Theories of Everything with Curt Jaimungal - Free Will Explained by World’s Top Intellectuals

Episode Date: December 8, 2023

YouTube Link: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=SSbUCEleJhg&t=9315sIn our first ontoprism, we take a look back at FREE WILL across the years at Theories of Everything. If you have suggestions for future... ontoprism topics, then comment below.TIMESTAMPS:- 00:00:00 Introduction- 00:02:58 Michael Levin- 00:08:51 David Wolpert (Part 1)- 00:13:48 Donald Hoffman, Joscha Bach- 00:33:10 Stuart Hameroff- 00:38:47 Claudia Passos- 00:40:27 Wolfgang Smith- 00:42:50 Bernardo Kastrup- 00:45:23 Matt O'Dowd- 01:19:06 Anand Vaidya- 01:28:52 Chris Langan, Bernardo Kastrup- 01:44:27 David Wolpert (Part 2)- 01:51:37 Scott Aaronson- 01:59:47 Nicolas Gisin- 02:16:52 David Wolpert (Part 3)- 02:32:39 Brian Keating, Lee Cronin- 02:42:55 Joscha Bach- 02:46:07 Karl Friston- 02:49:28 Noam Chomsky (Part 1)- 02:55:06 John Vervaeke, Joscha Bach- 03:13:27 Stephen Wolfram- 03:32:46 Jonathan Blow- 03:40:08 Noam Chomsky (Part 2)- 03:49:38 Thomas Campbell- 03:55:14 John Vervaeke- 04:02:41 James Robert Brown- 04:13:42 Anil Seth- 04:17:37 More ontoprisms coming...NOTE: The perspectives expressed by guests don't necessarily mirror my own. There's a versicolored arrangement of people on TOE, each harboring distinct viewpoints, as part of my endeavor to understand the perspectives that exist. THANK YOU: To Mike Duffy, of https://dailymystic.org for your insight, help, and recommendations on this channel. - Patreon: / curtjaimungal  (early access to ad-free audio episodes!) - Crypto: https://tinyurl.com/cryptoTOE - PayPal: https://tinyurl.com/paypalTOE - Twitter:  / toewithcurt   - Discord Invite:  / discord   - iTunes: https://podcasts.apple.com/ca/podcast... - Pandora: https://pdora.co/33b9lfP - Spotify: https://open.spotify.com/show/4gL14b9... - Subreddit r/TheoriesOfEverything:  / theoriesofeverything   - TOE Merch: https://tinyurl.com/TOEmerch LINKS MENTIONED:  • Free Will Debate: "Is God A Taoist?" ...   • Unveiling the Mind-Blowing Biotech of...   • David Wolpert: Free Will & No Free Lu...   • Donald Hoffman Λ Joscha Bach: Conscio...   • Stuart Hameroff: Penrose & Fractal Co...   • Wolfgang Smith: Beyond Non-Dualism   • Escaping the Illusion: Bernardo Kastr...   • Matt O'Dowd: Your Mind vs. The Univer...   • Anand Vaidya: Moving BEYOND Non-Dualism   • Should You Fear Death? Bernardo Kastr...   • David Wolpert: Monotheism Theorem, Un...   • Nicolas Gisin: Time, Superdeterminism...   • David Wolpert: Monotheism Theorem, Un...   • Brian Keating Λ Lee Cronin: Life in t...   • Joscha Bach: Time, Simulation Hypothe...   • Karl Friston: Derealization, Consciou...   • Noam Chomsky   • Joscha Bach Λ John Vervaeke: Mind, Id...   • Stephen Wolfram: Ruliad, Consciousnes...   • Jonathan Blow: Consciousness, Game De...   • Noam Chomsky   • Thomas Campbell: Ego, Paranormal Psi,...   • Thomas Campbell: Remote Viewing, Spea...   • John Vervaeke: Psychedelics, Evil, & ...   • James Robert Brown: The Continuum Hyp...   • Anil Seth: Neuroscience of Consciousn...  

Transcript
Discussion (0)
Starting point is 00:00:00 Free will is a representation in the system that it's made a decision, and the decision is being made on the best understanding of what's correct. The dynamics that break up that undifferentiated ocean of potential cells into one, two, or three, or more, it can go different ways. Out of this ocean of potentiality, these cells, you know, 50,000 cells, and each of them will have specific goals. Objectivists say that these probabilities are pointing to some real thing in the world. There is some real random generator in the world. And subjectivists say, no, these are just degrees of belief. What is free will? How is it different than agency? What constitutes a willful and an unwillful action? How do you define yourself as
Starting point is 00:00:42 separate from the world in order for you to even say that you act on the environment? What does physics have to say about all of this? And what are some of the alternatives to the classic compatibilism versus libertarian notions of free will? These are questions explored today by the approximately 25 or so guests of Theories of Everything. For those of you who are new to this channel, my name is Kurt Jaimungal, and what we usually do is explore theories of everything in the physics sense from a mathematical perspective. However, this is also a philosophical channel, investigating the fundamental laws, whatever they may be. You can think of it as an analysis from multiple perspectives on the largest looming questions we have, while also exploring an experiential approach. We've been having issues monetizing the channel with sponsorship, so if you'd like to contribute to the continuation of Theories of Everything, then you can donate through PayPal, Patreon,
Starting point is 00:01:28 or through cryptocurrency. Your support goes a long way in ensuring the longevity and quality of this channel. Thank you. Links are in the description. What you're about to watch is a new format called an OntoPrism, where instead of having comprehensive interviews with a single guest on a variety of subjects, we're flipping that and diving into a singular topic on a variety of subjects, we're flipping that and diving into a singular topic with a variety of guests. Think of it like a buffet where there's
Starting point is 00:01:50 a smorgasbord of variegated ideas, and you can sample and choose the one you like best, or create your own Weltanschauung by sampling from the assortment. Hearing opinions on a specific theme is strewn across the over 100 podcasts over the past three years on the Theories of Everything channel, though for convenience, they're co-located here. The guests in this episode include Michael Levin, Carl Friston, David Walpart, Donald Hoffman, Josha Bach, Stuart Hameroff, Wolfgang Smith, Bernardo Kastrup, Matt O'Dowd from PBS Spacetime, Chris Langan, Nicholas Jissen, Brian Keating, Noam Chomsky, Stephen Wolfram, Jonathan Blow, There's also Anand Vaidya and Scott Aronson. This ontoprism on free will is in preparation for a mountainous interview with the legendary Robert Sapolsky on this very issue.
Starting point is 00:02:41 If you enjoy this format, then you can suggest other topics for future episodes in the comment section. Now enjoy this peregrination into free will. Well, again, what I'd actually like to do is back up a little bit and put some of what you just said into very simple active inference language, if I see something happening on my Markov blanket, on my interface with the world, then I always have the question, did I do that or did the world do that? Where the world means everything outside me. where the world means everything outside me. And in a sense, the answer is always the world did it. So the question becomes, did the world do that in response to something I did to it?
Starting point is 00:03:40 Or did it just do it? Not in consequence of any of my actions. And so one gets immediately to this kind of babbling scenario that we've talked about many times, in which an infant or a robot or some system is trying to figure out by measuring correlations whether the world's inputs to it have anything to do with its inputs to the world. And just asking that question requires enormous representative capacity because one has to represent one's actions and represent them pretty well in time and one has to
Starting point is 00:04:35 have a good memory to represent enough actions to get any kind of statistical support for drawing an inference about correlation. And that memory has to be represented as a memory, any agent at all that's trying to get a model off the ground, which in a sense gets back to the question that Mike asked early, early on about how does this all start? early, early on about how does this all start? Maybe it starts with babbling in very simple systems. You know, I was thinking recently, this whole issue of how many agents are there and where is the border between the agent and the world and how do you self-model that border is a
Starting point is 00:05:41 fascinating topic. And there's an amazing developmental model for this, which is which is that, you know, we often talk about one embryo, and the embryo does this and the embryo does that. But actually, what happens at the beginning, let's say, for example, an amniote embryos is that there's a there's a flat blast disc, which has just a few cell layers thick. So it's kind of think of it like a like a Frisbee, and it just has a few cell layers. And normally, what has to happen is that one point in this disc breaks symmetry and then organizes the primary axis of the first embryo and basically tells all the other cells, don't
Starting point is 00:06:14 do it because I'm doing it. And that's how you end up with one embryo. Now, that process is very easily perturbed and many people have done it. I used to do it in my graduate work. And what you can do is, if you perturb that process, that initial blasted is that undifferentiated sort of pool of of cells, which are these sort of proto low level proto proto agents, that pool can break up into not one
Starting point is 00:06:37 embryo, but actually multiple. And so you can have so I did this in bird embryos, and you can have twins and chicken and duck and things like this, you can have in humans, humans have exactly the same structure. You can get them head to head. You can get them side by side. You can get all sorts of geometries. You can get triplets. You can get multiple individuals emerging by different partitions of this really kind
Starting point is 00:06:59 of medium, this particulate medium where you have a bunch of cells and you don't know ahead of time how many individuals at the level of, how many larger individuals, so embryos, are going to arise from this medium because the dynamics by which, and that's local activation and long-range inhibition and things like that, the dynamics that break up that undifferentiated ocean of potential selves into one, two, or three or more selves is actually um it's very dynamic it can it can go different ways and then you get interesting interesting things like this so for example you might know that human conjoined twins that are you know sort of stuck together side to side one of the twins often has left right asymmetry defects and it's because when you have two twins
Starting point is 00:07:40 side by side the cells in the, both twins can't quite agree on who they belong to. Are they the right side of this twin or are they the left side of that twin? And both twins think they belong to them, but in fact, they're overlapping. They're the same cells. And so one side will have correct left and right. The other side will have like two rights, for example. And this ends up giving one of the twins laterality defects with respect to heart and gut patterning. And so so their models each twins as as the collective of cells tries to compute uh things like which which where things are and what's left and what's right and so on their models can disagree with each other they can
Starting point is 00:08:16 they can draw the boundary between self and world in different ways and you can have these sort of disputes over certain areas as to where who they actually belong to and and so so i'm just i'm just incredibly interested in this in this process of of emerging of individualization so to speak out of this like ocean of of potentiality these cells you know 50 000 cells and some number of individuals at the um at the embryo level will be formed and each of them will have specific goals in morphospace each of them will try to achieve very specific morphologies. And you don't know ahead of time how many there were going to be. All right, we've just been diving into the interplay between the self and the world with Michael Levin, Carl Friston, and Chris Fields. Again, every link is in the
Starting point is 00:08:58 description. They dissect the process of self-modeling and individualization, which lead us naturally to our next guest, David Wolpart, who challenges us with a monotheistic perspective on free will. If they both have free will, at least once. That's incredibly interesting. So does an impossibility result against more than one god? Yes. Yep, that's why it's called the monotheism theorem. It might be that we are in a universe in which you could have one God, who knows? I'm not going to go there. I mean, my personal conclusions on it are that in our particular universe, no.
Starting point is 00:09:36 But there is no reason why I think the concept itself is not inherently self-contradictory like the past is demon. There could be universes. I would say there's no sense in which we can actually rule them out, in fact, in which there are deities. But there cannot be any of them that support two deities. So we might be in one of those ones in which there is a deity. Who knows? But we can't be in one which is more than one. And when you say deity, there can't be two omniscient deities?
Starting point is 00:10:09 There can't be two that have free will. Ah. So you could have one where there's Zeus and Hera, but Zeus can always be in a particular state that restricts Hera for being in some of her particular states. In that sense, she does not have free will of him. At one particular time, one particular state of Zeus, it's just not going to be any possible road line in any of the universe, in our universe, in which Hera is in one of her particular states. There's some limitation. My being in one particular state at one particular time causes a restriction on the possible states that you could be in at that time. And if that's true, then we have no free will.
Starting point is 00:10:57 Have you heard of Norton's Dome? Norton's Dome. I think I did a while ago, ringing a bell, but I can't bring it up. Sure. It's a thought experiment about Newtonian mechanics, and it's to show that Newtonian mechanics isn't deterministic, even though it's often said it is. And the reason is, there are certain configurations you can set up such that there's not a unique answer to the differential equations. You know, ordinarily in physics, just for people to know, one of the reasons why mathematicians quibble with physicists is that physicists hand wave and gloss over many details. And so one of them is whenever we have an ordinary differential equation, we tend to say there's uniqueness in existence.
Starting point is 00:11:38 However, that's contingent on something called the Lipschitz continuity. And if you don't have Lipschitz continuity, you don't necessarily have a unique solution. So you basically set up a certain situation with a ball on a dome, and the equation for the dome is fairly simple. It's almost like a parabola. And then it turns out one solution is it stays there forever, zero velocity initially. And then another solution is at some point t, and the time t is not specified, it goes down some route, and any one of them so that's extremely interesting let's imagine we live in a newtonian world is that related to free will would you say or is that not related to free will that's something different i know a free will forget
Starting point is 00:12:14 about the sense of intention interacting with the laws of nature to produce that effect yeah the norton's dome it's also um i think it was actually sabine, who has one of her FQXI essays that she points out that chaos is, in some sense, it can be a much stronger phenomenon that people understand, that you can set up physical systems in which the chaos is to such a degree that actually past a certain point in time, you cannot, it is not defined, but the state of the system will be after that. So that's, I think that's the context in which I ran across it. It's also, there are related things, the work that goes back to two people called Porel and Richards. Those were physicists who as well known that, for example, the three body problem, where even if you do, so there you do have the standard, there's just continuity and so on, you've got gravitational attraction and so on, you can set it up to be what's called a universal Turing machine. You basically, what you do is you encode the input tape to that Turing machine
Starting point is 00:13:18 into the actual precise initial conditions of these three bodies. the actual precise initial conditions of these three bodies. And then by reading the appropriate bits of the state of the system at some future time, you can figure out what that universal Turing machine state of its tape would be at that time. What this means is that you can feed in a configuration that's actually the halting problem, so that that physical system, in fact, it violates the Church-Turing thesis. That physical system, its state in the future would not be computable. All right, now having just gone through the monotheistic lens with David Walpart, we're pivoting to Donald Hoffman's cognitive neuroscientific perspective.
Starting point is 00:14:01 Also, Josje Bak joins Donald Hoffman. neuroscientific perspective. Also, Josje Bak joins Donald Hoffman. In a physicalist framework, which, so now I'll just talk about what most of my cognitive neuroscience peers think, right? Most of them assume that physical systems are fundamental. Neural activity causes all our behavior. And in that case, there can be a fiction of, a useful fiction of free will, but it's really just going to be a useful fiction. If I do something, it's really my neurons with the neural activity that did it. And there is a sense in which you can say, I chose to do it because actually neurons are part of me. So I think that's the point of view that Dan Dennett takes, for example, on this.
Starting point is 00:14:52 And Sam Harris replies on that. He says, well, yeah, I also grow my fingernails. I'm not sure that I'm doing that by free will. that I'm doing that by free will. So it's not real clear that just because my neurons are doing it, I have free will, just in the same sense that I'm not using free will to grow my fingernails. So Sam would say there's no such thing as free will, if you're a physicalist.
Starting point is 00:15:19 Dan Dennett would say I'm a physicalist, and there is this important notion of free will. say I'm a physicalist and there is this important notion of free will. I think that, of course, space-time isn't fundamental. And so that we have to completely think outside of that box altogether. And as scientists, we have to say up front what our hypotheses, what our axioms or fundamental assumptions are, and be very clear about them up front. These conscious agents in the mathematics, they get certain inputs. We call them experiences that they have. And then there's something called the Markovian kernel
Starting point is 00:16:01 that describes what actions they take and those actions affect the experiences of other conscious agents. So, that's just the mathematics that my team has written down. It's a very simple notion of a Markovian dynamics of conscious agents interacting. And it's not in a physicalist framework. We're assuming that this is in its own world, right? These are conscious agents and and that's the foundation space and time are not the foundation conscious agents so conscious experiences and interactions of conscious agents are the foundational notion and so then the question is how shall we understand the probabilities so if i get a particular experience that that comes into a conscious agent
Starting point is 00:16:46 and it then probabilistically affects the experience of other agents how shall i understand that probability that it shall i understand it as as a free will choice or or what and you know I could say I refuse to answer the question there's a probability there and that's as far as I go with the theory this agent so I leave that probability as just
Starting point is 00:17:16 where my theory stops where I say in some sense wherever we see a probability in a theory that's where explanation stops right that's basically explanation stops, right? That's basically saying, I don't know. So, whenever, so I would say this, whenever in a scientific theory, you see probabilities coming up, you're seeing the theory say, this is where I halt, this is where my explanation stops. And there are two major approaches toward
Starting point is 00:17:48 understanding those probabilities, the objectivist and subjectivist, two probabilities, right? So objectivists say that these probabilities are pointing to some real thing in the world. There is some real random generator in the world. And subjectivists say, no, these are just degrees of belief. Whenever you see probabilities, you're only talking about degrees of belief. But in either case, explanation stops, right? How do I come to that belief? Well, I can only tell you probabilities. What is that random objective process? I don't know, but I can just tell you probabilities.
Starting point is 00:18:34 And so really, whenever you see probabilities in a scientific theory, and they're all over the place, I read that as saying, here's where explanation stops and our theories halt. And if we want to go further, we're going to have to unpack that probability into some deeper theory. So if I say that it's free will in the case of the conscious agents, then, I mean, in some sense that's just words what what
Starting point is 00:19:08 what theory has is the probabilities and it has no further explanation so if I say if I call the probability of free will
Starting point is 00:19:15 then I I mean I can call it that but but I haven't really done much to give much insight into the notion of free will free will
Starting point is 00:19:23 then becomes a primitive and and maybe that's what I want to do. I want to say this is where explanation stops and so free will is primitive. So these probabilities are free will and I agree to that that's where my theory stops, that I can do no further. Now what's interesting in the conscious agent dynamics that we're working on is that any group of conscious agents together also satisfy the definition of a conscious agent.
Starting point is 00:19:57 And so they are a conscious agent. So any conscious agents interacting are also conscious agents. So in the theory, there's one conscious agent. Because if you take all of them together they form one conscious agent but then there are as many if you're computational there's only countable number of them or in my case i don't know if it may be an uncountable number of of conscious agents but what's interesting is that the you unpack this probability in the markovian kernel. There could be one big probability for the one agent, but you can unpack that into all these dynamical systems
Starting point is 00:20:31 interacting conscious agents with their own probabilities and their own kernels. And what's interesting is that you could then give, in some sense, an unpacking of the notion of free will in that way. You could say, well, yeah, the one agent has free will and this probability, but I can actually do some non-trivial unpacking of that notion in this sort of recursive unwinding of those probabilities throughout the network. So there is the possibility here of, I mean, ultimately, there will be a primitive notion of free will that is just primitive and not explained. But given that one, I can explain all these other free wills sort of interacting, arising from this most primitive notion of free will in a non-trivial way.
Starting point is 00:21:17 But once again, I would point out something that I see all the time in scientific theories. No theory in science will ever explain everything. And I would love to see if Josje agrees or disagrees. I'll just state to make a strong claim. There cannot be a theory of everything because every theory has to make assumptions, and those assumptions are not explained, they're assumed. It's just that simple. Okay, am I correct in my summary of your views on free will, that if in a physical theory you
Starting point is 00:21:54 have probability, now some of that probability is just due to our ignorance, but if there's a fundamental probability, you can just say, well, that's indicating that the theories break down, we just don't know. Or you can say that there's something underneath producing those and that which is underneath the probabilities is what you're calling free will. Is that correct or is that off? Right. So, if I'm a physicalist, I'll say that that probability is due to some process that I can say no more about, but there's some process that generates this stuff. It's not free will, it's just a physical process that I don't know. But if I'm taking consciousness to be fundamental, then it's an interesting move to say that probability can be interpreted as
Starting point is 00:22:36 free will. Now, of course, I'm not explaining anything. I'm just putting the notion free will, I'm just putting the notion free will, the word free will on it, right? I see. And free will becomes just a primitive notion as well. So that's where my explanation stops. And the most unpacking I can do is that recursive unpacking that I mentioned, which is an interesting unpacking. But ultimately, there's this primitive notion of free will that I have nothing further to say about. there's this primitive notion of free will that I have nothing further to say about. But I think that that's not a problem specific to this theory. The last thing I was saying was that that's endemic to all scientific theories. Every scientific theory will have miracles
Starting point is 00:23:16 at its foundation. By miracles, I mean assumptions that are taken for granted and not explained. If you explain them, then you have a deeper theory with new assumptions that explain those assumptions but the new assumptions aren't explained. And so, in this sense, science can never have a theory of everything because science theories always have assumptions and the assumptions are what you don't explain. Joshua, I know Donald said quite a Donald said there are quite a few elements to pick from there. We are interlocking
Starting point is 00:23:50 claims, but let's address them. First of all, I don't know whether there can be one theory of everything because my reasoning is not tight enough to make that proof one way or the other. So at this point, I have to remain agnostic
Starting point is 00:24:05 because from where I stand, it seems to be possible that there can be a theory of everything, and it seems to be possible that there cannot. From a computationalist perspective, whenever you have a set of observations that is finite, you will be able to construct a computational model that explains how to make such patterns. So in principle, there can always be a theory of everything that you observed.
Starting point is 00:24:32 That's something that I cannot, that I don't see a way around this. So this seems to be sound to me, and I think that can be formally proven, but it seems to be almost trivial that it's too proven. So it's more interesting. The question is, can you narrow this down to a single one, to one theory of everything? You will be always stuck with infinitely many theories of everything, where most of these theories will be super inelegant and redundant and basically
Starting point is 00:24:58 recordings of your observations. Or will there be one theory that is the most elegant and explains everything deeply and wraps it up? And of course, if you think about the space of all theories and think of them as things that you can do in a language and in which you can define truth. And if you realize that the languages in which you can define truth consistent, these are the computational languages. It turns out that all your models are going to be automata and that you can sort the space of automata by the length of their definitions so it also seems that in principle it should be possible to find the shortest automaton between to every pair of automata that you can construct and can up with now the question is
Starting point is 00:25:39 what's your search procedure for all the possible automata? Do you have a search procedure that you can hope that terminates? And this is not a question of whether it's mathematically possible, but whether it's efficient. So is there an efficient strategy to find a theory of everything that is the shortest one? And so far, we haven't found one. And it relates to what AI is doing in machine learning when it tries to identify what's going on in the domain. So in principle, we can always be sure that we could be a brain in a vat and everything is just a nefarious conspiracy that is playing out.
