great.
And well, good luck. Good luck with your ambitions. And I wish
you even more success in the public domain, because I think
that what you're doing is extremely helpful and brought
Thank you to the is mutual, absolutely.
All right, well, and hopefully we'll have a chance to meet at some point in
the not too distant future. Perfect. Very good to see you. You too. All right, bye for now. Bye-bye.
If you found this conversation meaningful, you might think about picking up dad's books,
Maps of Meaning, The Architecture of Belief, or his newer bestseller, 12 Rules for Life,
and Antidote to Keras, a much easier read.
But that's not the quality thing.
It's just simpler than Maps of Meaning because Maps of Meaning is insanely difficult.
Both of these works delve much deeper into the topics covered in the Jordan B. Peterson
podcast.
See JordanB.Peterson.com for audio, e-book, and text links, or pick up the books at your
favorite bookseller.
The next episode is Dad's lecture at the first Ontario concert hall in Hamilton, Ontario,
recorded on July 20, 2018.
Every one of his lectures I hear, I learn something different.
It's amazing.
I hope you guys enjoy and I'll talk to you again next week.
Follow me on my YouTube channel, Jordan B. Peterson,
on Twitter, at Jordan B. Peterson,
on Facebook, at Dr. Jordan B. Peterson,
and at Instagram, at Jordan.b. Peterson.
Details on this show, access to my blog, information
about my tour dates and other events, and my list of recommended books can be found on my website
Jordanbe Peterson.com. My online writing programs designed to help people straighten out their
pasts, understand themselves in the present, and develop a sophisticated vision and strategy for the future can be found at selfauthoring.com, that selfauthoring.com.
From the Westwood One Podcast Network.