Starting point is 00:26:19 And because we cannot exclude this, we can never be sure that our theory of everything is the best theory that could exist of things. So that's obviously the case. But if we take out this single thing and make the assumption that reality is not a conspiracy, I think then it starts to look a lot brighter. Let's get to the notion of free will. I think that free will is tied into the notion of agency. And the best explanation of what an agent is that I found so far is that an agent is a control system that is intrinsically combined with its own setpoint generator. A control system is a notion from cybernetics. It means you have some system like a thermostat
Starting point is 00:27:06 that is making a measurement using sensors for instance the temperature in the room and that has effectors by which it can change the dynamics of the system so the effector would be a switch that turns the heating on and off and the system that's being regulated is the temperature in the room and the temperature in the room is disturbed by the environment. And a simple thermostat will only act on its present measurement and then translate this present measurement using a single parameter into whether it should switch or not. And depending on choosing that parameter well, you have a more efficient regulation or not. But if you want to be more efficient, you need to model the environment and the dynamics of the system
Starting point is 00:27:47 and maybe the dynamics of the sensory system and the actuator itself. And you can do this. It means that you model the future of the regulation based on past observations. So if you endow the controller with the ability to make a model of the future
Starting point is 00:28:02 and use this control model to fine-tune the actions of the controller, it means that a controller now is more than a thermostat. It's not going to just optimize the temperature in the next frame, but it's going to optimize the integral of the temperature over a long time span. So it basically takes a long expectation horizon, the further it goes, the better probably. And then it tries to minimize all the temperature deviations from the ideal temperature from the set point over that time span. This means that depending on the fidelity and detail of the model
Starting point is 00:28:34 of its environment and its interaction with the environment in itself, it's going to be better and better if it assumes that there are trajectories in the world that are the result of its own decisions. By turning the temperature on and off at this particular point in time, I'm going to get this and this result, depending on the weather outside, depending on how often people open and close the door to the room at different times of the day,
Starting point is 00:28:59 depending on the aging of my sensor or the distance of my sensor to the heating, and depending on whether the window on top of my sensor or the distance of my sensor to the heating and depending on whether the window on top of the sensor is currently open or closed and so on. I get lots and lots more ways to differentiate the event flow in the universe and the path that the universe can take and the interactions that I can have with the universe that determine whether somebody will open the window and so on and so on. You have all these points where the controller is a very differentiated model of reality where it's going to prefer some events of others and is going to assign its own decisions to these trajectories.
Starting point is 00:29:40 This decision making necessarily happens under conditions of uncertainty, And this decision-making necessarily happens under conditions of uncertainty, which means the controller will never be completely sure which one is going to do the right decision. The controller will have to make educated guesses, bets on the future. And this even includes the models of itself, right? The better the control system understands itself and the limitations of its modeling ability, the better its models are going to be. So at some point of complexity, this thing is going to understand its own modeling procedure to improve it and to find gaps in it and so on.
Starting point is 00:30:12 And this also means that when it starts to do this, it is going to discover that there are agents in the world, other controllers that have set points generators and model the future and make decisions. For instance, people that might open the window when you make the room too hot and you lose energy because of that. So maybe not overheat the room and people are in the room. This means you have to model agency at some point. And you will also discover yourself as an agent in the world, as a controller, as a
Starting point is 00:30:38 set point generator and the ability to model the future. And you will discover this before you understand your own modeling of the future works and so you also have to make bets on how you work before you understand yourself right so you will discover a self-model the self-model is the agent where the contents of your own model are driving the behavior of that agent right it's a very particular agent it's one where your reasoning and your modeling has an influence on what this agent is going to do a direct coupling it's a very particular agent it's one where your reasoning and your modeling has an influence on what this agent is going to do a direct coupling it's a very specific model a very specific agent that you discover there and so in some sense free will i think is a perspective on
Starting point is 00:31:16 decision making under uncertainty starting from the point where you discover your own self-model up to the point where you deconstruct it again. And of course, you will deconstruct it again. At some point, you'll be able to fully understand how you're operating. And once you do this, making your decision becomes indistinguishable from predicting your decision. Because of computational irreducibility, often you will not be able to predict the position before you make it, right? But as soon as you understand that there's just a computational process going on and you understand the properties of that process, you will no longer experience yourself as having free will. Free will is a particular kind of model that happens as a result of your own self-model being a simulacrum instead of being a high fidelity simulation of how you actually work
Starting point is 00:32:05 and we are young beings we don't get very old it's very difficult for us to get to the point where we fully understand how we work except in certain circumstances right when we observe our children very often we get to the point as parents that we fully understand what they will be doing in a given situation we can fully understand their own actions and anticipate their decisions. And the child might experience that it has free will. And we experience that the child has free will up to the point where we suddenly understand, oh, this is what's going on. And at this point, I can completely control the child because it can outmodel it. And it's only to the point where this system is going to introduce levels that are, again, reaching my own level that decisions become unpredictable.
Starting point is 00:32:48 But if I am a few levels of modeling depth above the other agent that might think that it's free will, the free will starts to disappear from my own perspective. It also happens in my own mind. There's many things that I do that I thought as a child I'm acting out of my own free will and now I understand how mechanical it is and I can deal with myself by controlling myself, by outmodeling myself successively and becoming one more complex in this way. All right, having gone through the depths of consciousness and physical systems with Donald Hoffman, we now transition to the quantum world with Stuart Hameroff. Hameroff's exploration of temporarily non-local consciousness offers a different angle on the question of free will, moving from cognitive neuroscience to quantum physics.
Starting point is 00:33:33 Now, going to this backward time aspect, I heard you mention Libet's experiments and that they don't necessarily show a lack of free will, but perhaps the free will propagates backward in time. Now, can you explain that? Well, Libet did these experiments in, well, he did two sets of experiments. The first set of experiments that Roger wrote about in his book, The Embers of Your Mind, were sensory experiments,
Starting point is 00:33:57 where he had people in neurosurgery. He worked with a neurosurgeon named Bertram Epstein, And in neurosurgery, he worked with a neurosurgeon named Bertram Epstein, who, by the way, was the husband of Bertram Feinstein, who was the husband of Diane Feinstein, the governor, sorry, the senator from California. She's still around. He passed away years ago. But he was a neurosurgeon and lived at work with him. And so he had patients that he did neurosurgery on while awake. So he would drill a hole and numb it up with local anesthetic. And once you get into the brain, you can operate on the brain. It doesn't hurt, but you numb up the hole and you can access the brain.
Starting point is 00:34:37 And for example, for the finger on the opposite hand. So Libet did experiments like he would stimulate the finger and record from the brain and stimulate the brain and then see when the subject was conscious of feeling the finger. So you would expect, or I would expect, not knowing anything beforehand, that if you stimulate the brain, you feel it immediately. If you stimulate the finger, it would be a delay because it would have to get to the brain. Well, if you stimulate the finger, there is a delay, but it's only 30 milliseconds, evoked potential. So it's pretty fast.
Starting point is 00:35:15 But if you stimulate the brain directly, you need to have ongoing activity, and it takes about a half a second, 500 milliseconds, because you don't get the evoked potential. But if it continues for 500 milliseconds, you do feel it at 30 milliseconds. What's this evoked potential? Okay. So if you stimulate the finger, the signal, you get a spike. That's the evoked potential. If you stimulate it here, you don't get the evoked potential. You just get ongoing activity.
Starting point is 00:35:42 It looks like gamma. But if you do it for half a second, the patient subject has the conscious experience at the time of the evoked potential, 30 milliseconds. So somehow at 30 milliseconds, the brain knows whether or not there's going to be 500 milliseconds of ongoing activity afterwards. If there is, he or she reports it at 30 milliseconds. That's interesting. Okay. If there isn't, then he or she doesn't.
Starting point is 00:36:06 And so Libet concluded that there was a signal going backwards in time from the time of what he called neuronal adequacy. And that sends this information backward in time. Now, Roger wrote about this in Emperor's Neuron because that can happen in in quantum physics which is temporally non-local is this related to the subcutaneous rabbit have you heard of that where you come on the arm yes so this is related to that yes and also the color five phenomenon where the color bounces back and forth and it goes from red to blue and you go red blue red blue and you can guess and then it goes red red and you know you're not fooled and that's because you seem to know what's going on. And the cutaneous rapids, the same thing. I actually wrote a chapter about it. I can send
Starting point is 00:36:53 it to you about all this. Well, I've written several actually about it. And all those can be accounted for by you somehow know what's coming. And this is very important because if you and I are talking and you ask me a question, and if someone were measuring the activity in my brain for what you said, it'll happen in, say, 300 to 500 milliseconds after they get to my ears. But I will have responded to you at 100 milliseconds. This is very standard neuroscience. What neuroscience says about that is that I respond non-consciously and have a false illusion of answering consciously after the fact. The consciousness is epiphenomenal. My cognitive autopilot non-conscious self answers you. And then a little later, my conscious self says,
Starting point is 00:37:45 oh, I said that. I'm in control. And it means that consciousness is epiphenomenal and illusory. That's what Dennett says. That's what all the big name philosophers say, unless they have some way to weasel out of it. But if you have backward time, it means that you can do all that and you can still respond consciously in real time. What does your theory have to say about free will? Well, first of all, you need the backward time effect to be able to act in real time. It doesn't address determinism because even if you do act in real time, you still have the problem, well, maybe it was always going to be that way because of everything else that's already happened but
Starting point is 00:38:27 when you bring in the backward time effects i think that gives you the possibility of free will but you're still you're still governed by if that's true you're still governed by you know the deterministic schrodinger equation up to that point and uh and uh you know maybe even the platonic values so you know the best they could say is that free will is the experience of your volition being influenced by platonic values. Stuart Hameroff's exploration of free will and temporal perception naturally transition into Claudia Pesos' discussion on behavioral markers as indicators of consciousness. markers as indicators of consciousness. The audio conditions were suboptimal, thus prompting me to reiterate in post-production the question for you. The questioner was asking Claudia to how those behavioral markers would be markers of conscience.
Starting point is 00:39:32 And there is at least one field of consciousness that we've analyzed. If the creature has what they call flexible behavior, the capacity to react with flexibility will change our behaviors regarding, for instance, pain and stimulus. So imagine you're feeling pain, but you have a behavior to avoid pain and this behavior didn't begin with weak pain. We can change our strategy to avoid feeling that way. And this happens in some flexibility. Usually, if you're not conscious, you just have a kind of automatic response that is the same response all the time. And infants, they try to change their strategies to avoid that painful stigma.
Starting point is 00:40:14 So this is a kind of flexible behavior. For instance, for representational experience, we claim that flexible behavior is a mark of unconsciousness. Claudia Pesos' exploration of behavioral markers and their connections to consciousness sets the stage for Wolfgang Smith's discourse on the relationship between free will, love, and the divine. How does free will comport with knowing that there's a timeless realm so that you can see all of what occurs through time, but then if we exist as a moment in time and we're trying to plan something for the future and we have free will, how do we have free will when from another perspective all our choices have been made or all of it can be seen?
Starting point is 00:41:01 Well, I think there's only one answer to that question, and that is that a free will pertains to our present state, which is a state of half-knowing. Once we attain enlightenment, there's no question of free will. You know, sorry, enlightenment is the same as salvation, or is that different? Well, I think nothing short of salvation would put you into that state where there's no more free will. There's no more free will because there is no more will in our sense of the term.
Starting point is 00:41:44 Love is what makes things real. What do you make of that quote? Well, I think it is based upon one of the deepest teachings of Christ. teachings of Christ. St. John the Evangelist, in his, I forget what it is called, his letters, not the gospel, but his letters,
Starting point is 00:42:19 he says, Deus caritas est. God is love. So, love in the authentic sense that we're using the term now is itself divine. It is
Starting point is 00:42:36 God. It's not something that God makes, something that God creates. Well, there is love in that sense too, but love in its highest purest sense is inseparable from God. Wolfgang's peregrination of the divine and free will serves as a perfect precursor to Bernardo Kastrup's discussion on the illusion of free will and the deterministic
Starting point is 00:43:05 nature of the universe. It is the collective unconscious. It is the last dissociated parts of our minds or the completely non-dissociated mind at large. That's the natural wave. Remember, I am a naturalist and nature is a big wave. It's going somewhere. We can choose to swim with it or swim against it.
Starting point is 00:43:22 You can choose to be tools of it or to rebel against it and lose. You're guaranteed to lose. You're super interesting, super interesting. So you're saying that nature is this huge force and it generally controls you way more than you think. You are an aspect of it, so you're not even separate from it. So even to say it controls you is already a categorical mistake. You are not distinct from it. But you just have a hallucinated narrative about what you are.
Starting point is 00:43:47 In other words, nature has a hallucinated narrative about what it is, and it goes in conflict against itself because of it. Choices are instinctive. There is something instinctive that runs through you and is calling the shots, all the important shots. The problem is we think it is us choosing it. So we rebel against it or we regret against choices and suffering pours out from that dynamics, which is also a natural dynamics. It's nature fooling itself.
Starting point is 00:44:17 It's all natural. So the choice to swim with the current rather than against it, is that choice yours or is that choice ultimately another current? In which case, you can't. Nature can offer less resistance against itself. Let's put it that way. Because you see, it's impossible to use terms in a completely unambiguous way.
Starting point is 00:44:37 Because terms like I, or doing, or resisting, or nature, they have already a social meaning. So if I try to be completely accurate, they have already a social meaning. So if I try to be completely accurate, I will contradict that social meaning and nobody will understand what I'm trying to say. So I have to be ambiguous and seemingly contradictory per force if I am to use language. I don't think Bernardo Kastrup exists as a true separate agency. Bernardo Kastrup is a ripple or a metaphor I prefer, a whirlpool
Starting point is 00:45:06 in the ocean of nature. It's a process. It's a doing. It's not a thing. It's a Kastruping, not a Kastrup. Is that your intellectual mind saying that I don't believe Bernardo Kastrup exists? That's my intellect saying.
Starting point is 00:45:23 But you don't feel that in the moment, but you feel like that's actually correct. So let me just say that. And now we transition from Bernardo to Matt O'Dowd from PBS Space Time, as Matt talks to us about the subtleties of relativity, time perception, and the universe's self-consistency. Consciousness is just, it is in this sense an emergent phenomenon, but there's no very hard line, I think, for when it emerges. I started all this saying I'm no expert and then gave you super long treaties as though I know anything, but this is the picture that feels the least contradictory to me.
Starting point is 00:46:17 So then in this view, is there such a thing as free will? In this view, yes. Correct my misunderstanding, Sen. The way that I understand it is that there are some atoms moving around, and occasionally that is something we call information processing. That information processing is much like there's a lamp right here. That is casting onto the wall. That wall is now the feeling of consciousness. That is the effect.
Starting point is 00:46:42 And something is happening here. Now, that wall doesn't cause anything with this effect. And something is happening here. Now, that wall doesn't cause anything with this light. The light will move around. Right now, it's stationary, but the light can change colors. It can get brighter. It can get smashed on the ground. And that wall would change. But I wouldn't say that that wall has any causal influence on that. So, that's what I mean when I say that it sounds like there is no free will in what has just been outlined. So please correct my misunderstanding. Okay. So let's try to talk about free will. So first of all, so Baha, my partner, she's a science journalist and has
Starting point is 00:47:19 written a lot about these topics. I encourage you to check out her article in The Atlantic, which debunks some nonsense on the topic. But she always reminds me to think about these things in the context of their historical development. So pre-Enlightenment, there was this idea that free will and meaning and mind were inextricably attached to notions like God and the immortal soul. the materialist paradigm arose, so the Newtonian worldview of, you know, atoms bouncing around in the void, perfectly predictable clockwork. So at the same time that we discarded or started to discard the spiritual, and in that gap we inserted this sort of very first and and and perhaps naive um mechanistic determinism uh notions like free will which were conjoined with god and the soul got thrown out with the bath water and were replaced
Starting point is 00:48:36 by the idea that that these things are epiphenomena um of of you know, a call mechanistic universe. So that's one gripe. What it is, it's a gripe with what I think is an oversimplification of the approach to thinking about free will but all other things related to the mind also. So let me explain why my view doesn't suggest that free will is an illusion. And so what does it mean? It means free will means that your make your choices are your own.
Starting point is 00:49:25 They're not forced on you by something else. And for any choice you make, you could have chosen otherwise. And, you know, the standard argument is that your choices are not yours because they're determined by the particles that you're made of. Okay, you couldn't have chosen otherwise. So this is the argument that you hear. I won't mention any names. Because, you know, so you couldn't have chosen otherwise because the,
Starting point is 00:49:54 whatever, the exact position and velocity of all of your subatomic particles set and had to evolve according to the laws of physics. Or that, you know, if those particles have some fundamental randomness, then the randomness is still not free will. Okay, so that's the argument. And first of all, let me say that, you know, that picture of physics is, you know, it's right in a sense, okay? So I believe that subatomic particles evolve according to the Schrodinger equation, et cetera,
Starting point is 00:50:33 and the subatomic particles have no idea that they're in a brain or that they're part of a choice or they represent a data structure that that data structure feels as part of a choice. But the problem with this reductionist argument is that it's messing up its definitions, and in particular its definitions of causality. So if we think about the world as having these kind of layers of complexity, okay, you have physics driving the atoms and chemistry driving the molecules and
Starting point is 00:51:18 biology driving the cells, then you could say something like, so if you want to talk about then you could say something like, so if you want to talk about causality here in terms of the hierarchies of emergence, then you could say that quarks and electrons cause atoms, atoms cause molecules, molecules cause cells, cells cause apples and brains and brains cause minds, right? But this is a type of causation and it's like this cross-hierarchical causation. But I would argue that there's a real fundamental difference between that type of causation to what you might call an intra-hierarchical causation that defines the dynamics within a given layer. Can you give me an example? that defines the dynamics within a given layer. Can you give me an example? All right. So you can say that there's this causal power whereby a cell is,
Starting point is 00:52:15 or say a neuron is caused by the molecules that it's formed of. It is an epiphenomenon of those molecules, which in turn are epiphenomenon of those molecules, which in turn are epiphenomenon of their atoms, etc. But it's also entirely meaningful to say that an action potential in a neuron causes a downstream neuron to fire, right? So that's a reasonable statement okay a neuron fires one that's attached to fires and you can you can and and it makes total sense and and in a real sense it's true to say that the first neuron caused the firing of the second um it's less useful to say that like the wiggle of a quantum string on the Planck scale caused a downstream neuron
Starting point is 00:53:08 to fire even if the quantum string is the, let's call it the hierarchical cause or one of the electrons in the first action potential. That's like a roundabout and relatively inane approach to talking about causation. So there's this kind of bottom-up causation in which different levels in the scale of, you know, physical scale or complexity scale are generated by the lower layers, but there's a different type of causation within the layer, okay? So and within each of these hierarchical layers, you have a dynamics that is in a sense independent
Starting point is 00:54:00 of the layer below that generated it okay so you can um you know i mentioned bernoulli's equation fluid flow so you you had this whole field of hydrodynamics which is beautiful and in a sense it's causally closed like you can predict anything about the behaviour of fluids using these rules. And it does matter what the properties of the particles in that layer are, and the properties of those particles are generated by the layer below. But once you know the properties of those particles, you don't care about the detailed physics of the level below. You are in that layer and the rules
Starting point is 00:54:47 of that layer are in a sense closed and independent okay so so so brains have a dynamics of neural activity okay it's a physical system they behave like some type of neural network. We can even simulate it. Okay, current neural networks miss an awful lot, but in principle, we'd be able to run the dynamics of the brain with a different substrate. We can run them. probably will be able to run these in silico. And that dynamical system, the system of neural activity will be independent of the substrate once we figure out what that dynamics is. Man, Matt, I don't know if you realize you're saying such controversial statements at saying in principle. So, for instance, you're saying're saying in principle we could simulate the brain substrate independence like who knows i mean well that's like a huge open well i'm i'm gonna
Starting point is 00:55:50 understand i'm gonna crapple over the expression in principle i think because um so yeah who cares we're just talking and people who are listening just realize that none of us have the correct words and in order for us to just in order for us to convey anything that's non-trivial we're going to have to flummox and flounder okay well i'm happy i'm happy to put myself out there i think we will be able to simulate the brain but it might be a really long time away because there's so much that goes on sure and and the point is that once we once we figure out those dynamics it'll be independent of the substrate, silicon or meat. In the case, all right, so maybe we can agree that the dynamics within a layer are their own thing.
Starting point is 00:56:36 And the idea of cores within one of those layers is different to the cores that generates one layer from the layer below it okay oh i see what you're saying okay okay so you have you have you have this dynamics of cause and effect in you know in biology or in an ecological system okay it's true that reintroducing wolves to the Yellowstone National Park caused the deer population to become under control. Okay, that's a totally meaningful statement, and it would be absurd to try to do the same thing with quarks. Okay, yes, yes.
Starting point is 00:57:18 Quarks to deers, right? So you have these dynamical systems where, and the cause in that sense is like, we should have a different word for it. So we're mixing our definitions of the intrasystem versus the intersystem causation. So we're still not at free will yet. So our conscious experience may be emergent from the actions of our neurons it
Starting point is 00:57:46 probably is in some sense um but in another sense it is dual to our the actions of our neurons okay so the the our neurons have a dynamics which know, you can at some level explain their behaviour, but the, and they generate this pattern of information that, you know, tells a story about itself, et cetera. And so in a way, our minds or, you know, the description of our minds is just another way of casting neurodynamics that is essentially a duality. It is a dual to that system. But in a way, you could argue that it's more fundamental right so if in the broadest sense our minds are the result of a computation then then our minds are also a dynamical system independent of the substrate um so a set of elements in this case thoughts linked by a set
Starting point is 00:59:02 of rules uh, you know, and thoughts are symbolic representations. And so you can come up with a language that manipulates these symbolic representations and tell stories with them. Okay, that's, you know, in a sense kind of what a mind is and a bunch of other stuff. Okay, so in a sense, psychology is the science of understanding the dynamics of that system, and it's to some extent mappable,
Starting point is 00:59:33 maybe never completely, but you could write down the dynamics of the mind without referencing neurons, okay, just as you could write down the dynamics of the neurons without referencing neurons, okay, just as you could write down the dynamics of the neurons without referencing electrons. And the reason I said that in a sense the way of looking at neural dynamics, which is the dual of it, which is the subjective experience, is more predictively powerful than the neural dynamics themselves. And in some way of looking at it, that is the subjective experience, is more predictably powerful than the neural
Starting point is 01:00:05 dynamics themselves. And in some way of looking at it, that's more fundamental. There are things you can predict about what a brain will do and how an organism will behave that you could only get by looking at the thought dynamics, like the mental dynamics, and you could never get by trying to look at a few neurons and guess what they're going to do. Is this not a difference between what we can do and what is? I don't think so. So, all right, so first of all, let's, you know, put a pin in the idea that the mind is this,
Starting point is 01:01:00 its own dynamical system, potentially independent of its substrate, its own dynamical system potentially independent of its substrate uh and and understanding the dynamics of the mind is better than understanding the dynamics of neurons for for many many things uh but does it mean does that mean uh, yeah, like you said, is the mind, is this just our impression that, you know, particular types of people based on looking at their neurons or looking at their quarks, okay? But, okay, so now we get to this idea of in principle. Yeah, okay. Is it... That's the title of the podcast.
Starting point is 01:02:02 Is it even in principle possible to do so? And I would argue there also no. It's in principle possible to predict some human behaviour by trying to model the physical aspect of the brain, but I don't think it's possible to... So here things get a little bit messy. So you could predict someone's behaviour just by knowing them well. Does that mean they have no free will that they couldn't potentially
Starting point is 01:02:37 do otherwise? You could predict someone's inclination to certain types of behavior by knowing, you know, about any neuropathologies that they might have. So for sure, we aren't, you know, the epitome is a free will. We often fail to exercise free will or we are predictable. of free will we we often fail to exercise free will we are predictable but the idea that free will is an illusion because brains are mechanistic i think is a little fallacious and and the reason is that so so if a brain because of that dual notion well not even i think we can go to to physical here like there are physical ish reasons here so so the brain the idea is that that your actions
Starting point is 01:03:39 are predetermined and predictable because they're entirely determined by the configuration of physical matter and so on. But then I want to ask, to whom is the brain predictable and predetermined? To what observer and what reference frame? So if you have any sufficiently complex system like the brain, the dynamics are coupled across multiple physical scales. So, for example, an important part of the decision mechanism in the brain is the so-called Breitschach potential, which is just the way the brain, it's basically the correlated noise in brain signal that the brain actually uses as a sort of a tiebreaker in decision making.
Starting point is 01:04:47 And it partially drives the dynamics in ways that we don't very well understand at all, because it's super new that we figured out. Can you repeat the name of the potential? It's the Breishacht potential. It's also called the readiness potential. readiness potential okay yeah uh and you you want to look at um aaron scherger's work uh and uh and actually baha wrote an article on this i'm just mentioning that because i'm super familiar with it now but it's just one example of uh how uh that you have dynamics influence. In complex and even pseudo-chaotic systems, you have these dynamics linked across multiple scales of these hierarchies. And in that case, it becomes essentially impossible to predict behaviour based on the, you know,
Starting point is 01:05:50 the smallest piece, like the smallest elements of the substrate, whatever, the atoms. And, okay, so you have this, you know, system that is partially chaotic, and it's well known that these things can't be predicted without infinite computation. Okay. I think this is a manifestation of this computational irreducibility also. Okay.
Starting point is 01:06:20 So my question is what observer or what reference frame could predict your actions perfectly by knowing the exact state of all the quantum fields in your brain? So you could imagine, you know, some super advanced alien that could somehow perfectly scan your brain and get that and then run a simulation of your brain at the same time. But even that, I think here, like the very nature of quantum mechanics makes that challenging, okay? So you literally need to track every bit of quantum information in the most complex systems to make a perfect prediction. So maybe you can make some predictions, but it's not even practically impossible. It's probably even in principle impossible. So you have things like
Starting point is 01:07:21 the no cloning theorem, which forbids you from making a perfect copy of quantum information, which is what you would need to do to make a perfect prediction. in principle, not possible for any possible observer to perfectly predict your choice. Okay. It is possible for impossible observers like Laplace's demon, who knows the exact position and velocity of every particle in the universe. So from the perspective of Laplace's demon, you have no free will, but Laplace's demon is a mythical entity. And like other mythical entities, I don't think we should
Starting point is 01:08:18 rate something an illusion because a mythical entity could, in principle, predict your behavior. So, there's this guy named David Wolpert. I don't know if you know him, but he's in Santa Barbara, I believe, and he has the limits on inference machines, which says that even Laplace's demon in Newtonian mechanics can't exist. I agree that Laplace's demon cannot exist. I think even relativity forbids Laplace's demon because there's a limit to how quickly it could – anyway, this is a whole other topic. Yeah, yeah. Okay, so long story short, I think free will is real in a meaningful sense.
Starting point is 01:09:02 Okay, like going down the definition of real is like a whole other podcast but free will real in a meaningful sense because choice is a fundamental dynamical component in a particular dynamical system whose behavior is independent of its substrate and whose behavior is not fully predictable in the context of its substrates by by by mapping its substrates um in a in a in a way that is possible for any entity that that could exist uh but if you choose to not believe in free will then at least you have that choice yeah okay great well man there's so much that we can talk about okay how about instead of delving
Starting point is 01:09:54 more deeply into i'll just tell you the one thought i'll just tell you one of the thoughts why is this notion of to who important for instance we can say there is a computer here when we consider that to be an objective fact. We don't say this computer is here to who, unless you are someone who believes that the observer creates the reality. So let's disregard that interpretation and say there's an objective reality. So why is it that we're saying free will exists to who? Why can't we just say free will exists in the same way that this computer exists? Yeah, I mean, we live in a relative universe.
Starting point is 01:10:36 Particles have a relative existence. You know, Hawking radiation only exists if you're a certain distance away from a black hole unruh radiation only exists if you're uh accelerating uh so so there i mean there is a sense in which um the frame of reference is is is critical um and for like non-noisy so there's something noisy about the the radiation and the udra radiation so the hawking radiation and that one yeah well i think i think so maybe i i do i don't know but there's there is something non-trivial about the relativity of existence in terms of matter, for sure.
Starting point is 01:11:30 And so this is something I don't think we've properly wrapped our heads around. Maybe it's as confusing as the measurement problem, the idea that the universe can look, can and does look radically different depending on your frame of reference. And the only thing that is consistent is the self-consistency of the universe itself. Like no matter what changes, you know, based on a frame of reference,
Starting point is 01:12:07 how you choose to make measurements, for example, in, you know, things like a bell test, these things can radically change what universe you see. But the one thing that never change changes is that the universe remains self-consistent for all observers okay can you explain what that means and it's that different than the statement that the laws of physics are the same um so in the case of well i mean the simple case of of relativity like let's take the simple case of the twin paradox where uh so this is this thought experiment in relativity where a pair of twins, one jumps in a spacecraft and zips off
Starting point is 01:13:05 at a large fraction of the speed of light and, you know, comes back several years later from the perspective of the twin at home and the twin at home has aged and the twin who travel is much younger because time ticked slower for the twin who was travelling because of their relative speed. Okay, so from the point of view of the travelling twin, they didn't think that their clock was ticking slow. Okay, they were looking back home and they thought that at home the clock was ticking fast and from – no, wait on.
Starting point is 01:13:52 No. I should know this stuff. So this is a so-called parallel. You should watch this PBS Space Time. Yeah, yeah. This is a so-called parallel. You should watch this PBS space time. Yeah, yeah. The way it works is that when you observe a clock that's traveling at some speed, that clock appears to tick slow.
Starting point is 01:14:15 All right. So fast moving objects, the time slows down. So both twins see each other's clock as ticking slow, all right, because the spaceship is moving fast. But then for the astronaut twin, Earth appears to be moving backwards quickly because, you know, speed is relative. There's no preferred inertial frame of reference. So Earth races away.
Starting point is 01:14:41 That twin's clock seems to slow down. And yet when the twin gets back home after that long trip, the twin who stayed at home, so it has to end up inconsistent, which one aged more than the other? And the answer is that there is an answer, that there is a self-consistent answer. When they get home, both of them agree that the twin who stayed home aged more.
Starting point is 01:15:05 But how can that work if both of them saw the same change in each other's clock? And both of the twins have an answer for that. And their answers are different, but they lead to the same conclusion. The twin who stayed home sees the traveling twins clock ticks slower and so that the traveling twin ages less okay and and gets home meanwhile the one at home is waiting and and getting older and his twin comes back much younger okay because the less time passed. But for the travelling twin, they watch the twin at home and they watch the twin at home's clock tick slower. So, in fact, the travelling twin feels themselves ageing faster
Starting point is 01:15:58 until the moment that they turn around. Okay, so in order to turn around and come home, they have to accelerate. And the other thing that Einstein's relativity tells us is that if you are deep in a gravitational field, your clock ticks slower. So the amount that that twin has to accelerate in order to return home causes their clock to slow down enough that from their perspective, the twin who was at home not only caught up to them but aged a lot more. Okay. different stories about why they both agree that the travelling twin is younger than the stay-at-home twin.
Starting point is 01:16:52 And so, Kurt, how did we get to this? This was in service of a point. Okay, so firstly, I was asking about what does it mean to be self-consistent yeah yeah yeah so that so the universe will always conspire to be self-consistent and and and that uh observers will you know ultimately agree um and i have so many questions here that's even the case with particles. Like if you see unradiation, I can't remember what the solution to this one is, someone else doesn't see unradiation,
Starting point is 01:17:35 but they see, yeah, it's like if you accelerate fast enough, then you'll be incinerated by what's the equivalent of Hawking radiation. It's a type of horizon radiation. But someone who is not accelerating doesn't see your unruh particles and yet does see you incinerated. So why does the person who's not accelerating see you incinerated so why does the the person who's not accelerating see you incinerated i think the answer is you they see you being incinerated by something else like the drag on the quantum
Starting point is 01:18:14 fields or something i i don't recall but but there was a there's a neat answer to like the universe keeps conspiring to give us these neat answers that everyone ultimately is going to agree, even if the universe that they think they live in looks wildly different to the universe of the next person. The consistency conspires to always be there. And I think there's a mystery there. Now that you've heard from Matt O'Dowd of PBS Spaceacetime, the following is Anand Vaidya on Free Will. Anand is one of those rare philosophers who's well-educated in both the Eastern philosophical tradition and Western analytic tradition, particularly Indian and modal philosophy. Enjoy. What are your thoughts on Free Will?
Starting point is 01:19:05 Um, what are my thoughts on free will? Do you feel like there's pressure to go in the direction of there is no free will? No, it's actually the opposite. I had this really interesting dinner with Richard Swinburne, one of the leading philosophers of religion in the world. I had a dinner with him and my wife in Romania. And we ended up talking about free will. And I just told him, like, I never got into the problem of free will because I think I just was full-blown committed to the idea that free will and determinism are incompatible, and we have free will. Otherwise, I can't make sense of—yeah, I have—maybe I'll repeat the same sort of thing I said to him
Starting point is 01:19:46 that I say to all my students and everybody when they ask me about free will. There's two things about free will I care about. One is the thing I'm about to say, and the other is the relationship, again, between artificial systems and freedom and artificial systems and free will. So I'm very interested in those.
Starting point is 01:20:01 So here's the first one. I think speaking a language and communicating with someone is an agential activity involving free will at some level and degree of freedom in the choice of constructing sentences and embedding them with meaning to communicate them so that if we don't have free will i'm not talking right now no there's nothing it's a parrot there's nothing going on there right right so parrots are merely under one understanding simply repeating sounds that they've heard without any sort of choice about it in terms of the free construction of meaning. So, if I don't have, so one way to make it clear is some people think about free will only in relationship to bodily action. I think about free will in terms of its relationship to mental action. Speaking is a mental act. So, if I don't have free will, I don't have any mental actions. If I don't have any mental actions, then I'm not speaking, because speaking is a mental action.
Starting point is 01:21:11 That's the first point I care about in terms of free wills. I bring this up a lot. So yeah, then the other one that I bring up is that I'm not so sure that there's some kind of free will that we have that machines are incapable of having because they're so-called, quote-unquote, programmed in some way. And in fact, I just saw this wonderful episode of Star Trek. It was in the Voyager stuff, where they in fact had a discussion between the doctor who is a hologram and one of his assistants, and the doctor said to the assistant,
Starting point is 01:21:51 well, I don't choose anything when I give a diagnosis. I've been programmed to give the diagnosis based on these vast amounts of information that I've been trained on. Like, this is the hologram, talking to their assistant about a patient that they have, and expressing himself that he doesn't have choice or free will in diagnosing them, that he simply takes the data that's been given to him, runs it through all the data he has known before or been given, and then spits out a diagnosis. And then she says this brilliant response. She says, well, what's the difference? I mean, I went to medical school,
Starting point is 01:22:31 and I studied all this stuff. And basically, when they give me the information, I try to look at all the information in my head. And maybe the difference is that it's more easily accessible to you because your memory is so free-flowing with all its information and mine is forgetful. But isn't the fundamental nature? I thought this was one of the most insightful philosophical episodes of Star Trek because of, you know, how this was expressed. And so I thought, yes, I do worry about that issue too, about the degree to which we really can run the Charles Babbage, Lady Lovelace objection against machines creativity because it's all programmed in. As the initial objection goes, the Turing responds to in his famous paper. Yeah, so those are my two thoughts about free will, but I'm not a free
Starting point is 01:23:17 will expert, and I know there are many people who talk about in terms of quantum indeterminacy and things like that. probably should yeah with all the about sure yeah is there something about free will that makes it sufficient for something to have moral standing oh uh i don't think it's a necessary condition i think it could be in a condition so yes i think yeah so maybe like maybe this is something we can get from free will into the other thing that we kind of wanted to talk about. Moral standing and moral grounding. Yeah, so I'll just sort of paint the picture, you know, sort of synaptically what the difference is between. This is something I actually do have something to say.
Starting point is 01:24:00 I have a positive thesis more than just picking apart things I don't like and writing papers. Like, I definitely have strong feelings here. So, I don't think... Well, you're so well articulated that when you say that you don't have something to say, it's leagues beyond what most people say when they say, I have something to say. Oh, okay. So, your threshold is so above yeah maybe my threshold's too high uh no so yeah i think my view is that i don't yeah i don't think that uh consciousness is the grounding property so on my view in my research right now i think that there's another property that's important it is not free will though either it's not free will so we might say that free will is a sufficient condition for having moral status but not a necessary condition um but i think the property i'm
Starting point is 01:24:52 going to talk about now is more basic and it's the one that can explain what's going on with free will maybe when i explain the whole theory so the property i think is relevant is computational intelligence that's goal-directed and tied to preferential states. So this goes back to the example of the creature in the water who can detect magnetic north and south and tries to get oxygen-rich water by going
Starting point is 01:25:16 in one direction. Yeah, and you call that cognition. And to me, when I think of cognition... You should call it cognitive suffering. Yeah, sorry. When I hear the term cognitive, I think of a nervous system, and I assume that that's not what you mean. I don't mean that. No, I don't. So, again, let me explain here what's going on.
Starting point is 01:25:34 So, I think that there are lots of different, like, I'm always trying to find this word, and I never can find it,, like the word that properly applies to biological and non-biological creatures. I think sometimes I just want to call them natural versus artificial systems. I mean, a human is a natural system, and a bug is a natural system, and an AI is an artificial system, but I don't really like that. Anyway, you get the point. There's these two different kinds of systems, at least, and there are many different versions of each kind. So many different artificial systems and large language models are different than, you know, domain-specific chess playing games and different types of creatures, right?
Starting point is 01:26:13 Yes. is that there is a kind of intelligence in it that involves computations, and that intelligence is goal-directed, and the system has preferential states. So the little creature I was talking about prefers to be an oxygen-rich environment opposed to an oxygen-low environment. It has a detector for getting itself to that thing. It's not the greatest detector, but it does its job. And I can mess with it by putting a magnet over it and then killing it. But the thing is, that detector is giving it information that has to be computed
Starting point is 01:27:00 then to move that it goes in a certain direction, right? Now, I don't know if the thing has phenomenal consciousness i don't know if there's something it's like for the thing to detect north or south with that that thing but but that doesn't matter yeah for me it does because the thing is it definitely prefers to be in the oxygen rich environment over the low oxygen yeah and so that should be enough to say of that now Now, look, let's go further. So you understand like plants have computational intelligence that's goal directed that involves preferences. Lots of animals and insects above them. Preferences are different than tendencies. Is that correct?
Starting point is 01:27:43 That's a good philosophical question because sometimes people say that tendencies are related to the free will thing tendencies are a little bit more automatic and preferences require rational endorsement I don't really think I need to use preference in that way
Starting point is 01:27:59 this has a tendency to just want to stay at the minimal position so if I raise it am I causing harm to it this has a tendency to just want to stay at the minimal position. Yeah. So if I raise it, am I causing harm to it? This doesn't have moral standing because it doesn't meet the artificial life form.
Starting point is 01:28:15 I get what you're, I get what I get. This is good exams. I get clearly exactly like how it's challenging. I don't know. I'm not trying to challenge. I'm just, no,
Starting point is 01:28:23 no. Well, I mean, it's the right kind of corner case to think about is what I mean in that sense. Yeah, I definitely think the answer is no, that that thing actually does not satisfy my definitions. But I think the reason why it doesn't satisfy my conditions has to do with the fact that none of the things that are going on with it have to do with anything internal to the thing.
Starting point is 01:28:43 I mean, obviously it's gravity and mass alone that account for the tendency. So the use of the word tendency is eliminable completely. There's no tendency at all within the object. There's just the application of the laws of physics to things that have mass. That was Anand Vaidya. Again, links to all of these podcasts. The full versions are in the description. Now, hear from Christopher Langan on free will from his cognitive theoretic model of the universe perspective, also known as the CTMU. Okay, let's talk about free will. It seems like that's what is at the core here. So, I'll do so by reading
Starting point is 01:29:25 a question which is directed toward Chris. But then obviously, if you pull something out, even though it has some terminology that's specific to the CTMU, Bernardo, please comment on it as well. Okay. Hey, Kurt, I'm reposting this from YouTube. It's for Chris on the topic of free will derived from the CTMU. If you can ask this, you'll forever be my hero. You once said, I believe it's referring to you, Chris. Chris, you said that the universe, that because the universe has only itself to define itself, everything in it must exemplify its elementary freedom. I think I understand from your defining reality as all real influence that reality cannot be abbreviated, because if you were able to simplify it with no loss, whatever was removed could not logically have been real.
Starting point is 01:30:12 I understand where to take this to imply that reality could not have come from anything simpler than its full definition, and what can't be simplified must be contributory throughout. That said, you've still maintained a strong distinction between tertiary syntactors, objects, and secondary syntactors slash tellers, life forms, read life forms, in terms of the amount that they are determinative. Considering that you've shown that reality is a mind, could we liken the distinction to the difference between ideas of objects and ideas of self, where just just like ideas all objects have some significance specific to them however seemingly banal but only tellers as ideas of self would be self-modeling and therefore
Starting point is 01:30:56 truly take on self-awareness that's why they're called tellers that's why self type uh identity operators are called tellers, whereas tertiary identity operators are fermionic, more or less, and they are inanimate, or at least usually considered to be inanimate. But basically, they're embedded in secondary tellers, and therefore, they take that higher-order metacalization, that ability to self-model from the secondary tellers. So I assume you're answering the question right now, but Chris, I didn't understand the question. So can you explain the question back to myself and then answer it?
Starting point is 01:31:30 Well, states, you know, there's no such thing as a state in isolation. States are always relatively defined. That's why we have theories of relativity and things like that. But what must the state be defined relative to? Well, to completely define any state in the universe, you need to refer to every other state in the universe because it parameterizes that state.
Starting point is 01:31:53 Okay? And you don't get a complete parameterization unless you have the full matter distribution and the full metric. Okay? So that's what it takes. Can I make an analogy? There is a duality between a set and the complement of a set, assuming that the set is within some other large set that we can call. So let's say
Starting point is 01:32:11 the large set is S, you have a subset U, then there's a duality between U and U with a C, which is the complement of it. The teller and the environment, right, exactly. Self and non-self. Okay, sorry, continue. Okay, well, the environment, of course, is just the medium minus the teller. In other words, it's external to the medium, but it's outside the boundary of the teller. And so you get this basically the self-dual construct, which is a teller-environment coupling. And this teller-environment coupling is very important in the CTME because that's kind of a metaphorical one. It's one way of expressing CTME quantization.
Starting point is 01:32:50 You have to put the medium together with the object. The object is its own medium through this process called conspansion, which is the operation through which the universe evolves on the global level. Now, in order to get semantic meaning out of that,
Starting point is 01:33:06 basically, it's called cosmic expansion. To get meaning out of that, then you need another process called telecruciation, which then specifies that semantic structure to the syntactic structure that's built up by Cosmat. Chris, it's been almost a year since I studied the CTMU. And when I did, I didn't go back to it, which means I've forgotten so much of it, so much of the terminology. As I would have done myself. Okay.
Starting point is 01:33:32 So much of the terminology. It goes through me. So, telec recursion, I have a vague recollection that it's where the universe exercises free will. It looks at some generalized utility state and then makes a decision. That's where Tellor is self-configured. That's where secondary identity operators or Tellor is self-configured. They actually become the medium. And I know that Bernardo actually embraces something like this in his analytic idealism, I think is what he calls it.
Starting point is 01:34:04 Basically, you've got to have that. Okay, so let me be blunt. So free will in your theory, in your model, Chris, exists. And Bernardo, if I'm correct, you're against the idea of free will, at least currently. Well, let me tell you what free will is first before the model gets gone. Okay. Yes. As I said, there is no typographical array in the metaphorical system, okay?
Starting point is 01:34:29 You can't use the parameter as a state. You cannot just use a fixed array, a fixed array. The array has to be changing geometrically is the term that the followers of Einstein came up with to describe what must be going on. It's happening behind the scenes. Okay? Free will happens because things are determined metacausally, you know, and metaformally, which means that things have to be coupled or factorized. Right? coupled or factorized, right? In other words, it's just not this linear process, this causal process,
Starting point is 01:35:06 but it's this high-order process called metacalization that is occurring. And this is free will. If we look at a expansive cycle in the CTMU, it's an alpha-omega cycle. In other words, it starts at an origin, it ends with the boundary, and those two things are in advanced
Starting point is 01:35:24 and retarded communication with each other. Free will is in determining one of those expansive cycles, regardless of what its size is. So, in other words, there is a way to define free will that gets out of this pseudo-causal dichotomy between determinacy and indeterminacy that we were talking about earlier. In other words, you're creating the medium. You're actually creating spacetime as you create a new state.
Starting point is 01:35:54 When you bring that new mental state into your head, you've actually done it by creating spacetime. This is kind of a very profound, very weird way of looking at it. I understand that it sounds weird, but it's the only way, in my opinion, things can work. I will comment more generically because I'm not familiar with Chris's terminology. So it's impossible for me to go into the details of that. But you offered, Kurt, that I am currently against free will. There's a lot of nuance to this.
Starting point is 01:36:24 So let me try to clarify this. If the question of free will is linked to a materialist metaphysics, like people worrying that, oh, if my choices are determined by the patterns of brain activity in my brain, then I don't have free will. Well, on that account,
Starting point is 01:36:43 I think people need not be afraid because I don't think physiological patterns of brain activity cause your choices. I think they are what your choices look like. In Schopenhauer's terminology, they are appearances, representations. The thing in itself is your choice. So no, your choices are not determined by your brain activity your brain activity is what the process of making choices look like and then you would say well then i am endorsing free will well now we have now to
Starting point is 01:37:17 understand what people mean by free will what people mean by it is that their choices are determined by that which they identify themselves with, as opposed to being determined by something that they don't identify with. And most people don't identify with their brain activity. They never get to see it. They don't identify with it. That's why when a physicalist says, well, your choices are determined by your brain activity, people feel that as a violation of their free will because they identify with their own mental processes, the flow of their consciousness, not with physical patterns of brain activity inside their skull, which they never saw in their lives. Now let's think about the mind of nature. The mind of nature is the only thing there is. So need and will are the same thing.
Starting point is 01:38:10 There is nothing, I mean, I have to work, right? I'm forced by my society to work. So my choice to work is not freely determined by me. It's a need imposed on me by the society. And I don't identify with the rest of the society. So, my free will has been cut short in that regard. But if you are the mind of nature, there is no society, there is no world outside of you, there's nothing beyond you. So, whatever choices you make as the mind of nature are free in the sense that they are determined,
Starting point is 01:38:44 but they are determined by you. You see what I mean? Your identification, exactly. Yeah. The need and the choice are one and the same. There is no semantic difference between determinism and free will at the level of the mind of nature.
Starting point is 01:39:00 Because yes, the choices are determined. Even people who believe in free will, they are not saying that their choices are determined even people who believe in free will they are not saying that their choices are random they are saying that their choices are determined by their preferences their tastes they are determined by them at the level of the mind of nature every choice is determined by the mind of nature because there is nothing beyond the universal mind the universal consciousness so even the question of free will disappears there is nothing beyond the universal mind, the universal consciousness. So even the question of free will disappears. There is a semantic space for it.
Starting point is 01:39:32 It doesn't make sense to talk about it. But the choices are still determined in the sense that they are not random. The choices of the mind of nature are determined by what the mind of nature is. Its characteristics, its properties determine the choices it makes. It cannot abstract of itself. Otherwise, the choices would be completely random. And that's incoherent to say that. I would merely add that what we have to do is we have to distinguish free will, what's happening there, from determinacy and non-determinacy. Okay, so it is useful to talk about free will just to distinguish it from what we usually mean by causation. And once we do that, then we find out that we can describe it in a certain way, right?
Starting point is 01:40:16 In terms of this conspansion and teleprocursion thing we were talking about earlier. I think ultimately, everything is determined. Even your choices are determined by your tastes, by your dispositions, your opinions. Well, can I ask you a question? Just imagine the origin of reality. What determined the structure of reality? In other words, there was nothing outside reality. According to general relativity, basically, reality is ontically and geometrically closed. So, there's nothing outside reality. According to general relativity, basically, reality is ontically and geometrically closed. So there's nothing outside. There's no extrinsic form of causation that could have caused the universe to take any particular form.
Starting point is 01:40:56 So aren't we talking about the universe taking its own form, somehow deciding within itself what form it should take? deciding within itself what form it should take. Deciding within itself can only happen if that decision is determined by what it is. Yes, but who decides what it is? Nobody. At the end of the day, at the bottom level of nature, something exists that cannot be explained in terms of anything else. We cannot explain one thing in terms of another forever. It doesn't matter what metaphysics one subscribes to.
Starting point is 01:41:29 One cannot keep on reducing forever. Otherwise, eventually you will go back to the beginning and it will be circular reasoning. Unless it's item potent. That actually applies to themselves. You don't get to the top of the ladder. You just keep on going from rung to rung, and each rung is identical to the last run, right?
Starting point is 01:41:46 Then it's some form of infinite regress. No, no, but idempotence says that it stays the same. You're not regressing anywhere, okay? It's just, it reaches a static point of maximum generalization, and then it holds steady. It doesn't make any difference what you do. You're going the other way around now. I'm thinking about reduction. I'm going down to the bottom. There has to be something at the bottom that simply is. It simply is what it
Starting point is 01:42:10 is. Now, earlier you said, for something to exist, it needs to have properties. To say that something is an object means that it has properties. So to be is to have properties. I agree with you there. To be is to have properties. Whatever it is that you are, you are one thing and not another. In other words, there are properties associated to your beingness. Now, whatever there is at the end of the chain of reduction, the bottom line of nature, it just is, and therefore it has properties. line of nature. It just is, and therefore it has properties. Everything that it does is then determined by its properties. It's determined by what it is, as opposed to what it is not, or to what it could have been. So even the mind of nature is a mind that has properties. That's awfully unspecific, though. I mean, we're not attaching any. You're not attaching any properties to this ultimate reduction that you're talking about.
Starting point is 01:43:08 But you're saying, and yet, everything that the universe is is somehow determined by it. I don't think that's quite kosher. I think that we have to actually try to attach some properties to it in order to derive. I just said to be is to have properties. So whatever there is at the bottom level of the chain of reduction, it has properties. Now, we may not know directly. Self-assigned properties, right? Yes. Intrinsic. Not self-assigned. It's intrinsic to the beingness of the thing. To be is to have properties. But against what background are we distinguishing those properties?
Starting point is 01:43:44 The background of what could have been. So the laws of nature are what background are we distinguishing those properties? The background of what could have been. So the laws of nature are what they are. So gravity makes objects fall. We could live in a universe in which gravity pulls objects up. It's a repellent as opposed to an attractor. Now, that's not what is. The laws of nature are what they are, as opposed to what they could have been in our imagination. So whatever nature is, it has properties.
Starting point is 01:44:10 And that's why objects fall and static electricity is produced when you rub ember to a cloth. So the stuff that is… I understand everything that you're saying. Okay, but if it had properties, then those properties had negations, and something had to distinguish those properties from their negations. Okay, otherwise it is useless to talk about them having properties at all. Following Langan and Kastrup on the nature of free will as a dynamical system, we transition again to David Wolpart, who discusses the limits or the no-goes on human cognition. These are also known as impossibility results and arise in Turing theory as limits of computational abilities.
Starting point is 01:44:53 These constrain our understanding of free will and bridge the metaphysical and mathematical. So we can never know what is the simplest program size for determining, what is the simplest program for actually doing those calculations. It's an amazing restriction on what we human beings can do. To give you another example, this is one that I know best from a book by Lee and Vitani. It's kind of like the Bible and these Turing machine things. You can actually prove the existence of a function from the integers to the integers, which is always increasing. Sometimes it'll stay the same, but it never goes down, and eventually gets to infinity,
Starting point is 01:45:40 such that every function you can possibly compute, no matter how you do it, that is also always increasing and gets to infinity, will be strictly greater than this. You wouldn't have even thought there is such a limitation that could even make sense. Do whatever you want. Say, okay, here's a function which has the value 1 for the first million numbers, for 1 through a million, it's got the value 1. Then it's got the value 2, but that's for the next million to the millionth. Make it be whatever you want. Any rule that you can put down for how to construct this, it's going to actually be getting to infinity faster than this other function,
Starting point is 01:46:28 which is a very strange thing. And it's one of the most fundamental philosophical results in the sense that philosophy should not be biased towards what we human beings consider to be compelling. I find it that impossibility results in general, and of these sorts in particular, they are very deep philosophy, whether or not we even appreciate they had meaning before we came across them. Another one- What was the name of that one, that second one? Oh, this is, I don't even think it has a name. I don't even think it has a name. I can point you to the chapter and leave it. Yeah, that'd be great. But there's
Starting point is 01:47:10 another one that, for example, Scott Aronson has a nice blog post on this. It's called the Busy Beaver Function. And he's actually recently written some papers on it as well. And this is kind of the flip side of what I just said, that let's try to make the fastest increasing function possible. So you, Kurt, say that, well, for the value one, it's got the value one. For the value two, it's got the value 10 to the 10 to the 10. For the value three, it's got what it had for the value 2, but now itself. Make it be whatever you want. There is always going to be something which is called the Busy Beaver function, which is actually increasing faster than the fastest increasing function you can write down. In other words, there's an upper limit to the speed of increase of any function from the integers to the integers that you can possibly define.
Starting point is 01:48:11 In a certain sense, it's mind-boggling that there's that kind of a limitation on what we can do. I'm not understanding it correctly. So, at first, the way that I understand what you said is that you have a function that's increasing, and then you can make it increase faster. But then there's a bound. There's a bound. I can write down the definition of a function, and it exists. I can prove it exists. And it is an increasing function, and it will be increasing faster than any function that you can possibly write down. Now, I have a question about that. Like I mentioned, I'm speaking to someone who's an ultra-finitist, an intuitionist, and they don't particularly like existence proofs. They like construction proofs. No, they don't. Yep, and that is the foundation of intuitionism. I don't think that actually Nicholas Gisson goes that far, though I'm not
Starting point is 01:48:59 sure. He might in some side idea in one of his papers. But yeah, that was the foundation. They don't like existence proofs. They want a constructive proof only. Is this constructed or you just showed the existence of this function? Of the busy beaver function? It has been constructed for the first some number of values of the integer. So we can write down a busy beaver function for one, for two, for three, for four, and so on, up to some particular value. But I think that in the busy beaver function, its entirety, almost by definition, no, it can't be constructed. Because if it could be constructed,
Starting point is 01:49:38 you would construct it. That's the point, that this thing exists. Wait, sorry, I don't get that last point. Wait, if it could be constructed, I could construct it. What do you mean? Um, so the definition,
Starting point is 01:49:49 so if, if, if by construct, if by construct a function, we mean you write down a program that spits out its values. That's what we mean to construct a function. Then the busy beaver function is something that increases faster than could be the output of any such program you can write down.
Starting point is 01:50:08 Ah, okay, okay, okay. I mean, it's very, very easy to define. And so, it is purely an existence function that you can't construct it, but I can define it very, very easily. It takes only a couple of sentences to define what the thing is. So there are these kinds of results which I find in many ways flabbergasting because if one adopts the Church-Turing thesis, these are limitations on human thinking. And there are other ones, and this is in addition to all the ones like the halting problem, you know, halting theorem, which is very closely related to, of course, some girls' incompleteness theorem.
Starting point is 01:50:57 And then there's Rises theorem and all these other things, which really, I think that the only actual philosophical advances that have been made by humanity are these kinds of results. Everything else is not only questionable and is being questioned. It is ultimately going to be quicksand and it's just going to be squishy and you're not going to get anywhere. These are the only ones that we have managed to generate so far. These are it, folks. By definition, they are the deepest because they are the full set of things that we have actually established incontrovertibly or as incontrovertible as any deductive logic could be for mathematics. We shift gears now from David Walpart's exploration of the limitations of
Starting point is 01:51:52 cognition and the deterministic nature of mathematical computation to Scott Aronson's perspective. Scott is a world-renowned computer scientist, a child prodigy, and a researcher in quantum computing. Here are his thoughts on free will. To you, does this touch on free will? Some people think it does. I mean, I tend to think that if there were a computer in another room and it ran faster than my brain does and it perfectly predicted what I was going to do before I do it. And, you know, maybe it just, it leaves its prediction in a sealed envelope, you know, but then after I take the action, then we can open the envelope and we can see that it perfectly predicted what I would do. I would say, you know, that would really profoundly shake my sense of free will, you know, just speaking personally, right? And I would say that based on the known laws of physics, we don't actually know
Starting point is 01:52:45 whether that prediction machine can exist or not, right? It comes down to, you know, questions about how accurately would you have to scan someone's brain? Would you have to go all the way down to the quantum mechanical level? You know, would that not be necessary? Right? And, and, and I would say that, that, you know, the thing that most people don't realize is that this is an empirical question. You know, who's who's who's, you know, maybe who's whose answer will someday know. But but but we don't know it yet. And that's the that's sort of, you know, what I would advocate as the best sort of empirical replacement for the free will question, right? And if you accepted that, then it's, you know, the fact that I myself can't predict, you know, my future actions is not really the core of the matter. You know, the question is just whether any machine could do it.
Starting point is 01:53:33 Yeah. Why is the sealed envelope important? Well, just because, well, because if I saw the prediction, then I could resolve to do the opposite. Yeah, right, right. So if this machine existed, does it still say something about your free will if you were able to look at it and you could go against the wishes of the machine or the predictions of it? Well, yeah, I mean, you could say if that machine cannot be reliably built, you know, if any attempt to build it consistent with the laws of physics, you know, fails, then that seems to me like about as far as science, you know, could possibly go in saying that, well, you know, there seems to be something that,
Starting point is 01:54:11 you know, that corresponds to part of what we mean by free will, right? There is this inherent unpredictability to our actions. And, you know, and conversely, if the machine did exist, and that seems to be, to me, like about as far as science could possibly go towards saying, you know, actually, you know, free will is an illusion, right? Not, you know, not just in some abstract metaphysical way, but because, you know, here is the machine that predicts what you will do, you know, look at it, try it out. Yeah, you had a blog post on Newcomb's paradox. Yes.
Starting point is 01:54:47 Can you please outline it and then what your proposed resolution is, if it exists? Sure. A Newcomb's paradox is the thing where, you know, we imagine this super intelligent predictor, you know, just like I was talking about before, you know, this sort of machine or being that, you know, knows what, you know, you're going to do before you do it. And it puts two boxes on a table. Okay.
Starting point is 01:55:12 And inside of the first box, you know, there might be nothing and there might be a million dollars. Okay. And inside of the second box, there is definitely $1,000. And now you have a choice. the second box, there is definitely $1,000. And now you have a choice. You can either take the first box only, or you can take both of the boxes. Okay, but now the predictor, the catch is that the predictor, you know, has told you in advance that if it predicts that you're going to take both boxes, then it will leave the first box empty. So it punishes greed. Yes, right. If it predicts that you're going to take only the first box, then it puts a million dollars in it. Okay, so and let's say that the predictor has played this game with, you know, 1000 people before you, and it's never been wrong. Right? So then, you know, what do you do? People have actually made it into verbs. Do you one box or do you two box in the Newcomb paradox? And there seem to be basic principles of rationality that you could use to prove either answer is correct, right? On the one hand, you know, everyone who takes only the first box
Starting point is 01:56:26 ends up, you know, about a million dollars richer than the people who try to take both, right? And, you know, by the whole setup of the problem is that, you know, that's because the predictor knew and, you know, it's over. But on the other hand, you know, by the time you're contemplating your decision, the million dollars is either in the box or not. Right. And so how could your decision possibly affect, you know, what is in the box, it would seem like it would have to be a backwards in time causation. Right. And therefore, you know, you know, whatever is in the first box, you're going to have $1,000 more than that, if you take both boxes, and therefore you should take both, right? So, so, you know, so we can prove two contradictory answers, you know, that is the basic setup of a
Starting point is 01:57:11 paradox. And, you know, and people have argued about this for half a century, there is an enormous literature on this problem. And, you know, many different points of view. I had a blog post back in 2006 where I suggested what seemed to me the natural resolution of this. And since then, I've learned that other people have had broadly similar ideas. Some of them do cite that blog post of mine. So, you know, some of them do cite that blog post of mine. But, you know, my resolution of the paradox was, okay, I think that, you know, in this scenario, you should take one box, right? You should one box. Okay, but the question is why, right? The question is, how can we possibly explain how your decision to one box could affect the predictor, could affect whether the predictor puts the money in the box. And now the key is, we have to think harder about what the world would be like with this predictor in it. The predictor contains within it a perfect simulation of you. I mean, whatever you're going to base your decision
Starting point is 01:58:26 on, you know, whatever childhood memory, whatever, you know, detail of your brain function, you know, the predictor knows all of it, right? By, you know, by hypothesis, right? But the way that I would describe that is that the predictor has effectively brought into being a second copy of you, a second instantiation of you, right? And now, you know, the key is that as you're contemplating your decision, whether to one box or two box, you know, you have to think of yourself as somehow, you know, being both versions of you at once, right? Or, you know, as somehow, you know, being both versions of you at once, right? Or, you know, or perhaps, you know, you don't know which one you are, right? If you are the simulation being run by the predictor, well, then, of course, your decision can affect what the predictor does. So, you know,
Starting point is 01:59:18 you don't even, you know, in the scenario, you know, that was hypothesized, like, you have to be radically uncertain about where you physically are, about what time it is, right? Like, these are the kinds of things that you have to worry about Newcomb's paradox because I believe that this predictor cannot exist at all. As I said, I regard that as an empirical question to which we don't yet know the answer. As I said, I regard that as an empirical question to which we don't yet know the answer. Again, that was Scott Aronson. Links to the full podcast of each of these guests are in the description, and you can always search their name plus my name, Kurt Jaimungal. You should also know that Theories of Everything is on every single audio platform like iTunes, Spotify, Pandora, Google Podcasts, etc. Just search Theories of Everything with with Kurt and you'll find it. That's Kurt with a C.
Starting point is 02:00:31 Now we switch from Scott Aronson's perspective, this time to another quantum computer scientist, Nicholas Jisson's perspective, which is that of indeterminism even in classical mechanics. Nicholas Jisson rejects the law of the excluded middle in propositions, and we explore the implications of that for free will. Okay, let's talk about Sabine Hossenfelder, who says that the idea of free will is both incompatible with the laws of nature and entirely meaningless. Okay, what are your thoughts on that statement? Yeah, so I know Sabine, and I use actually, so she does a lot of these videos, and I love most of them.
Starting point is 02:01:10 Now she has one indeed on free will, and actually I use that one when I give some of my lectures to illustrate how extreme some physicists, including very good physicists, can become. And indeed, in this video, Sabine goes really a very long way and, you know, claiming that if you believe in free will, you are denying science. So she's really claiming that actually science has answered the question in the negative, there is no free will. has answered the question in the negative, there is no free will. And this is, in my opinion, a clear overstatement. It's taking physics as a religion somehow, and it's physics with classical mathematics.
Starting point is 02:01:57 Again, we just discussed that. And it's pretty strange that Sabine Offenfelder makes that kind of mistake because one of her books, which I like very much, I think it's called Lost in Mathematics, actually says we have to be careful, we the physicists, have to be careful not to overestimate mathematics. You know, in high energy physics, people try to guess the future theories just by the beauty of mathematics, by symmetries and elegance and things like that. And so she says, no, but maybe actually the correct mathematics of the next physics theory will not be as elegant as we think or would like it to be.
Starting point is 02:02:55 So, okay, that's a reasonable argument, and I certainly buy that argument. But then herself takes classical Platonistic mathematics as the truth. And because Platonistic mathematics considers only objects, mathematical objects that are outside of time, it's a timeless language, classical mathematics. And so when she concludes that time cannot exist, and that everything has already to be settled. So she also believes strongly in super determinism. You know, everything is already determined, there is no quantum randomness, Bell inequality violations can be explained by super determinism. And yeah, at least she's very consistent as a Celtic mentor. But when she claims that science has proved it, for instance, the idea that free will is an illusion, she goes too far.
Starting point is 02:03:58 And she goes too far by taking mathematics too literally. Earlier in the conversation, you said indeterminacy is a necessary condition for free will. It's not sufficient. However, any indeterminate theory can be made determinate with supplementary variables. We can talk about that just for people who are wondering what the heck that means. And then similarly, a determinate theory can be made indeterminate, so they're equivalent. And thus, is determinacy truly a necessary condition for free will? Yeah, well, the way to make an indeterministic theory deterministic is by adding variables. And the trivial way of adding variables is just to
Starting point is 02:04:37 add all the future results of all future events or future measurements. It's a trivial way of doing it. It's not very practical, not very useful, but obviously you can always do that. Somehow maybe one could say that instead of God playing dice when an event happened, God played all dice at the initial condition, at the Big Bang, and coded all this information of all these dice that he played there initially,
Starting point is 02:05:06 he coded it into the initial conditions, the initial conditions of these real numbers that contain all this information of all future events. Or in Bohmian quantum mechanics, it's a similar idea. You have this additional variable that also contains infinite information and that somehow in a clever way, code all the outcomes of all possible future measurements. So you can always do that.
Starting point is 02:05:33 But you don't want just to be able to do it. You want to be able to do it in a faithful way. You want to describe nature in a faithful way. And adding the result of future measurements into your initial condition, I don't think this is a faithful description. When I was speaking with Carlo Rovelli, he said there are two interpretations of quantum mechanics that he feels like are consistent, relational quantum mechanics and then the many worlds.
Starting point is 02:06:02 Of course. Right, of course. But he doesn't like the many worlds interpretation so he chooses the relational one now from my understanding of your views there can't be a wave function of the universe because this can't just simply evolve in time determinately is that an incorrect meaning no no correct correct okay now does that mean that you don't believe in the many worlds interpretation no No, not at all. I think that's quite an empty concept.
Starting point is 02:06:29 And I think the explanatory power of many worlds is essentially zero. Again, it's again one of these things which is super deterministic. There is the initial wave function of the universe, and then everything evolves according to that. And there is never any event that happens. Nothing really happens. It's just this unitary evolution, which is an enormous rotation in this gigantic Hilbert space. So I think that there's nothing happening there.
Starting point is 02:06:59 You cannot tell a story here. No, no. So my view, I'm much closer. I'm not claiming that I have the solution to all these problems, but my feeling is much closer, my heart is much closer to a spontaneous localization theory, so stochastic evolution of the Schrodinger equation. And so in this way also, as time passes, this Schrodinger equation, this wave function, sorry, gets added additional information, a bit like my numbers for classical mechanics. And as time passes, this additional information that gets added to the wave function may localize it here or there with appropriate probabilities.
Starting point is 02:07:46 And we have stochastic equations doing that perfectly. I won't keep you for much longer. I know that you probably have to get going soon. So I'll just ask a couple more questions. Now, going back to when you were younger and your little Nicholas was philosophizing in his armchair and you dabbled with different logical systems. So we talked about periconsistent and intuitionist.
Starting point is 02:08:04 Did you dabble with questioning even if logic should be the basis of mathematics itself? Well, when I did my PhD in Geneva, indeed a long time ago, my PhD advisor, Professor Piron, was actually a guy working in quantum logic. I don't think himself really believed in quantum logic, but there are many people around. And so we had visitors who were really thinking of this quantum logic and that by changing the laws of logic, we could make sense of better sense of quantum mechanics. I don't think that this is an interesting approach.
Starting point is 02:08:48 I think that that's okay. So my answer to your question is no. And again, this is so I'm rejecting the law of the excluded middle, essentially, about propositions that concern the future. You know, my bicycle, now you may ask, is my bicycle on that side or on that side? Well, maybe I forgot. Actually, I know, but let's suppose I forgot. Even if I forgot where my bicycle is, my bicycle is definitely either there or there.
Starting point is 02:09:20 It's not in an indeterminate position. Now, if you ask me, where will my bicycle be in a week time? or there, it's not in an indeterminate position. Now, if you ask me, where will my bicycle be in a week time? That's indeterminate, as of today. One of my favorite ways of showing that classical mechanics has indeterminacy built in it is Norton's Dome. Have you heard of Norton's Dome? Yes, yes, I know that. Yeah, well, but this is a very nice example that shows that indeed you may have initial conditions that don't determine the future of these dynamical systems.
Starting point is 02:09:55 But you need very specific dynamical systems. You need this dome. That's why it's called a dome. this dome, that's why it's called a dome, in such a way that if you have a particle coming to that dome, it will, okay, if you don't throw it hard enough, it will just go up and back again. If you throw it too far, it goes over it and goes to the other side.
Starting point is 02:10:18 So there's precisely an initial condition, an initial velocity, such that it will stop at the top. And that doesn't exist for all domes. It exists only for very specific domes. And for these very specific domes, so of course, whether or not the ball comes from that side or from any side, let's suppose it's a two-dimensional thing,
Starting point is 02:10:35 from any direction, it can stop at the top, which means now the initial condition, it may go at any time in any direction. And that will always be a solution of the Newton's equation. So this is fascinating indeed. But I don't think it's super convincing because, you know, if you change the shape of that dome by an epsilon, by a little bit, by an epsilon, by a little bit, it's gone. I mean, this peculiarity is gone. So it is not a generic feature. It's a feature of some very, very specific domo potential, as we call it.
Starting point is 02:11:15 The reason why I like it is because I know that it's predicated on real numbers and so on. So maybe that's another dispute you have with it. The reason why I like it is that even in the classical domain, we can show that it doesn't have certain with it. The reason why I like it is that even in the classical domain, we can show that it doesn't have certain continuity condition. And then because of that, it allows for multiple solutions. And not only that, but you mentioned that it's not a generic feature. I don't know if there's a result that says, much like we can say that the typical real number has infinite information in it. I don't know if there's a result that says the typical configuration of matter is that which has a Lipschitz continuity condition. I would think it's the opposite. I would think that
Starting point is 02:11:47 not satisfying the Lipschitz continuity condition would be typical if we have the general space of functions. But I don't know if that's true. I don't know if there's a result like that. Okay. I also don't know. My bet is that this is very specific and that generically we don't have this phenomenon, but I'm not sure about that. My last question is, with regard to quantum gravity, is there an approach that you favor? make relativity indeterministic. But you know, that's a vast program. Okay, now let's get to the audience questions. This one comes from Stephen E. Robbins.
Starting point is 02:12:35 A great question to ask Nicholas is, I'm curious if he has looked at Bergson, Time and Free Will. Wait, yes, I'm curious if he's looked at Bergson. So that's it. Yeah, yeah. So's looked at Bergson. So that's it. Yeah, so I looked at it, I read some of it. I mean, it's too large, I didn't read everything. Certainly, a lot of his writing resonates. But somehow, that's where I'm a physicist, much more fun a philosopher, and thereson was clearly a philosopher.
Starting point is 02:13:08 So at some point, it is kind of too vague. I cannot really grasp it. I cannot really anchor on it. And yeah, so for that reason, I think I cite him even in one of my papers, things like that. So I'm certainly sympathetic, but it's not really my way of doing physics or science. Now, this question comes from Complex Plane at K-E-K-U-L-E-6. Does he think that the denial of free will by physicists is an attempt to make evidence fit a model? Now Chomsky says that it may be something outside human cognitive abilities, that is free will, to understand. Does he hold a similar view? So again, I mean, for me, free will comes first in this logical order.
Starting point is 02:14:09 So you need it to start arguing about the existence of free will. So somehow you cannot really deny the existence of free will, because if you want to argue against the existence of free will, you need free will to be able to buy or not buy the argument. Then someone may say, well, how is it that you're choosing so-and-so? Because we use our free will to choose among possibilities. Are you saying there's nothing that influences that? Is it random? How does that work? No, no, no, no.
Starting point is 02:14:30 So, of course, we get influenced. I mean, obviously, we are under very heavy influence. So free will is not something that we use continuously and so on. I mean, most of our decisions are not so important and so on. And we get influenced by ads and whatever. And they're also not random. I mean, they might be partially random. You can, for instance, decide whether you go to a restaurant tonight
Starting point is 02:14:59 by just tossing a coin. So sometimes it will be. But most of the time it will be not random and not predetermined. Now you may say but who is now making the decision is there a little guy in my brain? Well, it should be myself. So I'm not sitting in my brain or whatever. So that's where brain or whatever. So that's where our understanding of what free will is, is limited. We don't have this kind of understanding. Maybe it comes also back to what you asked initially about consciousness, like somehow, like, am I making conscious decisions? not always, by the way, but sometimes I'm making conscious decisions. And yeah, I'm not sure I have much more to add on that.
Starting point is 02:15:56 Our decisions are extremely determined by our environment, but being extremely determined is not the same as being fully determined. Exactly. There is room for some decisions. There are clearly some decisions where we spend a lot of time thinking about, we really wage, we discuss with ourselves, maybe also with our friends and relatives. And there are clearly also other discussions, decisions, sorry, that we don't really care much and uh that much easier and where we can yeah accept that we get uh seriously influenced by the outside world professor thank you so much for spending some of your time with me i appreciate it i know it's late where you are
Starting point is 02:16:41 no it's okay it's a 20 past 20 20 past eight so no that that's perfect uh so thank you very much for for your time and uh yeah tell me when that will be online very good thank you thank you for your interest in uh in physics in science in free will and in my poor understanding of all those. Now we switch one more time back to David Walpart, who challenges us to redefine free will in a way that is not only provable, but aligns with our common understanding of the term. How about we define free will, or you define free will, and then tell the audience what your inference theorems have to say about free will. You'll have to define free will and also define what your inference theorem is, and then what the theorems have to say about free will. You'll have to define free will and also define what your inference theorem is and then what the inference theorem has to say about free will.
Starting point is 02:17:28 Okay, so first a warning. There is an unfortunate tendency. It should have a particular name as one of the rhetorical fallacies. It's, you know, the ad hominem fallacy, the this fallacy, the that fallacy. For people to take a term that's in very common use and is very controversial because of all these reasons, they want to establish that it's true. So they redefine it in a certain way that they can establish that it's true that redefinition all of the original reasons that it was so controversial they are now defined out and what you're left with is actually a very different kind of a concept
Starting point is 02:18:21 and they now then herald it and say, oh, look, I've just proved such and such where what they've really done is redefined it in such a way that they could prove it. But all the reason people were interested in the first place is now out of their new definition. So it's a bait and switch. The fallacy is called Martin Bailey, I believe. Martin Bailey. Okay. How's that spelled? M-O-T-T-E, and then Bailey's as the drink, I believe. Martin Bailey. Essentially, you take some fact, and then you're strawmanning it, and you use the strawman to disprove the larger one.
Starting point is 02:18:56 Yeah, or to prove it, as the case might be. Martin Bailey, that's nice. I've got to look that up later. So continue. So, yes. So, for example, certainly if you're familiar with the concept, the notion of God has been treated that way. You know, many people would say, oh, Einstein really believed in God because, you know, he said the laws of nature, and so the laws
Starting point is 02:19:16 of nature is God. But of course, the reason that God is considered to be a controversial topic is because it's a bananthropromorphized. It's this dude in the sky with a big beard who's deciding who's going to win the football game Sunday night. And that's the one that's controversial and so on and so forth. And Einstein wasn't saying anything about in favor of that particular one. And Einstein wasn't saying anything about in favor of that particular one. So it's a little bit of a Martin Bailey. And frankly, I think that he has done some great work and he's a good friend and a great guy. But I think that Dan Dennett was recently involved in this with free will.
Starting point is 02:20:07 He wrote a book and he tries to now claim I've with free will. He wrote a book in which he tries to now claim, I've proven free will. And in essence, he's defined away its aspects that made it controversial in the first place. So what do I mean by free will? There's one aspect to it, which would be that of the people who write dictionaries. What does it mean in common discourse? And when I think free will means a common discourse has something to do with a means by which it is possible to abrogate the laws of deterministic science in such a way that a human's cognitions are not subject to those laws.
Starting point is 02:20:56 So that what is going on in your head right now is not some very complicated, too complicated to calculate, but nonetheless inviolable function of what it was you were thinking 10 seconds ago, together with the sensory stimuli from the environment. But somehow there's something else that is not subject to any laws of science, in some sense. It's not even subject to stochastic laws. It's just amorphous and ill-defined. And so, certainly, all of us have a subjective experience
Starting point is 02:21:35 of such a thing. But the proponents of free will in this sense, which is controversial, would say that no, that's actually an objective truth. I don't see that there's any room for that, to be quite honest. So, in that sense, no, I don't, if that's what, if we do adopt that kind of a definition, which I think isn't in accord with the way it's used in common parlance, no, I don't see. There's any room for such a thing. You can maybe kind of get close and Scott Aronson, again, he's involved, engaged in a Martin Bailey's in this particular paper of his, but he and even worse Martin Bailey's is Seth Lloyd. They try to make the case that Turing machine notions of computability provide a way out in that they say that, yes, it might be, there are various flavors of the argument, but one version of it is, yes, the present state of
Starting point is 02:22:34 your mind is a deterministic function of what it was and so on, but it's an uncomputable function in some technical senses. Yeah, Stephen Wolfram says something similar where he uses his term computational irreducibility and says, well, yes, there are outcomes that are computationally irreducible, and that's where free will may live, but ultimately you don't have control over the laws. It's still a deterministic step-by-step algorithmic process. Yeah. And in a certain sense, it's kind of interesting because one might ask in terms of the laws of science or physics or how the universe actually evolves, is there any room for anything besides deterministic or stochastic evolution? I can write down the definition. You can go look it up in math textbooks what a stochastic process
Starting point is 02:23:24 is. And you can look up in math textbooks, what a stochastic process is. And you can look up in math textbooks, what a deterministic convertible process is. And you can actually formulate the one is a special case of the other. Is there any way you can even in theory, imagine science that would not be either random or deterministic? Is there anything else it could possibly be? And there are notions in the original motivation for Komogorov in terms of his work on Komogorov complexity and many other people who are wondering about intrinsic randomness, what does complexity mean, what does random really mean? They came up with definitions which is something that is random, but is not random, but it has no probability distributions.
Starting point is 02:24:24 whether that's a difference without significance or whether there is a significance to that possibility that physical systems might in essence violate the physical church Turing thesis and have this kind of an uncomputable character to them which is not random and it's not deterministic but it's something different and that whether that has any kinds of consequences even if it's true. So that's interesting in almost like a philosophy of science kind of a way. But it really is, I would say, irredeemably far from what people mean by free will to really say that's relevant to the discussions that people have about what free will is. I think for them, for the vast majority, for what philosophers have meant by it for millennia, it's certainly nothing to do with comagorical complexity and turning machines
Starting point is 02:25:11 and so on and so forth. It's simply the notion of this supernatural in the literal sense of above nature, above the laws of nature, which is inherent in me and my soul, and I cannot even define it because it is something that's non definable. And that allows for superseding of the laws of physics when it comes to my own brain. That's what is sometimes meant. I think that's most fully what is meant by people who are talking about free will, have been talking about it historically, and I almost view it as a non-starter. And what I'm saying is that when I'm over there wearing my metaphysics hat, if I'm just going to push metaphysics to be what I personally, David Wolpert, I'm interested in, which is all the
Starting point is 02:26:06 way down the road reasonably. Yeah, I see. I see. Okay, I see. So, let me put it like this. It sounds like what you're saying is if one is making a claim that your brain, David, that you have some free will and it supervenes the laws of physics. Sorry, it doesn't super... So, physics supervenes on that your free will somehow determines the laws of physics, at least momentarily enough for a neuron to fire differently. And so therefore you have free will. So you have some, your free will has some ontological status. And then you're saying, well, okay, where along the chain from electrons to cells to neurons to, well, neuron is this type of stuff, to the whole brain configuration to your behavior where on that chain was physical law broken because you can look at any given one of those chains and you can say well look at if there's no violation of physical law and so if the nebulous person is making the claim about some nebulous concept like free will you'd better show me where it comes in so far the laws of physics are not violated at any level as far as we've examined it. Is that
Starting point is 02:27:05 what you're saying? Essentially, yeah. As opposed to, do I have a feeling of free will? Yes, I do. Okay, now what I would say to that is, I'd still say that we don't know, and I don't think you're making the claim that you know either. So I don't think that we're speaking differently. Let me put a bit of a monkey wrench. So when we look and we examine any one of these features, so we look at, let's say, the electron bound with a proton, we say there are no laws of physics being violated here. This is all explainable with what we have currently as our models. Or at least we have the idea that some other model may exist in the future. And then cells and so on and so on.
Starting point is 02:27:40 It's as if you're looking individually at small parts, but still, the counterclaim could be that you show me that the laws of physics are obeyed for someone making a decision across the whole spectrum and not looking at it individually across different people in different circumstances and saying, here, it's not violated. It would be almost as if what you're doing is looking at a small billiard ball bouncing around in a small environment saying, there's no time here, there's no time there's no time here but yet you're saying you're saying that there's time at the higher level there can be there can be emerging i mean phil anderson's more is different you can have um laws i mean that's what condensed matter physics is all about parisi just won you know the nobel prize for um spin glass models which is thermodynamic limit, an infinite number of
Starting point is 02:28:25 phenomena that arise, strictly speaking, only when you have an infinite number of these interactive models, but it's all being governed by mathematics. And so, you're correct. I'm not saying that I now, and maybe not humanity ever, would even be able to fill in all those steps. would even be able to fill in all those steps. I'm saying that there is a consistent picture in which those steps are part of a mathematics, which may forevermore be beyond humans. But I'm then going a little bit further and saying, give me, provide for me anything other than essentially an elaborated version of describing the experience that you have when looking at a beautiful painting, something that's got something that is not mathematics. I don't even see what one could call free will.
Starting point is 02:29:37 Other than, I just don't even understand what else there could be besides mathematics and then aesthetics. I don't see that there's, I don't see how we can be doing reasoning, reasoning rigid. Ironclad, we know that with the things that Ironclad could come up with, given all the stuff about noise deterministic reasoning, deductive reasoning, but how we can actually come to any kinds of conclusions
Starting point is 02:30:00 if we're not using logic. Let me say that, second-order logic. That's part of mathematics. Second-order logic is part of mathematics. And I don't see how we can even define the terms in something like what is called in mathematical logic a language, where you've got an associated set of axioms and so on and so forth, I don't even see how we can be speaking about it in those terms. I don't see what philosophy can be if it's not that.
Starting point is 02:30:39 I see. When we're talking about how some of these philosophical claims are volutinous, they're bleary, they're opaque, dubious, you don philosophical claims are volutinous, they're bleary, they're opaque, dubious, you don't know what the heck it means because they're speaking ambiguously. And then you're saying, well, I don't know what it means. I understand what mathematics would mean if mathematics was fundamental. For me, please help clarify for me, what the heck does that mean? Because to me, that's just equally, I can understand the statement that mathematics
Starting point is 02:31:04 describes what we've seen so far. But then to say that mathematics is what we've seen so far, I don't understand what that is, is. What is the mathematics? And then when we say it's a rule, what is a rule? We can play that game. So can you help me understand the ontology? This is the, so first of all
Starting point is 02:31:25 assuming that we're not worrying here about things like girdles and completeness theorem or the other things about math eating its own tail
Starting point is 02:31:31 sure we're not trying to do for example Pressburger arithmetic which would allow you to avoid girdles and completeness theorem
Starting point is 02:31:39 or anything it that's one of the things that I find so a deep flaw or attribute in me is that the more I can be smashed on my ass by the universe, realizing that I have been misconstruing my limitations for being those of the universe, the more I feel I'm making progress, the more I actually,
Starting point is 02:32:21 that's my aesthetic acme. I don't think I can answer your question. And that's to me, and I understand your question and feel your question. And the fact that I cannot answer it to me is a beautiful, stunning illustration of the fact that the deficiency is in me. It's a feature, not a bug. It's a feature, not a bug. And we arrive now to Brian Keating. Again, links to every single one of these full-length
Starting point is 02:32:57 podcasts are in the description. Keating explores the ontological underpinnings of the materialistic perspective of consciousness. explores the ontological underpinnings of the materialistic perspective of consciousness. This question comes from Vison Cosman. This is to both of you. Ask all of your materialist guests to give one single example of something outside of consciousness. I think there are great difficulties in doing that simply because we are the ghost in the machine that is defining, A, what consciousness is, what our experience is, what is materialistic or not. I should say that I'm much more – I'm much less materialistic than I assume Lee is. I know what Lee is.
Starting point is 02:33:41 I don't know so much about Kurt, but I'd love to know more, in that there are, what I usually talk about is, you know, are there, is there permission to believe? Not the proof. I said this on Lex's podcast. Like, I don't care if I believe in God. You know, like, does God need me? Does God care about Brian Keating? Who gives a crap? You know, maybe if God believes in me, you know, if God exists. But the question of whether or not you – I'm a behaviorist, so I think that people manifest how they behave. The underlying consciousness that they are internalized, that they have internalized is manifest externally by their behaviors. So I look to things like religion in a very practical sense. Can this give community? Can this give, can this give community, can this give a purpose,
Starting point is 02:34:26 can this without necessarily accepting the reality as provable in a scientific context? I don't think you can prove or disprove. And I give upbraid my religious friends too. I say, if you don't learn science, you're, you're basically just, you know, kind of living in this, in this bubble. If you don't learn, because science may actually bolster your faith. As I said, in Lex's podcast, and I've said it in other places, what if the fact that we can perceive an infinite spectrum of colors, an infinite diversity of life, an infinite number of tastes and dimensionality of things, it could be otherwise.
Starting point is 02:35:05 dimensionality of what could be otherwise. And the fact that the universe is extravagant is potentially a clue, a symbol, a talisman. I'm not saying it's proof, of course, because I don't think there can be proof. But I think those are sort of non-materialistic. But again, it's materialistic in a reductionist sense, because I do believe that you can practice it for your own benefit. You can glean wisdom from it. You can glean experience, community, charity, things that improve you, Stoicism. I'm one of the few people, I read the Christian Bible every day and the Jewish Bible every day. I read the Stoics, the ancient Greeks, the Romans. These are things that I think broaden your mind, whether you believe it has to be true
Starting point is 02:35:43 or not. So I'm more of a pragmatist, I would say, in terms of what consciousness things could not be explainable via science. On a day-to-day basis, do I think that it's not possible to learn about the universe? Of course not. No, I do. I believe we can learn tremendously about the composition, the structure of the universe on a practical level. And so, to be honest, I don't really concern myself so much of these questions, the ultimate question, like, do I exist? Do I have free will? I actually don't personally find those interesting. I know you're interested in it. Yeah. Forget about if you find it interesting. Do you happen to believe
Starting point is 02:36:21 that you have free will? I do. Yeah, I do. And how does that comport with your experimentalist reductionism? I don't know if you believe in reductionism, but it's I don't, I don't necessarily believe in reductionism. I find all these things kind of, again, so I participated with Stuart Hoffman, who is a good friend, not Stuart Hoffman, Stuart Hammeroff at University of Arizona, who runs a science of consciousness seminar every other year, alongside Roger Penrose and others. And actually, Noam Chomsky spoke with me a few years ago here in San Diego when I was here. And, you know, I became very frustrated and disillusioned a little bit, because they couldn't even, like, say for sure what consciousness
Starting point is 02:37:03 was. And yet they said they have a science of consciousness, or they're working towards a science of consciousness. I know Sam Harris is the hard problem. I think the burden is on other people who believe that there isn't free will and there is super determinism. And I know people will just throw it around like the block universe, but there's no evidence for it. So I guess the question is – Okay, I'll give you – Yeah, go ahead. I'll play devil's advocate. Sure. Let's say you have free will.
Starting point is 02:37:41 Okay, well, so that means you made a decision of your own choosing. Well, what caused you to choose in that particular direction? And then if you say, well, I had some play in that, well, then I asked what caused that? It's just what caused until you get to something that is outside of you. So for example, the initial conditions of the Big Bang, maybe or your mother giving birth to you, which you didn't choose. How is it that you have free will? I guess I would ask kind of like the Turing quote, like, how would you tell the difference? Like if I did have free will, you know, uh, you know, as they say, like, I have to believe in free will. I have no choice. Uh, but, but the question of, you know, I would say, isn't that,
Starting point is 02:38:19 is that the super, you know, the superset of all events that have taken place since the big bang, if you want to say that that's deterministic, when we know that there's certain quantum decoherent effects that cannot be modeled as, as intrinsically being deterministic or could possibly allow for, um, for violations of certain bells inequalities. Uh, if you look at it that way, I guess it's just that, then it becomes very, very too much, too all encompassing. So like I recount to somebody a couple of days ago, like when I was dating my wife, we went to an astrologer and she knew I didn't believe in astrology and she wanted to have fun. So she said, go tell her, uh, tell her about yourself and she'll predict your horoscope.
Starting point is 02:38:59 And so I said, yeah, I'm Pisces. I do this, this, and this. And she said, Oh, it's going to be good. You guys are going to do this. And, and, and I said, is it, is it really true that Pisces are born in September? I forgot. Oh no, you're born in September. Yeah. I'm born in September. Oh, you're a Virgo. But don't worry. This, everything I said is still going to happen. So it's like, what was the, what is the difference? Like if everything is so all encompassing, then I guess I'm a Virgo too, by the way. Oh, you are. Okay. Well, Virgos are the ones in their right minds or something. I don't know. I think, you know.
Starting point is 02:39:26 I think you're right. I think you're right. Well, I also happen, I wouldn't say I believe in free will, but I don't find the arguments against free will as particularly convincing. I just want to know what your opinion was. So is it your counter argument is that, is the Turing test, how would you tell one way or the other? It's an experiment in this question.
Starting point is 02:39:44 Exactly. And isn't it, I'm a pragmatist, Kurt, you know, at the end of the day, you know, what I'm concerned about are things that I can get a crisp answer to. So I don't believe I'll ever get a crisp answer to that, nor do I, and you could ask me about God, and I don't think I'm going to have like some answer about God or the existence of God. But I think, you know, I think a place for a physicist, especially an experimentalist, is to be agnostic, but actually agnostic, which means like if you just don't go to church or you don't go to synagogue, in my case, you go to the same, you know, you have the same religious performance as Richard Dawkins.
Starting point is 02:40:22 Like there's no functional delineation between you and richard dawkins i actually had this conversation with freeman dyson before he passed away you know because he said he's an agnostic and i said well what church do you go to i don't really go to church i said so oh so you go to the same church as richard dawkins and he's like cognitive dissonance a little bit so um i when i when i look at is uh behaviorism so how do i behave and if i knew that everything was controlled uh, you know, the initial condition state, if there was a big bang, which we don't. So I guess I think about it in terms of what is the pragmatic day-to-day implication of
Starting point is 02:40:56 this? Does it have any bearing on me individually? So in the case of free will, I don't think it does. I don't think I'll behave differently and treat my kids, you know, like one kid hits another one. I say, oh, well, you don't really have free will. So I'm not going to be, no, of course I'm going to punish them or make them understand and apologize. I'm not going to lay it off. As some people like Michael Shermer, I've had this conversation, you know, he basically is much more libertine about this. On the other hand, if God exists, that's a much bigger question, right? And I'm not saying if I believe or I don't. As I said, I'm a fully practicing devout agnostic,
Starting point is 02:41:32 meaning I go to services, I read and I learn, I've taught myself Aramaic so I could understand the arguments of the second holiest book in Judaism called the Talmud. I learned that at age 30. It wasn't easy. And I study it on a regular basis because I want to take it seriously. Because if God exists, that would have a, if you knew, I don't know your religious beliefs and it almost doesn't matter to me, but if you knew, like I asked Sean Carroll this question, I said, you want, you know, what is the probability of the multiverse is true? He said 50%. And I said, what's the probability that God exists? He said less than 5%. He didn't say zero. So imagine now, that means he's open. He is a brilliant man. So I could tell him, let's say I provide evidence, whatever, some miracle that he can't dismiss.
Starting point is 02:42:17 And then he believes it. So he would change his life. I know that he would, even though I don't think he thinks the probability is even that high, by the way. But it was a good soundbite. We had a good conversation about it. But do you know what I'm saying, Kurt? The bottom line is, I am concerned with things that will impact my life as a behaviorist. How will it change my behavior? How will I change my treatment of the poor, the sick, my wife, my kids, you? How will I change my behavior is much more influenced to the good, I would say, by wrestling with the question of whether or not God exists. Whether or not it does exist is an important question for that reason. Because if the answer is yes, it would have huge implications. And even Dawkins has said, like, he doesn't rule it out. So, but free will,
Starting point is 02:43:01 if you told me that, you know, everything is super deterministic, it wouldn't change how I operate on a daily basis. Alright, we're now done with the philosophical musings on free will of Brian Keating. We will segue into Josje Bak's exposition on the nature of free will. Josje Bak sees free will as an outflow of a control algorithm and explicates its implications for human behavior. Where does free will come in? Free will is a representation in the system that it's made a decision, and the decision is being made on the best understanding of what's correct.
Starting point is 02:43:47 And free will is basically the outflow of this control task. It's the outflow of the control algorithm being executed in the right way. The opposite to free will is not determinism. If you are indeterministic, you cannot have free will. If you behave randomly, there is no will involved, right? It's just random. And the opposite to free will is also not coercion because you are deciding that you are giving into the coercion you wouldn't need to be coerced if you wouldn't have a degree of freedom but uh the opposite to free will is
Starting point is 02:44:18 compulsion it's basically when you do something despite knowing better the opposite of free will is compulsion as well as randomness? So randomness is the absence of will at all, right? The system that is random has no will. So the will cannot be free or not. So we have to look at the opposite of the freedom. And the opposite of the freedom is not the coercion, it's the compulsion. What's the difference?
Starting point is 02:44:42 The compulsion means that you have a model of what you should be doing, but you don't find yourself acting on it. You find yourself acting on something else. You are acting based on some impulse or some addiction. And that is basically the true impingement on your freedom. But it's important to realize that freedom is not an absolute notion in the physical sense. It's a reference that we make to certain internal states. experiential context experienced by will is free when i have the impression that i made the decision based on parameters that are the right ones that are in the proper order with respect to the control structures that my mind currently implements and not because of some glitch in
Starting point is 02:45:37 the matrix of some glitch in the system that implements me or of some erroneous programming or some external force that is spreading in my mind so when people have the impression that they interact out of a compulsion for instance because they say for instance have anorexia they might decide to or bulimia they might decide not to throw up after eating but they cannot cannot help themselves. They just have this enormous urge to throw up or make themselves throw up. There's nothing that they can do about this. And it's a very disturbing experience because it impinges on your freedom. There is one thing that you want to do and another thing that you find yourself to be doing. We now transition from Josje Bok's views on consciousness and free will to Carl Fristens,
Starting point is 02:46:26 transition from Josje Bok's views on consciousness and free will to Carl Fristens, who will illustrate the function of consciousness from a free energy principle perspective. There's one quote that I love, that I try to live by, and it's only the shallowest of minds would think that in great controversy one side is mere folly. I'm sure you've heard that before. I haven't heard that particular one. I've heard something similar. Okay, so do you believe in free will? And if so, how do you define it? So free will, yeah. I mean, you asked do I believe in it. There's certainly space for free will
Starting point is 02:47:00 in the realization of a free energy principle in sentient artifacts at many levels. When you actually come to write down and simulate or build little toy agents, you very quickly realize that the most interesting, in fact, the only interesting behaviors that you can simulate arise when you write down the generative models as containing autonomous dynamics, usually of a chaotic sort.
Starting point is 02:47:35 So the reason I use the word autonomous dynamics is that mathematically speaking, there's a sort of free will in the autonomy. is that mathematically speaking, there's a sort of free will in the autonomy. Even in a deterministic setting, there is an unpredictability, given the initial conditions, that cannot be determined. So in that sense, there has to be a mathematical kind of free will at play. The other sort of take, I guess, on free will comes back to what we were talking about before, about making our own sensations, creating our own sensorium. So if you remember that from the point of view of minimizing um prediction error as surprise
Starting point is 02:48:28 there are two ways i can do that i can um change my mind so that my predictions are more like what i'm sensing and that would be a minimization of prediction error through perception but there's another way of doing that minimizing the prediction now i actually just change what i'm sampling to make the sensations more like the predictions so that's you know that's action in the service of minimizing surprise or prediction but what that means is that my actions are basically in enslaved to where they can fulfill my predictions. So they are in the service of fulfilling prophecies. So collectively, action perception is a self-fulfilling prophecy.
Starting point is 02:49:13 And in that sense, I think you can find free will. If we are creating our own worlds and our own sensory inputs, we're constructing our sensorium. Who else is doing it? So in that very simple, I won't say deflationary, but simple account of free will, then I can't see how it could be any other way. As we move from Carl Friston to Noam Chomsky, Chomsky will take us through a history of the philosophical thought on free will. I'm curious about your views on consciousness. If you've ever had any experiences, whether it's with psychedelics or marijuana or an unconscionable amount of alcohol or meditation that has changed your views on consciousness. That's part of my universe.
Starting point is 02:50:02 I'm probably the only person you've ever spoken to who never used marijuana. So what do you think the function of consciousness is? It's our window into the world and into ourselves. Very fragmentary. Most of what's going on in our mind is completely inaccessible to consciousness. Do you take a materialist standpoint, that is, that the world is made up of atoms and from that consciousness is an epiphenomenon,
Starting point is 02:50:38 or do you see consciousness as foundational at some level ontologically? foundational at some level ontologically? There is no clear notion of materialism, so it's impossible to answer. By materialism, we mean anything we more or less understand. And I'm curious to know what your views are on free will. Free will? views are on free will free will like a hundred percent of other people even those who deny it i think i can decide right now whether to lift my finger up or down
Starting point is 02:51:14 science tells us essentially nothing about this it only tells us we can't incorporate it within our current understanding of science. Okay. So there's a certain sense that material reality from some of the people that we've been speaking to is secondary to that of consciousness. They think that it's a material that's more epiphenomenal. That's more of an epiphenomenomena as opposed to consciousness being something that sparked from the material world. And we were curious because we know you have more kind of materialistic aspects or atheistic aspects in your thinking.
Starting point is 02:51:55 If you thought there was something that was more transcendent or if you think it's something more material, something more like it's just us on earth. Well, that discussion can only be pursued if you have some notion of what the material world is. So what is it? Actually, if you look at the history, there was a quite interesting debate about this several centuries ago. So the foundations of modern science, Galileo, Descartes, Newton, Huygens, Leibniz, the great scientists of the 17th century, developed a concept of material world. The concept was called the mechanical philosophy. Philosophy meant science, so it's mechanical science. The idea was that the world is a machine.
Starting point is 02:52:56 It's like the complex artifacts that skilled artisans were producing and spreading all around Europe. Mechanical clocks, performances that looked like real actors, digestion of a duck, the fountains at Versailles, all over the place, incredible machines. And the assumption was, well, the world is just a bigger machine. Machine meant what it means to you and me, levers, gears, and things pushing and pulling each other and so on. And that was the reigning doctrine, the idea that Galileo and others considered a theoretical account
Starting point is 02:53:50 not acceptable if it wasn't, if you couldn't construct a machine to duplicate it. Well, Newton came along and showed that there are no machines, none. He thought that was a total absurdity, spent the rest of his life trying to overcome it. His associate, the other great scientists of the day, Leibniz and Huygens and others accused him of reinstituting occult ideas, interaction without contact. He agreed. Problem was never resolved. Science just abandoned the quest. They basically said, well, we'll just construct intelligible theories. Newton's theories were intelligible. The world he described wasn't intelligible, but they said, well, forget it.
Starting point is 02:54:47 Science lowered its goals. Now we just try to construct intelligible theories. Whatever the theories tell us, that's the material world. So there's nothing to discuss. The material world keeps changing as we understand more. So the question whether something transcends the material world is just a way of saying we don't know how to incorporate it within our intelligible theories. Maybe we never will. Maybe someday we will.
Starting point is 02:55:19 Moving now from Noam Chomsky to Josje Bak and John Verveke, who were both in a theolocution together, they talk about Searle's Chinese room experiment. And so we have updated in a sense because we no longer just see money as an agreement between people. But this agreement between people has been extended into machinery that we have built in the world that works independently of the beliefs that people have. And this leads us to the question of what is software and software is not a thing right software is something else in which sense does software exist and the best answer that i have so far discovered is that software is a physical law the physical law says if you for instance arrange matter in this particular way the following thing will happen and this is true for software right so no matter where you are in
Starting point is 02:56:11 the universe in which universe you are if you produce the following functional arrangement of things the following thing will happen this is what software is about so the programmer in some sense is discovering by constructing certain very peculiar circumstances, a very specific physical law. I just want to interrupt. That's really cool. That's really cool. I really like that idea. I'm sorry for interrupting.
Starting point is 02:56:37 I want to make sure I'm following you. You're proposing that software has the same kind of ontological status as physical law. Exactly. Wow. That's really, really cool. That's cool. Keep going, please. I just wanted to say as its physical law. Exactly. Wow, that's really, really cool. That's cool. Keep going, please. I just wanted to say that's very cool.
Starting point is 02:56:49 Yeah, I thought when I stumbled on this insight that it was a good insight that basically started to make sense, right? Because it's a parent pattern in the interaction of many parts. Yeah, yeah, yeah. That's very good. I like that. That's very good. That's very good. I like that. That's very good. That's very good.
Starting point is 02:57:05 So this also means, because I think that mental states are best understood as software states, that the ontological status of our mental states is different from the ontological states of the one that we attribute to physical things. so this has to do with the notion of identity of a mental state that is similar to the identity of a physical law which means it's not this point wise identity yeah it's a functional identity yeah yeah and now let's go back to so the original chinese room argument is very simplistic in a sense like it's a children's story myth that Searle himself doesn't believe in. And it's an argument that is by Searle, when he repeats it today, made in bad faith. Searle is affiliated with this. His actual contributions to philosophy have been largely an extension of Austin's speech act theory that are boring and wouldn't give praise to fame.
Starting point is 02:58:01 But the Chinese womb is somebody that everybody understands because it interfaces with certain intuitions, and it's an intuition pump. And if you disassemble these intuitions and try to make them more distinct and more clear, then many of them fall apart. And Searle is aware, because he's not stupid, he's a very smart individual,
Starting point is 02:58:21 of many of the ways in which they fall apart. But he is still repeating the original Chinese womb argument because it's his brand. So it's not because he believes in it. And if you actually read his work, he is aware of many of the counter arguments, and he knows that he needs to go into a few levels of complications to have an interesting argument, to have an interesting case that he's making. So the superficial level of the chinese womb argument is maybe not that interesting a slight extension that is more interesting is
Starting point is 02:58:51 the chinese brain argument that's also aware of and the chinese brain argument suggests that instead of having this library with books in it in which you execute the algorithm, we use a different implementation of that whole thing. And instead, what we do is we take a mechanization of the neuron itself. So if we accept that what the brain is doing is facilitated by the interaction of neurons, the neuron has to follow certain rules in order to make that happen. And maybe we can spell out these rules in our thought experiment, and then we assign a Chinese person to a neuron. And maybe we need a few more.
Starting point is 02:59:31 Maybe we need 86 billion Chinese people instead of 1.4, but it's a thought experiment, so not a problem at all. And now, instead of neurons, we have Chinese which follow these rules. Or we could use machines instead of the chinese that are following these rules and so i think that this matching between a neuron and a chinese person is not completely absurd on the face of it of course it would be much larger and we blow it up and now seoul would say of course the chinese brain doesn't have the necessary and sufficient conditions to produce a conscious mind and then access to meaning so it doesn't have the necessary and sufficient conditions to produce a conscious mind and then access to meaning so it doesn't change anything whether the chinese room or the chinese brain is
Starting point is 03:00:11 performing these operations the chinese brain is still not able to speak chinese because the individual identities of the chinese people and their knowledge does not interfere in any way with their emulation of the functionality of individual neurons. So now if we have established this case where Searle would say the Chinese brain is not conscious, but your brain is conscious, let's see where is the boundary between those two systems. So let's take your brain, blow it up until a person and a neuron have roughly the same size, so change the time so it doesn't matter how much the Chinese need to talk to each other to make the neural functionality happening and send messages back
Starting point is 03:00:50 and forth. So let's keep this an identity. And now we basically take your neurons and Searle accepts that neurons are facilitating mental activity. He is not a mysterianist or something. He doesn't know how the brain does it, but he agrees that the brain is doing it. He is a know how the brain does it, but he agrees that the brain is doing it.
Starting point is 03:01:05 He is a physicalist in a sense. So now let's replace step-by-step the neurons by some other machinery, for instance, Chinese people or machines that have neuron-like functionality. And Searle at some point says this loses the ability to be conscious. So the consciousness is drowning out of the system
Starting point is 03:01:23 by this replacement process. And what this means is that Searle has a strong anti-functionalist position. He basically says that the function of the individual parts is not producing the essential behavior. There's somehow an essence. He's an essentialist. And I don't know how to get essentialism to work because nobody has ever seen an essence, right? We can talk about an essence, but it's epiphenomenal. And the problem with epiphenomenalism is the following. Epiphenomenalism is, if you go back to our dualism
Starting point is 03:01:56 from the beginning of our conversation today, it's the idea that there is maybe a read axis from the mind, where the mind is reading physics, but no write axis from the mind into physics. So it's not violating the causal closure of physics. But there is a problem with epiphenomenalism. And that is the phenomenal experience that you don't think you can explain in the physical mechanism is not driving anything of what you are saying, including your utterances of beliefs. including your utterances of beliefs.
Starting point is 03:02:25 So when an epiphenomenalist says, but I feel, and this cannot be explained by physics, this is caused by physics, right? Because the epiphenomenalist has to move their mouth or move their fingers to express the statement. And all these movements are caused by an entirely mechanical process. The true feeling which happens next to the physical, mechanical part of their mind, the philosophical zombie and so on, is not driving any behavior.
Starting point is 03:02:49 So basically there would be this locked-in epiphenolism that would helplessly watching their body make statements in favor or against epiphenolism, but there would be no causal relationship between the epiphenolism. So no epiphenolist is an epiphenolist because they have phenomenal experience that cannot be explained by physics. That is the issue here. And so if Searle goes down that path, he goes down to a very inconvenient place that I don't know how to resolve. Okay, John, I know that you have to get going. So how about I read the last question? If it would take too long for you to reply, then send me an email and then I'll read it when I'm re-editing this podcast. Sure. Okay. So the last question comes from Xantheus. He says, or she says, these models of consciousness seem to focus on explaining the production of intelligence or a simulation, but it isn't necessarily clear to me why a simulation should be able to perceive slash experience itself. If we think of metaconsciousness
Starting point is 03:03:45 as a combination of intelligence and consciousness, the model seems to focus mainly on the rise of intelligence in metaconsciousness. How do you explain the ability to perceive slash experience the simulation? John, you start. So it's just a very short, easy question. Wrap it up for today with this simple question. I mean, it's important to ask that question, but it's important to not ask that question the wrong way. You can always ask what it is like,
Starting point is 03:04:21 and this is like Moore's thing about the good. I can ask that for any proposal. You can even ask that, well, what it's like is to have qualia. Well, what's it like to have qualia? Do I have qualia of my quality? And this is the difficulty. You have to come to a place where you're saying that's what it is like to be what it is like. And we didn't get into it too much, but like I said at the very beginning, that primary sense of relevance, I think, is a big piece of what it's likeness. It's why things stand out and are salient and are backgrounded. It's why things are aspectualized for us, to use one of Searle's notions. for us, to use one of Searle's notions. And many people are converging on the idea that the function of consciousness is this kind of higher-order relevance realization, and that's why it
Starting point is 03:05:13 overlaps with working memory and attentional machinery. So, what it's like, if that's right, if what it's like is this ability to do salience landscaping, to have this dynamic texture of how things are relevant to you, if that's a big part of what it's like. And I think it is, by the way, because all of those, in the pure consciousness event, all of those other things that are so beloved, all the adjectival qualias and all the other things, they go away and consciousness doesn't. So those things can't be necessary conditions for consciousness. If that's a significant part of what it's like, then being intelligent is also that. Being intelligent is this capacity to zero in on relevant information,
Starting point is 03:06:02 exclude relevant information. That's why you get high correlations between measures of general intelligence and measures of working memory. But of course, there's deep anatomical relations between the machinery of working memory and attention and fluid intelligence and consciousness. So, I think the question is now being to a place where I want to say, no, no, no. And by the way, notice how you run on that. You generally attribute consciousness where you attribute high orders of intelligence. You track them together. of intelligence. You track them together. Like Yasha, I don't, well, I go further. I don't even eat mammals because of that conclusion about mammals. Well, there you go. And so for me, there has to be a level at which you accept an identity statement. Because like I said,
Starting point is 03:07:04 you can always play the game no matter what. If I say X is what it is like, then you can just do, ah, but what is it like to write X? You have to come to a place where you accept an identity claim. And I'm proposing to you that if you look into the guts of intelligence, at least general intelligence, fluid intelligence, and then you look into the guts of consciousness, and where do we need consciousness? We seem to need consciousness for situations that are novel, that are complex, that are ill-defined, and situations that don't have those demands, we can make automatic, unconscious. That's a good point made by Bourne-Seth.
Starting point is 03:07:46 unconscious. That's a good point made by Born-Seth. I don't think the questions about intelligence and consciousness are ultimately separable questions. And I think there's good reasons for that. I've just given you some. And therefore, I think at some level, and maybe Yoshua will like this, when a system is sufficiently intelligent, Maybe Yoshua will like this. When a system is sufficiently intelligent, it's going to be conscious. That's what I would argue for the reasons I've just given. And asking me, but what is it like to be intelligent? Or what is it like to be?
Starting point is 03:08:23 Notice you don't ask the question of what is it like to be conscious in the sense of what's behind it, right? You have to come to a level at which you say, no, this is what it is liking is. This is the function it's performing. This is the kind of process it is. If not, if you don't put some bound on where that identity is possible, then you just get an infinite regress of this question. Because no matter what I posit for you, you can step back and say, but what is it like to X? And then I'll say, well, what's it like to X is to Y? And you'll say, but what is it like to Y? This is like the four-year-old asking you why all the time, right? You have to come to a place. And what I can't give you is I can't give you a phenomenological experience of that, because you're trying to ask how phenomenological experience is itself possible. What I can give you are these plausible arguments about overlapping functionality, etc. That's how I would answer that question.
Starting point is 03:09:20 Okay, let me try. So there is an issue, for instance, with free will. Free will is an intermediate representation, I think. Free will is what decision-making under uncertainty looks like from your own perspective between discovering the first-person perspective and deconstructing it again. And once you have deconstructed your first-person perspective, you basically realize that there is a particular procedure that you are following when you are making your decisions and when you observe yourself following that procedure you will not have an experience of free will it's just we
Starting point is 03:09:54 rarely get to the point in our short lives where we fully deconstruct this and i just give this example to argue for the possibility and i'm'm not sure, there's no certainty there, that consciousness might be an intermediate representation. It's basically a simplification of the state of affairs in which we are in before we automate all the necessary behaviors that an intelligent system might want to exhibit when it's being confronted with the world in which we are in. when it's being confronted with the world in which we are in. The reason why we experience things is not because physical systems would be capable of doing so. It's quite the opposite. Neurons cannot experience what it would be like to be a person that is confronted with a complex world and that changes its attitudes in response to what's happening to it in this complex world.
Starting point is 03:10:43 But for the organization of the neurons that is controlling the behavior of the organism, it would be very useful to have this knowledge of what it would be like to be a person that is changing its attitudes in response to what's happening to it. So what the neurons are doing is they implement a model of what that would be like, a simulation of what that would be like, a simulation of what that would be like. In the same way as the neurons create a simulation of a Euclidean universe with objects that bump into each other and have causal interaction, the neurons create the model of agents that care about future states and how they play out and make decisions about this. And one
Starting point is 03:11:22 of these agents is going to be a model of the organism itself and the behavior that motivates the organism. And the reason why we experience things is not because we are in the brain. It's because we are in that model. We are in that simulation. We are in that dream that is woven by the brain to explain its own behavior. We experience things for the same reason that a character in a novel experiences things. It's because it's written in the story. And the story that we experience, of course, is not a linear
Starting point is 03:11:49 narrative made up of words. It's a more complicated world. It's a causal structure that contains the necessary properties to simulate physics and personality and agency and so on. And we find ourselves in that dream. So our experience of the world is virtual. It's a result of the capacity of neurons to dream and to create dreams. There was a question that came from Anil Seth, Professor Anil Seth, and there's a podcast of Anil Seth on this channel if you'd like to check it out on consciousness. Professor Anil Seth asks, Yosha, do you believe consciousness to be substrate independent, i.e. a silicon computer in principle could be conscious, and if so, why? Yosha responded to me via email and said, there is no known reason why the process playing out in the brain cannot be functionally replicated
Starting point is 03:12:41 on a silicon-based computer. I think that consciousness is not so much a side effect of how a biological brain makes sense of the world, but of the need to create a coherent representation out of dynamic perceptual features. Because of this, I think it's likely that intelligent, autonomous sense-making agents with similar complexity as ours may be considered conscious in ways that are comparable to ours, even if they run on a silicone substrate. There's an important caveat. Our computers provide some functionality which is hard to achieve in the brain. They're almost fully deterministic. They're synchronized in ways that
Starting point is 03:13:15 allow each part to rely on the functionality of all others at any given time, and they can make information available very quickly throughout the entire processing architecture. Crucial parts of the phenomenology of human consciousness, especially reflexive consciousness, may be the result of self-organizing processes that our brains cannot do without, but that may not be necessary in our digital computers. Thank you both for coming. The audience thanks you. Bach and Vervaeke's exploration of consciousness, simulation, and the interplay of neurons provides a compelling perspective on the nature of our existence. These insights are particularly relevant to our next guest, Stephen Wolfram, who's been
Starting point is 03:13:53 on the podcast at least twice, by the way, and links to all will be in the description, as usual. Stephen's work on computational irreducibility and the complex nature of space and time sheds light on the nature of free will. Why don't you give a three-minute synopsis, I know that's difficult, as to your theory for those who are unacquainted? Well, gosh. So I've been working on this for like 40 years, so it's a little bit hard to compress, but I suppose as gradually as one learns more about what one's talking about, it becomes easier to explain.
Starting point is 03:14:26 All right, let's talk about physics and kind of what's the universe made of, so to speak. And I think one of the things that has been, the first question is, we think about things like space and time, and the traditional view of something like space has been been it's this thing that you put things in. It isn't a thing itself, it's just sort of a background, and you get to specify a position here or there in space. That's been kind of the idea of space since Euclid and so on. So one of the basic points in kind of the models that we've developed is there's something, space is made of something, just like a fluid like water. You might think of it as just a continuous fluid where you can like put something anywhere in the fluid. Actually, you can't. It's made of discrete molecules bouncing around. And so we think it is with space that sort of at the lowest level,
Starting point is 03:15:31 at very small scales, space is just made of a whole collection of discrete elements. We can think of them as like geometrical points, but they're not points that have a known position in anything. They're just discrete elements. And the only thing we know about those elements is how they're connected to other elements. So it's kind of like the points that exist in the universe are sort of friends with other points, and we build up this whole network of connections between points. of connections between points. And so our universe as it is today might have maybe 10 to the 400 of these sort of atoms of space that make it up. So sort of the first point is everything in the universe is just space. So what all of the particles and electrons and quarks and all
Starting point is 03:16:22 those kinds of things, they're all just features of this details of the connections between these atoms of space. So sort of the first thing is, what's the universe made of? It's made of space. What's space made of? Space is made of this giant network of nodes, giant network of discrete elements. And we don't even from that know why space is three-dimensional, that the thing could be connected in any way it wants. What happens is that on a large scale, something which is discreetly connected like that can behave as if it is, for example, a three-dimensional manifold on a large scale. And for example, one thing that can happen and we think does happen in the early universe is that the universe goes from being essentially an infinite dimensional network where everything's sort of connected to everything else to this sort of more or less
Starting point is 03:17:09 three-dimensional, so far as we know right now, perfectly three-dimensional, although we suspect there are some dimension fluctuations that exist today. So, okay, so that's sort of what space is. Then what's time? Well, the point is is the idea is that there are these definite rules that will say if there's a piece of network that looks like this transform it into one that looks like that and that's continually happening throughout this this network that represents uh the structure of space and the content of the universe and so what's what um uh what we're what we're seeing then is a sort of progression of all of these little updates of this network that represents space. And that progress of all
Starting point is 03:17:52 those updates corresponds to the progress of time. And one of the things that's unusual about that is for the last hundred years or so in physics, people have kind of assumed space and time as sort of the same kind of thing. One knows about relativity, one knows that sort of there's processes that kind of trade off space with time, yet in our theory, space is this extension of this, as it turns out to be a hypergraph, this network basically, and time is the progressive sort of inexorable computation of the next configuration of the network based on rewriting the previous configuration. So one of the things that is sort of an early thing to realize in our models is this question
Starting point is 03:18:31 of, so how does something like relativity arise? Well, the answer is, if you are an entity embedded within this network, it turns out that the only thing you are ever sensitive to is kind of the work. It turns out that the only thing you are ever sensitive to is kind of the network of causal relationships between updating events. And it turns out, there's a few more steps here, but it turns out that with certain conditions on the way those updatings work, it is the case that basically special relativity comes out of that. We can talk in more detail about how that works. So the next thing that happens is this space just made up from this network, it's sort of the continuum limit of this network in the sense it's like you've got these atoms of space underneath,
Starting point is 03:19:17 and then on a large scale space is like kind of a fluid made up of lots of atoms that behaves in the continuous way that we're used to perceiving it. And then it turns out that you can get space in any of the dimensions, you can get space with different kinds of curvature. One of the big results is that you can get the way the curvature arises in space is exactly the way that Einstein's equations for gravity say curvature should arise. Roughly, energy, momentum, mass, these are all associated with levels of activity in the network. And roughly, levels of activity in the network produce curvature in the network, in just the way that Einstein's equations say that energy momentum in physical space-time should produce curvature in space.
Starting point is 03:20:09 So that's a pretty important thing. I actually knew that back in the 1990s, that these models could reproduce general relativity, reproduce Einstein's equations. So then the next big sort of pillar of 20th century physics is quantum mechanics. There are really probably two or maybe three pillars of 20th century physics. General relativity, the theory of gravity, quantum mechanics, and also to some extent statistical mechanics, which also sort of comes out from the formalism of these models, but maybe it's not the first thing to explain here. So how does quantum mechanics arise? Well, first thing is, what is quantum mechanics? What is the important feature of quantum mechanics? Basically, in classical physics before the 1920s or so, people thought that in
Starting point is 03:20:59 physics, there were definite equations of motion. Things behave in definite ways. You throw a ball, it goes in a definite trajectory. What quantum mechanics says is, no, that isn't what happens. Instead, there are many possible histories that develop. And the universe has many possible histories, and all we get to be sensitive to is some kind of aggregated probability of what happens, not knowing specifically what the history of the universe is. Well, it turns out in our models, that's something that inevitably works that way. And what happens is we're talking about sort of the rewriting of this big network. And the point is that there isn't just one possible rewrite that happens at any given time. There are many possible rewrites. And each of those different possible rewrites represents essentially taking the universe in a different path of history. But the
Starting point is 03:21:50 critical fact is that just as there might be two possible rewrites that could happen and they produce a branching of two paths of history, so also it will turn out when there are other rewritings that can happen later that actually these branches can merge. So you end up with something which is this whole graph of possible histories, we call it a multi-way graph. And in this multi-way graph, there is both branching and merging of histories. And that process of branching and merging of histories, that ends up being the story of quantum mechanics, basically. And one of the things that's sort of a thing to think about is when we look at, they have this whole multi-way graph of all these branching histories of the universe. And we say, let's imagine that we are observing that. We are, it's a little bit hard to imagine because what's happening is we, our brains,
Starting point is 03:22:43 our minds are themselves embedded in this multi-way graph. So just as the universe is breaking into all these different parts of history, so too are our brains breaking into all these different parts of history. So in a sense, what's happening is it's a branching brain observing a branching universe. You have to kind of think about how does our mind make sense of that universe? And what you realize is that you're kind of defining what we might call reference frames, kind of quantum reference frames. They're analogous to the reference frames that we think about in relativity, where reference frames, typical inertial frames, are things like you are at rest, you're traveling at a certain velocity, et cetera, et cetera,
Starting point is 03:23:28 et cetera. There's kind of a quantum analog of those. And that's the way that we perceive this multi-way graph of possible histories. And so when we say, let's pick a particular quantum reference frame, corresponds to more or less a particular time. And let's then ask, what is the sort of slice of this multi-way graph defined by this quantum reference frame? What we have is all these different possible histories, and they're all kind of laid out in some sense. Histories can be close to each other if they had common ancestors recently. Histories can be further away from each other if they didn't have a common ancestor for a long time and so on. All these histories are kind of laid out in some kind of space. We call that branchial space, the space of branches, the space of quantum branches.
Starting point is 03:24:13 And that branchial space is not like physical space. It's not like something where you have ordinary motion from one place to another. But in branchial space, it's a layout of possible states of the universe, effectively. So one of the things that I find really neat is that you can talk about motion in physical space. You can talk about, for example, even ever since Newton, we've kind of had this principle that if things aren't acted on by a force, they will keep going in a state of uniform motion. So it's kind of like things go in straight lines if you leave them by themselves. And kind of Einstein's big idea in general relativity was to think that, yes, things do go in kind of straight lines in the sense that they're shortest paths, geodesic paths, but space can be curved. And then what might be to the thing, kind of its straight-line
Starting point is 03:25:08 path to the outside is a curved path, and because that curvature is associated with energy momentum, that is what leads to the effect of gravity, so to speak. So in physical space, that's how things work. Turns out in branchial space, they work in essentially exactly the same way, except now in terms of the equations of gravity, we have the equations of quantum mechanics and quantum field theory. And essentially what's happening is that there are sort of paths in branchial space that are being followed. And we are seeing deflections of those paths actually associated also with energy momentum and the way those deflections work exactly gives one the path integral of quantum mechanics. So the thing that's really pretty neat is, I mean, one of many very neat things, but one thing that I just found really was a very wow
Starting point is 03:26:00 moment about a year and a bit ago now. Gosh, I can't believe it's so long. Congratulations, by the way. It's, yeah, well, time inexorably moves forward, right? But I think that sort of a wow moment was realizing that the Einstein equations of physical space are basically the same thing as the Feynman-Path integral in branchial space. So in a sense, general relativity and quantum mechanics are the same theory, just played out in these different kinds of space. And that has a lot of implications because it kind of shows one how there are correspondences between general relativity and quantum mechanics, and there's sort of, I don't
Starting point is 03:26:46 know, intersectional cases when one's dealing with black holes and so on. But so that's at least one level of the story of our models of physics. And, you know, there's a lot of detail and a lot of things that are now, it's now clear, yes, we really can reproduce exactly what happens in, you know, black hole mergers. We can reproduce what happens in quantum computing. We can reproduce all these other kinds of things. And we're starting to have kind of ideas about, you know, a lot of, I know a lot of experimental physicists who keep on saying to me, when are you going to give us actual experiments to do? And we're getting closer, you know, it's no point in telling them there's a lot of actual physics and astrophysics and so on to be done to work out exactly what to look for. But I mean, another direction here that is, well, there's several directions. I mean, one is kind of understanding.
Starting point is 03:27:42 I've had sort of in the last few months, kind of a deeper understanding of what kind of observers of the universe we actually are and how consciousness relates to what kinds of things we do and don't observe about the universe and what consequences that has for the kinds of laws the kinds of physical laws that we believe are going on in the universe. That's one direction. Another direction is trying to understand if we can say, yes, we have the simple rule that's updating this hypergraph and so on. And then you say, why is it that simple rule, not another one? What I've realized recently, what we realized a while ago, but it's become a lot crisper now, is this idea that actually there is the, in some sense, the universe can be running all possible rules, and we are seeing some kind of
Starting point is 03:28:34 reference frame, not in physical space or in branchial space, but in this thing we call ruleal space, the space of all possible rules, we are essentially picking a particular description language, a particular reference frame with which to understand the universe. And so the sort of paradox of why or this sort of conundrum of why does the universe follow one particular rule and not others, turns out the answer is it follows all possible rules. And we are just at some place in ruleal space observing it in a particular way. And that has the big surprise to me recently last month or so has been realizing that I actually think we can get a serious answer to a question like, why does the universe exist? And as a matter of fact, the thing that comes out of that is the realization that as soon as we say
Starting point is 03:29:23 the universe exists, and as soon as we give that argument, we are forced into a position that mathematics, in some sense, fundamentally exists too, which is something people like Plato have said, but something very different from the way that people have assumed the foundations of mathematics work. So you asked me for a three minute, I'm sure that wasn't three minutes, but summary. I mean, I have not talked about a lot of the intuitional underpinnings that are necessary for this theory of physics. Concepts like the principle of computational equivalence, computational irreducibility, and so on. I mean, what's basically happened in the building of this this theory is uh it's sort of the result of well it's i guess it's now 40 years of my uh activities um that in the first of the first layer is probably
Starting point is 03:30:14 you know i i used to do sort of traditional quantum field theory general relativity particle physics kinds of things so i i know that stuff fairly well although although it's kind of it's a rip van winkle type situation for me because that was 40 years ago and i'm now kind of uh it's it hasn't changed as much as you might have thought a field might change like if i look at biology over that period of time you know there were all these things in biology where it's like i learned stuff about cells 40 years ago 45 years ago ago, whatever. And it was like, that's an organelle of unknown function. And now there's a whole, you know, vast journals devoted to exactly what, you know, the Golgi complex does or something, something like this. So, so in a sense, that field has advanced a lot more than physics over that
Starting point is 03:30:58 period of time. But I think the, you know, sort of that layer, then there's the layer that I've spent years building practical technology for actually computing things. And both the level of understanding of how formal systems work that has come with the process of designing Wolfram language and Mathematica and so on, that has been really critical to what we built. And then the very practicalities of, you know, so we actually have an environment in And then the very practicalities of, you know, so we actually have an environment in which to do experiments. We can, you know, do graph theory easily and things like this. And then the whole new kind of science development of what simple programs do, understanding principles of that and so on. And I realized there's in the end a fairly tall tower that we've ended up relying on to kind of construct
Starting point is 03:31:47 this theory. And to me, it's this funny feeling because I'm really excited that we managed to get this done and it's gone a lot better than I expected it would go. But it almost didn't happen. I mean, it very, very nearly didn't happen. And the question that I might ask myself is, if it hadn't happened, when would it have happened otherwise? And the answer is, I don't know, 50 years, 100 years, I don't know.
Starting point is 03:32:15 It wasn't a thing where, you know, it wasn't like all the stars were lined up for everybody, so to speak. It was a particular series of things that are kind of the story of my life. And then people like Jonathan, who had their own things that they bring into this, you know, it's kind of an unexpected and unusual alignment. Plus, it turned out, we managed to get a lot further than we ever expected to get. So it's, anyway, that's a little bit of an outline of kind of where we are, I suppose. I mean, there's a lot more to say about the details of what's happening with the models and how we compute things from them and so on. But you asked for a basic introduction. That's my
Starting point is 03:33:00 attempt at a basic introduction. Now we move from Stephen Wolfram to Jonathan Blow. Jonathan has a take on the second time around problem and the Everidian interpretation of quantum mechanics, which posits that all possible histories do occur. They just aren't in our universe. Of course, predicting new things is always like the gold standard of like, how you know you're into something. But there's always the question of, is this just one of a large number of models that are isomorphic to each other? And because he likes cellular automata,
Starting point is 03:33:35 he found the cellular automata one, which would be a big deal anyway, right? But it doesn't really answer the question of like, are cellular automata fundamental or something? Although he probably has some angles in which he would argue that it does, having to do with with computational irreducibility and stuff like that. Okay, speaking of computational irreducibility, Wolfram thinks free will is tied to that. I'm curious. But the way that he defines free will,
Starting point is 03:34:15 I don't think is the way that most people would think of the word free will being defined. More that you can't predict your own actions, so it has to do with predictivity. Either way, do you believe that people have free will? Or do you believe that you have free will? Let's say that. You're asking the hard questions today. What I think is that the idea of free will, the question, do I have free will, the question, do I have free will, it takes as assumptions for the question to make sense. It requires a picture of reality that is too simple. And that by the time you develop a picture of reality that is sophisticated enough, that question kind of doesn't make sense anymore.
Starting point is 03:35:08 I'm not claiming that I'm at that level of understanding of reality, but I am saying, yeah. Can you explain to me the simple background assumptions that go into a question like that? And then how with more articulated assumptions or more advanced assumptions that dissol into a question like that, and then how with more articulated assumptions or more advanced assumptions that dissolves the question. I mean, I feel like this is ground that has been covered at least okay. I mean, I don't know. I'm
Starting point is 03:35:35 often very unsatisfied by discussions about these topics. But the problem is to do a convincing explanation on this requires going into a lot of subtopics that if people who haven't heard them before hear them first from me, I'm not going to give a particularly convincing version of them because it's not my shtick. I don't go around talking about free will. But there are, for example, things you can Google that'll give you good starting points. So for example, there's a thing called the second time around problem, right? Which is that it seems to be indistinguishable whether like this is the first time things were happening and we chose what could happen, or whether it's a fully deterministic playback of that. And so that's a simpler question that
Starting point is 03:36:33 you could start with. Like, how would I even know the difference between those two things? Because in the first time around... So our reasons for believing we have free will, the primary one is that we feel like it. We feel like we have free will. Maybe the first time we felt like we had free will because we had free will. But the second time, it's a reproduction of the first time, so we have to feel the same way, or it's not a good reproduction. But it's a deterministic reproduction, so it's not like we could have changed our mind, right? And so thinking about a simpler sub-problem like that is much easier than thinking about the problem of the actual whole universe that we're in right now. But by thinking about smaller problems like that, you can broaden your
Starting point is 03:37:27 horizons in a certain way. You can broaden the scope of things that you think about, right? So in that second time around problem kind of case, it's unclear whether you had free will or not because which one of those, are you in the original or the replay, changes the answer. But then it's exactly the same experience in both of them. So is that one experience or two experiences? Do you even know? Do they map to the same thing, or are they two separate? For people who know a bit of quantum mechanics, you know that the Everettians have become quite well represented currently in terms of the way that people interpret what's happening. The way to interpret things from an Everettian standpoint is that just all things that can happen do happen, right? And so what does it mean to have free will in that case? It doesn't mean what people naively think determinism means,
Starting point is 03:38:37 which is that only one thing happens and must happen. It's like, no, actually a bunch of things happen, but then does it maybe like, maybe the question of free will is orthogonal to that in some sense anyway, because it changes the weighting on how much of things happen or not. Like it's unclear, but so I think that rather than trying to answer this question directly of, do we have free will? I think the best that people can do right now is like go to the gym and work out, right? And like pump some iron, get buff, and come back later and answer these questions. Do you mean that metaphorically, go to the gym? Yeah, but you know, it might help non-metaphorically as well.
Starting point is 03:39:24 Yeah, but it might help non-metaphorically as well. So what do you mean metaphorically by that? Do you mean go study philosophy, go live your life, go try and develop a skill? Well, I mean, if you're interested in the question of free will, then thinking about these sub-problems, I think can very quickly get you at least to a point where you realize why the question as originally posed is too simple to really make sense. But that's then been replaced by all these possibilities of how things could be. Are those possibilities fictional? Are they real? That's sort of the material you would be contending with in that domain. But then there's maybe equivalent questions that are something like, do I have free will, but that are
Starting point is 03:40:17 more answerable and maybe more specific, right? Jonathan Blow's probing of free will in the context of deterministic and stochastic processes in quantum mechanics has been shared, and now we move again to Noam Chomsky, the renowned linguist and philosopher who's been on the Theories of Everything podcast approximately nine times, actually. Chomsky actually challenges the deterministic perspective and argues for the existence of free will and discusses the impact of our belief in free will on our societal structures and even personal identity.
Starting point is 03:40:52 This question comes from the chat, so it's not on your list. This is Laura Sosa who says, forgive a novice here. What are your thoughts on retrocausality, quantum entanglement, time perception, and precognition studies? Well, it's an interesting question about the only argument I've ever seen from the sciences on why there can't be free will is retrocausality, the argument that if in our life experience X precedes systematically Y and we take X to cause Y and if it seems that we're carrying out an act, say, my lifting my finger, just because I decided to do it. At some level, maybe not the level of experience, there's an argument that time is reversible, which means that the lifting my finger could have preceded the decision to do it,
Starting point is 03:42:08 which seems to conflict with the idea that I decided to do it. I personally don't think that's a very persuasive argument, but it is at least one argument, I think probably the only argument, that comes from the sciences against the universal belief which we all have, whether we deny it or not, that we can make decisions about our next action. Number 15. Beers Adajou from Chechnya asks, Realistically, would a human society where the lack of free will is the commonly accepted truth be any different than the current human society where having free will is the commonly accepted truth. There are sub communities in our society where lack of free will is the commonly accepted truth.
Starting point is 03:43:07 Large part of the scientific community believes that. Large part of the philosophical world believes that, thinks everything is determined, that freedom of will is just an illusion. Actually, none of the people who profess this really believe it, in my opinion. In fact, they're trying to convince you of it. They're giving reasons. If we're all just thermostats acting in a totally determined fashion, giving reasons is totally pointless activity. You don't give reasons to an automaton. It behaves the way it's going to behave.
Starting point is 03:43:53 But my feeling is, intuitively, all of us believe that we can make a decision as to whether, say, to lift my little finger or not. I can decide, do I want to do that or don't I? I think everybody intuitively believes that there are a large number of highly sophisticated, brilliant people who think they can convince themselves that they can't make that decision. who think they can convince themselves that they can't make that decision. They're among us. Society functions exactly the same for them as it does for us. So the answer to the question I think is already given to us. There are great many among us, some of the most sophisticated people who think about these topics, who think there is no free will. Everything is determined.
Starting point is 03:44:47 Do they behave any differently from anyone else? Not detectably. They behave like we all do. Joe Surow asks, if mental events are causally predetermined to physical events, in parentheses, which themselves are attached to volition. What does the data say about the relationship between conscious volitions and unconscious wiring in relation to the problem of freedom of the will? What does linguistics say about this?
Starting point is 03:45:23 Linguistics doesn't say anything. But there is a question about decision and choice, and consciousness of decision and choice. And there is experimental work, the famous Libet experiments about 30 or so years ago, which showed that there's a gap of a couple hundred milliseconds between a decision and conscious awareness of the decision. They don't talk about complicated things like what we're doing, like making up sentences, not that, just simple things like, say, lifting your finger. So suppose i decide i'm going to lift my finger well it turns out that the musk the musculature and the instructions to it are
Starting point is 03:46:14 already being implemented before i'm consciously aware of having made the decision. Well, what does that tell you about free will? Nothing. It just puts it back a little further. It says the conscious decision is maybe already determined, but what about the decision? No, actually, the sciences tell us essentially nothing about this. What the sciences tell us is we can't explain it. What we can account for is things that keep to determinacy and stochastic processes, randomness, basically. So if it's within the framework of stochastic processes and deterministic processes,
Starting point is 03:47:07 we can develop theories. Well, is freedom of choice within that framework? That's the question. But the sciences don't answer it. They can just say, we can't handle it. it. I mean, there are some kind of exotic arguments in quantum theory and in relativistic physics. There's an argument that actually time is reversible. It has no particular direction, could be going in another direction. So, for example, if an observer makes a measurement in the split experiments, it's determining the waveform's collapse and it's becoming a particle. Well, it could go in the other direction in principle. so the collapse of the waveform could have preceded the decision to make a measurement so does that tell you there's no free will i don't really think so but it's a kind of an argument and it's about the only kind of arguments there are the rest is just basically, we can't handle it. So if you think that the sciences are complete, then there's no free will,
Starting point is 03:48:29 because it doesn't fall within the framework of determinacy and randomness. But the question is, are they complete? That's the question of free will. When you look at the study of voluntary motion, at the study of voluntary motion, turns out there is extensive neurophysiological study of voluntary motion. There's a recent article by two of the leading scientists who work on it, Emilio Bitsi and Robert Ajayme, in which there is a state-of-the-art article, What Do We Understand About Elementary Voluntary Motion? It appeared in Daedalus, the Journal of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences.
Starting point is 03:49:17 They point out, they go through what we've learned about it, and they kind of end up by saying, as they put it, fancifully, that we're beginning to understand the puppet and the strings, but we have nothing to say about the puppeteer. We can't say anything about decisions. And it's a fact. You just can't. So you can believe what you like. We actually all believe that we are free to make decisions. I'm sure you believe it. I believe it. We could all be deluded,
Starting point is 03:49:53 but there's no evidence that we are. Chomsky's belief in free will, despite the seemingly deterministic nature of the universe, or at least the ineluctable quality of the physical laws, has implications for our personal identity and agency. This leads us to Thomas Campbell, who provides a contrasting perspective. Campbell argues that individual consciousness is merely an avatar in a larger quote-unquote simulation, suggesting that perceived free will is some illusion. Thomas Campbell also explicates his views on death and the continuation of consciousness. One question is, when you mentioned that we're this consciousness and we're logged onto the game and that ordinarily we identify with the avatar of the game and that that's a mistake and what
Starting point is 03:50:34 we should identify with because it's true, at least in your theory, sorry to put quotation marks around it, at least it's true in your theory that this is who we truly are, the consciousness above that's logged on. Then you said that when we die, well, some parts of our memory, I'm not sure if some parts or all, but regardless, let's not harp on that. Some parts of the memory, at least, continue on as well as with your choices, whether you've done good or bad or evil or lower entropy or raised entropy, however you would like to word it. What I'm wondering is, is that supposed to bring someone comfort? I hear some people say this plenty. I hear some of the people who are on the more Vedic ends of the tradition that say, well, your consciousness does continue on past your death.
Starting point is 03:51:13 Now on the Western end, they'll say your consciousness continues, but you go to a place. Whereas on the more Eastern end, it's your consciousness continues, but it's not you. It's not your ego. It's something else. but then what i'm wondering is the eastern side doesn't seem to provide at least someone like me it doesn't provide me with any comfort because that me that me the player that's logged on bears so little resemblance to who i identify with now that it would be just like a materialist trying to give me hope by saying well all your molecules are going to continue on anyway. So technically you do live on. You're breathing the sun from, you're breathing the Big Bang.
Starting point is 03:51:50 So you are like, I'm like, okay, well, I see that, but it bears so little resemblance to what I conceptualize as my identity. I don't give you a lot of comfort either. That free will awareness unit we talked about before, that's the part that's really logged on. That's the piece of the IEOC, individual unit of consciousness that's logged on to the avatar. That's a one-off.
Starting point is 03:52:11 When after that life is done, that partition is taken down, it's integrated back into the individual unit of consciousness, and now a new partition gets put down with just what it's been learned, and that goes off and logs on. So all of those petitions, all those free will awareness units are just one-offs. When they're done, they're done. But what you accumulate is all of your experience, all your growth, all of your learning, all of your quality, all of your entropy reduction. That is accumulated. And you have a database.
Starting point is 03:52:47 It's not memory, but you have a database of all the things that you've done, all the thoughts, all the feelings. What about your friends? What about the relationships? Are those also cataloged? Because I could imagine that even if somehow I am to continue on with my attributes, but if I don't have the people that I love around me and I'm not able to recognize them at least, then that also is somewhat meaningless,
Starting point is 03:53:10 at least to me, at least right now. Yeah. That's because where you are now and the way you see life and so on and an ego that wants to continue on as you and wants to continue on those relationships because, you know, your children, your wife, you know, there's people who are dear to you and you want that to continue on those relationships because you know your children your wife you know there's people who are dear to you and you want that to continue on it doesn't that's that is here when you die your awareness of your life here begins to fade like a dream and you don't continue that it's it's not practical yes that's kind of soft and warm and it's comforting, but it doesn't work that way because it isn't functional.
Starting point is 03:53:52 It doesn't work. So let's say here you are and you've been through 10,000 lifetimes and you've had 10,000 sets of parents. You've had 30,000 children, whatever. And you're going to remember all those and want to do something with all those relationships? Or is it just the last 20 or the last 500? You know, it doesn't work that way. That just is going to wide you up into a big ball of stuff that is emotionally grabbing at you, and it's not going to be functional at all. Each time you take what you've learned, you graduate from third grade, and you take what you've learned, and you go into fourth grade. And it's a new experience, new teacher, new subjects expect you to know new
Starting point is 03:54:36 things. So you it's that comfort of you being you. Well, it's only a problem if you see you as Kurt. If that's you in your mind as Kurt, then you have this problem. But if you in your mind is your individuated unit of consciousness, the collector of all the experience, if that's you, then you lives on forever. And it's not a problem. You realize that these relationships you have now, as meaningful as they are, they happen because those are the people you ran into. If you're born on the opposite side of the planet, you'd run into different people.
Starting point is 03:55:14 And next lifetime, you're going to run into different people too. And most of your learning comes from these relationships. They're very important. They're very significant. But, you know, so is your third grade teacher significant, but you don't make her come along under the fourth grade with you. It's done. Now that we've heard from Thomas Campbell, we talk about free will, as well as responsibility and what is causally relevant with John Vervaeke. Do you personally believe in free will?
Starting point is 03:55:46 No. I mean, if I understand what you're saying, I'm a compatibilist. I'm somebody who thinks that whenever we've been talking about free will, we didn't mean what is typically meant by free will. I take it that this is what you mean by free will. And if you don't, of course, correct me. But at least when I have discussions with people about this, they mean that there's something in them that is uncaused, an uncausal center, a non-causal center of causation.
Starting point is 03:56:16 So that there's, in some way, a first mover. There's something in them that is totally uncaused, but then can make things cause, can initiate a causal chain. And I find that both incredible in the sense of something I can't believe in, and I also find it – I don't understand why people want this, why they want to possess this capacity. First of all, I think my life gets better as my thinking is more and more determined by what's true. My actions are more and more determined by what's good. My experience is more and more determined by what's beautiful. I don't think freedom in that sense is an intrinsic good. by what's beautiful. I don't think freedom in that sense is an intrinsic good. I mean,
Starting point is 03:57:11 part of the project, for me, freedom is an instrumental good about, right, about getting more and more. I would love it if my everything about, if my thoughts were completely determined by the truth, my actions were completely determined by what was good. If I completely lost my freedom in truth, goodness, and beauty, great. Why not? Freedom for its own sake, I don't understand that as a value. I understand it as an important political value, an instrumental value, but as a metaphysical thing, I don't find it inherently valuable. So when I talk about what it is to say that an action is free from a compatibilist framework, for that, what that means for me is the most causally relevant explanation of my behavior was my current, you know, my current state of consciousness and cognition, right? That's what I think it means
Starting point is 03:57:59 when you say I am responsible for X. I know, did we ever mean that I was the sole cause of it? No, of course, I can't think of an instance where we think we are the only causal thing for something happening, even when I'm speaking. It's dependent on all the causal properties of my lips and my vocal cords, right? I can't think of anything where we're talking about sole causation.
Starting point is 03:58:24 For me, we've always been talking about causal relevance second i don't want a part of me that's what i was trying to do earlier that is uncaused like that is not causally connect that would mean my actions were completely arbitrary they were in no way relative to or relevant to the events in the environment. Because if they are in any way relevant to the environment, that's going to play out in there being some important causal relationship between what's happening in the environment and my state of mind. Not that I believe in free will, but just to play devil's advocate, what you're saying is that there are constraints. So there are physical constraints, the laws of physics, how your tongue is situated in your mouth, the words that you speak.
Starting point is 03:59:06 I'm also saying there's normative constraints, truth, beauty, and goodness. Yeah, but go ahead. Okay, so there are constraints. Why can't there be free will with constraints? So you're saying, well, if you go back, then you would have to be a first mover. Yeah. But you could be a first mover within constraints, not just a first mover with no constraints. Like, what the hell are you going to do?
Starting point is 03:59:24 Wait, wait. Are you saying the first mover is responsive to the restraint think of it like chess or think of it like go right the game go so there's tremendous constraints first of all we're playing a board game right second of all you can only move this piece and so on so but there's so many options within go that if you ran a supercomputer from now from the beginning of the universe to the heat death of the universe it it still wouldn't exhaust it. Yeah, it's combinatorial explosive, right? But there, so... So what I'm saying is that there could be constraints, heavy constraints on free will.
Starting point is 03:59:51 So commensurate with your... Wait, wait, but there's a difference here. Your example of go, your example of go is that, right, there's lots of possibilities, right? And that's not the same thing as saying you have free will right then you choose from those possibilities you choose from those possibilities based on okay so that now we're getting into a causal model but free will has to be outside of causality that's exactly what i can't get an analogy well well well we know when we come down to subatomic particles that causality
Starting point is 04:00:21 is just you throw it out the window so causality being not a part of this universe is true it breaks down to right sense but and there are other systems like you said a structural structural functional i forget what it was called organizational sure so that that also breaks a causal model but wait wait we were we have two different things we're talking about and and I think that's important. There's causation and there's constraints. And those aren't identical. Causation is about events that change actuality. Constraints are about conditions that shape possibility. And I'm invoking both of those and saying freedom of the will is, I mean, if... So you think it's logically impossible? Or do you just not want to believe it? Or you feel like you have a propositionally consistent worldview that proves that there is no free will?
Starting point is 04:01:18 I think that it doesn't make any sense. I don't know if that's the same thing as saying it's logically possible. Logically impossible, sorry, logically impossible. Logically impossible would mean it clearly makes sense, and then we can find it's inherently contradictory. I don't know if it makes any sense. The idea of free will. The idea of free will.
Starting point is 04:01:37 That doesn't make any sense to me. And also the valuation of free will doesn't make any sense to me. I'm not trying to be obtuse. I don't know why people want it. I mean, most of the major philosophical conundrums like the mind-body problem and things like that, they deeply interest me. The free will determinism thing leaves me cold, right? I don't know why people want it, and I don't know what they mean when they say they have it. Because even to say that you're choosing, unless your choice is completely arbitrary and not in any way affected by the options you're considering, constrained by them,
Starting point is 04:02:16 then it's not a free choice in the free will sense. If your actions are in any way responsible to, responsible to the environment, you don't have that kind of free will we're talking about. Now, a compatibilist said, we were never talking about that when we said I acted freely. What we mean when I say I acted freely is precisely what we're talking about. I'm acting responsibly and responsibly to the environment. And the most causally relevant, not the sole cause, not the original cause, but the most causally relevant explanation of that responsiveness and responsibility is my current cognitive state. That's all we ever meant, I think.
Starting point is 04:02:58 Mathematical philosopher James Robert Brown will now speak about his Platonistic perspective on free will. What are your views on free will, by the way? Do you believe in it? Yes. Or do you believe against it? Oh, interesting. Okay, now are you like Daniel Dennett where you say, well, I have a compatibilist view?
Starting point is 04:03:17 No, I have, here I feel completely at sea. Speculate away. I operate, I live my life as. Speculate away. I operate. I live my life as if I have free will. I eat too much, and I blame myself. I blame my willpower. And while it would be very nice to blame something else, I can't. I just blame myself.
Starting point is 04:03:42 I get angry at others. I get angry. I mean, some people, I think, can't help what they believe. Others, I think, have gone out of their way to make themselves stupid, and I blame them for that. So I'm happy to blame people for not doing what I think they ought to do. And I do think they have free will. I don't know how to live in a world where we really don't have free will. But I may be just highly, that's not an argument for free will. That's just an argument for we have to live as if there is free will. I don't know how really to live otherwise. Now, I've seen some people who are very sophisticated, you know, talk about
Starting point is 04:04:26 this subject and maybe they'll be able to persuade me in the long run that we don't have free will or there's a very good chance we don't have any free will but we should we can act like this and this and this and this and so on. So I really, I have childish immature underdeveloped views about free will the standard view that's opposed to free will is well what caused you to make so-and-so decision and then it's your neurology okay well what caused that and you keep going until you get to a cause that's not you so you just get along that chain of causes right right where does that chain of reductionism, because we just talked about physics being extremely powerful and more and more accurate, and there doesn't seem to be room for free will. So where does free will comport with our view of physics in the way that it's formalized currently? No, it's terrible.
Starting point is 04:05:20 But it doesn't have to be quite as crude as you just put it. But it doesn't have to be quite as crude as you just put it. Here's another issue in which I do not have strong views, but it's sort of in the background. And this is the difference between, this is the issue of reductionism and emergence. So if you have a complete reductionist view and your world is deterministic, it's very hard to make room for a free will. it's very hard to make room for a free will but if you have an emergentist view that is uh yeah physics is at the bottom but in a certain level of complexity there could emerge biological laws like strong emergence yeah and out of that could emerge uh psychological laws and so on and and free will would be you know something that is emerging at some higher level it's not going to it's not going to it's not going to emerge out of elementary particle physics
Starting point is 04:06:11 i mean sometimes people try to do that because they take quantum indeterminacy to to be uh you know that's just stupid it's just really bad arguments um but But if we did have some kind of emergence, you might have free will. Right. But again, I can't make up my mind on that issue either. Okay. Yeah. Where I was going to go is there's no evidence for strong emergence, but there's plenty of evidence for reductionism. Like there's no link in the chain that's broken in the reductionist account as far as we could tell.
Starting point is 04:06:47 So then to believe that we have free will, and I'm not suggesting that I don't believe, I'm just throwing something out. So to believe that we have free will seems to be counter to evidence. So how do you jive with saying that I'm a person who goes wherever the evidence leads me, but simultaneously saying that I'm someone who believes in free will. And when I say go wherever the evidence believes, sorry, that I'm a person who goes wherever the evidence leads, I mean evidence in terms of scientific evidence, because obviously you can be a spiritualist and say, well, I have the intuitions. And maybe you might appeal to intuitions, but I'm curious. So what do you say to that? What do you say to that? Well, I do.
Starting point is 04:07:29 I do count myself as somebody who's led by the evidence. Scientific evidence. On the other hand, I don't agree with you about there's no gaps in going from us to elementary particles. to elementary particles. I mean, try to imagine accounting for Donald Trump's election in terms of writing down the Schrodinger equation
Starting point is 04:07:53 for the population of the world and solving it and getting out that Donald Trump is president. What I meant was that so far there's no link that's been shown to be false. That doesn't mean that there is. No, no, no. I completely agree with you. So there's no link that's been shown to be false. That doesn't mean that there is. No, no, no. I completely agree with you.
Starting point is 04:08:08 So there's no evidence for it. And there's plenty of evidence. It wouldn't be very reliable. That would be like religious people who argue for the God of the gaps. God fills in the gaps in our scientific knowledge. Yeah, it's a foolish way of doing it. Let's talk about Platonism. Do you mind defining for the audience what Platonism is?
Starting point is 04:08:24 Sure. Modern Platonism. Do you mind defining for the audience what Platonism is? Sure. Modern Platonism, as opposed to being a strict follower of Plato. Modern Platonism is simply the view that there are abstract entities. Numbers being the most obvious example of this. That they exist in some way, shape, or form? Yep, they're real.
Starting point is 04:08:49 They exist. And there are facts about them, like two plus two equals four. There are infinitely many prime numbers and so on. And these objects and these facts are completely independent from intelligent creatures. So even if no intelligent life existed anywhere in the universe, it would still be true that there are infinitely many prime numbers. If you believe that, you're a Platonist.
Starting point is 04:09:21 In fact, there's a little litmus test for audience members who've never thought about it before. Ask yourself, do you think mathematicians discover new truths of mathematics, or do they somehow invent or create them? Shakespeare created Hamlet. If Shakespeare or no intelligent being had ever existed, Hamlet would not exist. On the other hand, the spherical shape of the earth would still be a fact, even if no intelligent being had ever existed. I say math is more like the shape of the earth and less like Hamlet. That's what it is to be a mathematical realist or a platonist now you definitely should read that paper that you sent me which i thought that you knew nicholas jessen and you were completely familiar with his work anyway just for the audience i read it at the time i remember
Starting point is 04:10:15 i do remember sending it to you but i just completely forgot it okay i'm just gonna give a bit of background favor yes send it if you yeah yeah i'll send you a letter from him because it's it's wonderful okay has nicholas justin is a physicist who is answering question that i was curious about which is why i asked jim here i said hey is there any other logical foundation of physics other than classical logic because i'm wondering i'm always curious like what's holding us back from theories of everything and i'm trying to tackle it from as many angles as i as i can and so i thought maybe this is one and you said well there is this person named nicholas jessen who thinks that intuitionist logic is a way to go and when i read that now i'm getting um now it's coming back yes
Starting point is 04:10:58 yes okay and so what he was saying he has a few different reasons for believing that first of all real numbers aren't real and the reason for this is to say is because there's only a finite amount of information that can be in any finite volume so let's say it's a real number if it's an arbitrary real number then it's going to collapse into a black hole if for whatever reason the particle somehow carries that information with it okay well you can leave and leave that aside he says that all of deterministic physics like classical physics yeah actually is completely compatible with an indeterministic view forget about quantum mechanics and the reason is that all we can do is test it to a certain precision
Starting point is 04:11:37 let's say 30 decimal places that's being a bit generous but let's say 30 decimals place for classical physics then you can easily construct indeterminate indeterminate functions so here's one i can't say it because i can't say it i would just have to write the function out but let's say you have the real line, so 0 to 1, and then you somehow stretch the real line, and then you cut the real line in half. I'll have to tell you what the function is, but either way, that real line, you can describe any number as 0.b1, b2, like the digits of, okay, great. What that function effectively does is remove the first digit. So instead of it being 0.B1, B2, B3, it's 0.B2, B3, B4. Okay. Now, given that, given that, let's say finite, let's say non-real numbers are completely compatible with classical physics because we don't know where the end of the error bar effectively gives a real number or if it's just cut off you understand you understand what
Starting point is 04:12:55 i'm saying sorry if i'm not explaining correctly okay given that then we can have these simple systems that actually are not just chaotic because we don't have sufficient information but because within it it genuinely is indeterminate for example that function like if you just choose an arbitrary okay so you get the idea okay so then he was saying that indeterminacy is not incompatible with classical physics even though we like to think of classical physics as being a determinant theory you can't it. So then he goes on to say, calling physics deterministic or indeterministic is not a scientific question because both models predict the exact same reality that we see classically. Forget about quantum mechanics. And then he goes on to make a connection between that and free will.
Starting point is 04:13:43 He's a proponent of free will, much like yourself. And he says it can be saved. The libertarian version of free will, not the compatibilist, that is that I choose from the possible world. Oh, anyway, that's extremely intriguing to me. Like, I thank you so much for that. And I'm going to talk to Nicholas about that. Moving from James Robert Brown, we now go to Anil Seth,
Starting point is 04:14:07 a neuroscientist who talks about not only free will but what strange loops are and how that has any relevance to what we think of as a self that is your personal identity do you agree with his conception of free will the compatibilist approach i i'm a compatibilist, yeah. I mean, I think free will is another kind of perceptual experience. And I think this whole debate about determinism is totally irrelevant to understanding free will. I'm trying to get Dendon on the podcast. He said that he's busy writing a book, so he can't come on.
Starting point is 04:14:42 I'm also trying to get Douglas Hofstetter. What are your views on Douglas Hoflas hofstetter's model i just don't know him well i don't know him personally and i've read only really the amazing um it's one of the best books everybody should read that it's phenomenal um it's just playful what i take from that is just this incredible um it's just playful what i take from that is just this incredible playfulness creativity i have it right here i keep only it's um three books beside me four books it's one of them yeah now that's one that's one of them you know that's that's i don't know if you know this show the desert island discs we have it on the radio here in the uk and the idea it's been going on for like decades and the idea is you what are the eight songs that you
Starting point is 04:15:28 would take with you if you're getting banished to a desert island never to return you can only take eight tracks um and then you're also allowed so most people in england spend half their lives figuring out what these eight tracks are going to be just in case they get invited onto the show at some point you want to be ready um but you're also allowed to take a book cool and so for you that would be definitely well i wouldn't say it would be the one but it would certainly be up there i haven't made a decision about the book yet but it's so i love the way it just creates it playfully explores our intuitions about what cognition is what mind is what what explanations in biology physics consistent i think it's i think it's synopsis he's a genius full of insights
Starting point is 04:16:12 yeah have you read his analogy book i haven't i haven't it's a great one but it's far too long sometimes it goes through lists and lists what i find it to be somewhat tedious okay so what are your views on his views of consciousness where do you agree disagree well it's a tricky question because to be honest i i it's been i i would be hard pressed to articulate what they are i mean to me it got he talks about strange loops and things like that um To me, he talks about strange loops and things like that. Yeah, I don't have a particular strong view because to me, I've always just associated him with these things about language recursion, all these playful insights. So I don't think he's, as far as I know, he's not come into my radar
Starting point is 04:17:06 specifically about consciousness more about what self consists in and what we think of as a self and that's where do you agree disagree well it's a tricky question because to be honest i i it's been i i would be hard pressed to articulate what they are. I mean, to me, it got, he talks about strange loops and things like that. I don't have a particular strong view because to me, I've always just associated him with these things about language, recursion, all these playful insights. So I don't think he's, as far as I know, he's not coming to my radar specifically about consciousness, more about what self-consistence and what we think of as a self. All right, if you enjoyed this
Starting point is 04:17:58 peregrination into free will, which I know you did, then let me know what other subject you'd like covered for another Onto Prism compilation episode. Some examples may be hearing about quantum gravity, or what is the best evidence for UFOs, or a deep dive into entropy or complexity. Let me know in the comments. These compilations take a considerable amount of time and effort, going through the back catalog of Toe, doing some research, making sure it's cohesive, improving the audio quality, creating thumbnails, and other finishing touches. We've been having trouble monetizing this channel with sponsors, and so your support goes a long way. So if you'd like to contribute to the continuation of Theories of Everything, then you can donate through PayPal, Patreon, or through cryptocurrency.
Starting point is 04:18:40 Links are in the description. Your contribution goes a long way in ensuring the quality and the longevity of Toe. Either way, thank you. You may enjoy exploring the mysteries of the universe and free will in this solo episode with me reading mathematician Raymond Smullyan's blithesome debate on free will between man and God. Many of those who watch this consider it to be one of the best videos on Toe, and the link to that one with Raymond Smullyan is in the description. Thank you. The podcast is now concluded. Thank you for watching. If you haven't subscribed or clicked that like button, now would be a great time to do so, as each subscribe and like helps YouTube push this content to more people. You should also know that there's a remarkably active Discord and subreddit for Theories of Everything, where people explicate Toes, disagree respectfully about theories, and build as a community our own toes.
Starting point is 04:19:31 Links to both are in the description. Also, I recently found out that external links count plenty toward the algorithm, which means that when you share on Twitter, on Facebook, on Reddit, etc., it shows YouTube that people are talking about this outside of YouTube, which in turn greatly aids the distribution on YouTube as well. Last but not least, you should know that this podcast is on iTunes, it's on Spotify, it's on every one of the audio platforms. Just type in theories of everything and you'll find it. Often I gain from re-watching lectures and podcasts, and I read that in the comments. Hey, Toe listeners also gain from replaying. So how about instead re-listening on those platforms?
Starting point is 04:20:10 iTunes, Spotify, Google Podcasts, whichever podcast catcher you use. If you'd like to support more conversations like this, then do consider visiting patreon.com slash kurtjaimungal and donating with whatever you like. Again, it's support from the sponsors and you that allow me to work on Toe full-time. Thank you.

There aren't comments yet for this episode. Click on any sentence in the transcript to leave a comment.